Difference between revisions of "Being and Existence" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
 
(245 intermediate revisions by 8 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Edboard}}{{Ready}}{{Contracted}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{Copyedited}}
+
{{Ebcompleted}}{{Ready}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{Copyedited}}{{2Copyedited}}
{{For|the philosophical movement|Existentialism}}
+
[[File:Being Parmenides.png|thumb|350px|The Being according to [[Parmenides]]is like the mass of a [[sphere]].]]
{{For|the existence of god|Existence of God}}
+
'''Being and existence''' in [[philosophy]] are related and somewhat overlapping with respect to their meanings. Classical Greek had no independent word of "existence." The word "existence," as distinguished from the word "[[being]]," arose in the [[Middle Ages]]. Influenced by [[Islamic philosophy]] that recognized the contingency of the created world as compared with [[God]] the Creator, [[Christianity|Christian]] philosophers such as [[Thomas Aquinas]] used the Latin word ''"existere"'' ("to exist" or "to appear") as distinct from ''"esse"'' ("to be") or ''"essentia"'' ("essence"). The Medieval distinction between essence and existence in the world, however, was critiqued by later [[theology|theologians]] and philosophers for various reasons.
  
The question of existence or being (Greek, "eon" or "ousia"; Latin, "esse"; German "Sein"; French, "étre"), in [[philosophy]], has been one of the central topics of [[metaphysics]]; the study of "being" or "existence" is called [[ontology]].
+
Modern [[existentialism]] maintained the distinction between essence and existence, but reversed the Medieval priority of essence over existence. The [[Germany|German]] philosopher [[Martin Heidegger]], who critiqued the Thomistic theory of the causal relationship of difference between God and the world as well as its related theory of the distinction between essence and existence, dealt with the question of being in a very new way that involved the [[human being]] as ''Dasein'' ("being-there"), which to him is synonymous with existence.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
The majority of [[analytic philosophy|analytic philosophers]] have rejected the distinction of being and existence. But, for philosophers and theologians who consider the distinction between being and existence an important one, there are two significant issues: [[teleology]] and individuation or embodiment. For what purpose do individual things exist? How do things become individual embodiments of their corresponding universals? A notable approach to the first issue was proposed by the [[America]]n theologian Schubert Ogden, who combined existentialism with [[process thought|process theism]] to explain the unity of reality centering on God's aim. The [[Spain|Spanish]] [[Jesuit]] [[Francisco Suárez]] approached the second issue by proposing that the [[form and matter]] of a [[substance]] in union determine the individuality of that embodied substance.
  
Being or existence has been often inquired into in contrast to its reciprocal concept, and the meaning of being differs according to its paired concept, for example, being and becoming, being and appearance or phenomena, being and thought, being or "is" and ought, being and essence. Philosophers, particularly [[metaphysics|metaphysicians]], implicitly or explicitly, often hold a certain sense of being as primary and his or her understanding of being constitutes the framework or the background of his or her thought, although the philosopher does not necessarily discuss it thematically.
+
==Relationship of being and existence==
 +
===Greek philosophy===
 +
History shows a rather complex relationship between [[being]] and existence. The classical Greek equivalent of the English verb "be" was ''"einai,"'' but there seems to have been no classical Greek equivalent of the English verb "exist." It was only in the [[Middle Ages]] that the Latin word ''"exsistere"'' was made from a combination of ''"ex"'' ("out of") and ''"sistere"'' ("to cause to stand") to mean "to exist," "to appear," or "to emerge." The reason why classical Greek did not have any distinct concept of "exist" was that in [[Greek philosophy]] from [[Parmenides]] to [[Aristotle]] the primary project was a veridical one of articulating truthfulness in reality through copula sentences of the form "X is Y."<ref name=Kahn>Charles H. Kahn, "Why Existence Does Not Emerge as a Distinct Concept in Greek Philosophy?" in ''Philosophies of Existence: Ancient and Medieval'', ed. Parviz Morewedge (New York: Fordham University Press, 1982).</ref> The theory of predication was central, and the theory of existence peripheral. So, even when Greek philosophers wanted to express the concept of existence, they did so only in the predicative form; "X exists" was expressed as "X is something." Thus, the word ''"einai"'' ("be") had to be used more widely than its predicative meaning. It was in the context of this wider use of ''"einai"'' ("be") that Aristotle referred to the concept of existence as ''"hoti esti"'' ("that it is") as distinguished from ''"ti esti"'' ("what it is"), which would mean [[essence]].
  
[[Thomas Aquinas]], for example, conceived [[God]] as the primary being, from which all other beings in the world receive its existence. [[Materialism|Materialists]], on the contrary, conceive a material or sensible entity as the primary model of being and identify physical sensibility with the primary sense of being. [[Aristotle]], [[Husserl]], and [[Heidegger]], are some of philosophers who developed their philosophy with the full awareness that there are diverse senses of being. Although we use the same word "is" or "exists," the meaning of being or existence is different according to its kind such as: sensible material being; values and norms; principles; mathematical objects; time; space; God, and others.
+
Of course, in late Greek philosophy the old Greek verb ''"hyparkein"'' (originally, "to make a beginning") started to be used non-technically to mean "to exist"; but, it and its early Latin rendering ''"exsistere"'' still continued somewhat ambiguously to retain the predicative meaning as well, and furthermore the use of the noun ''exsistentia'' ("existence") was not popular yet.
  
[[Logic|logicians]] use the symbol ∃ to denote the [[existential quantifier]], which asserts the existence of some object with certain properties.
+
===Medieval Christian philosophy===
 +
Eventually, however, the concept of "''existentia''" ("existence") was established amongst Medieval [[Christianity|Christian]] philosophers such as [[Thomas Aquinas|St. Thomas Aquinas]] as a technical term contrasted with "''essentia''" ("essence"), an abstract form of the presumed present participle of ''"esse"'' ("to be"). While essence apparently meant "what a thing is," existence meant "that a thing exists." According to Charles H. Khan, this development of the modern sense of existence occurred under the influence of [[Islamic philosophy]], which distinguished existence ''(wujud)'' from essence ''(mahiat)'' in its radical revision of Greek ontology in light of a [[Bible|biblical]] [[metaphysics]] of [[creation (theology)|creation]] within [[Islam]] which distinguished the created world (contingency) from [[God]] (necessity).<ref name=Kahn/> Aquinas adopted this, maintaining that the essence and existence of each and every contingent, finite creature are distinct, while essence and existence are identical within God, who is therefore preeminent over the world. According to him, God causes each and every finite creature to "exist" with its "essence."
  
==Distinction of Being and Existence==
+
Aquinas, however, indicated this causal relationship of difference between God and the world in terms of the ''"analogia entis"'' ("analogy of being"), referring to God and each finite creature as ''"ipsum esse subsistens"'' (Self-subsistent Being) and ''"ens"'' (being), respectively. This means that in spite of the development of ''"existentia"'' ("existence") as a new word with a distinctive meaning in the Middle Ages, still the term ''"esse"'' ("to be") was used more generally to cover the meaning of existence as well. Modern [[existentialism]]'s emphasis upon the priority of existence over essence was still alien.
Philosophers often distinguish between being and existence, saying that being is broader than existence, i.e., that the former applies not only to objects that actually exist but to objects that are merely abstract (e.g., qualities, relations, and numbers) and fictitious (e.g., centaurs, dragons, and Pegasus), whereas the latter covers only non-abstract, non-fictitious objects that actually exist.<ref>Arthur Norman Prior, "Existence," in ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', ed. Paul Edwards (New York: Macmillan, 1967).</ref>
 
  
Another way of distinguishing between being and existence is rather historical. The classical Greek equivalent of the English verb "be" is "''einai''," but classical Greek seems to lack any word equivalent to "exist." It was only in the Middle Ages that the Latin word "''exsistere''" was made from a combination of "''ex''" ("out of") and "''sistere''" ("to cause to stand") to mean "to exist," "to appear," or "to emerge." The reason why classical Greek does not have any distinct concept of "exist" is that what was primary in Greek philosophy from [[Parmenides]] to [[Aristotle]] was the veridical project of articulating truthfulness in reality through copula sentences of the form "X is Y."<ref>Charles H. Kahn, "Why Existence Does Not Emerge as a Distinct Concept in Greek Philosophy?" in ''Philosophies of Existence: Ancient and Medieval'', ed. Parviz Morewedge (New York: Fordham University Press, 1982).</ref> The theory of predication was central, and the theory of existence peripheral. So, when Greek pholosophers wanted to express the concept of existence, they did so only in the predicative form; "X exists" was expressed as "X is something." Thus, the word "''einai''" ("be") had to be used more widely than its predicative meaning.
+
===Later criticisms of the Thomistic position===
 +
The Thomistic distinction between essence and existence in the created world was criticized by later theologians and philosophers for various reasons. Critics include [[Duns Scotus]], [[Francisco Suárez]], [[René Descartes]], [[Gottfried Leibniz]], [[David Hume]], and [[Immanuel Kant]]. But, especially existentialim's criticism was notable because of its attempt to reverse the order of priority between essence and existence. [[Søren Kierkegaard]] denied the importance of the objective essence of a thing in favor of the subjective appropriation of it. He, thus, held that there is no truth in objective knowledge of essence itself, and that the truth about reality is revealed only in the human subject's "passion of the infinite" as a believer. In talking about the essence and existence of a human being, [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], for whom existentialism meant an [[atheism|atheistic]] [[humanism]], went so far as to say that because there is no Creator, existence precedes essence.  
  
According to Charles H. Kahn, although the old Greek verb "''hyparkein''" (originally, "to make a beginning") started to be non-technically used to mean "to exist" in late Greek philosophy, nevertheless it and its early Latin rendereing "''exsistere''" still continued to retain both the existential and predicative meanings at once somewhat ambiguously until the end of the thirteenth century, when [[Duns Scotus]] finally established "''existentia''" ("existence") as a technical term contrasted with "''esse''" ("to be") or its participle "''essentia''" ("essence"). "Thus the modern terminology of 'existence' seems to derive from Scotus."<ref>Charles H. Kahn, "On the Terminology for Copula and Existence," in ''Islamic Philosophy and the Classical Tradition: Essays Presented by His Friends and Pupils to Richard Waltzer on His Seventieth Birthday'', ed. S. M. Stern, Albert Hourani, and Vivian Brown (London: Bruno Cassier, 1972).</ref> It is usually understood that the development of this position of Scotus occurred under the general influence of [[Islamic philosophy]] which radically revised Greek ontology in light of a biblical metaphysics of creation, and more particularly under the influence of [[Avicenna]] who distinguished existence (''wujud'') from essence (''mahiat'').
+
The most notable critic, however, was the German philosopher [[Martin Heidegger]]. According to Heidegger, Aquinas' theory of the causal relationship of difference between God and the world through the analogy of being, and his related theory of the distinction between essence and existence in the world, are far from answering the fundamental question of the meaning of being, which was not answered in the long philosophical tradition in the West anyway because being itself was taken for granted as self-evident or undefinable. Therefore, in order to let the human being constantly pursue the question of "being" ''(Sein)'', Heidegger referred to that human being as ''"[[Dasein]]"'' (literally "being-there"), who, as a "being-in-the-world" ''(In-der-Welt-sein)'' thrown out to the temporal and phenomenological world of "beings" ''(Seiendes)'', is faced with [[angst]] and mortality there, but who nevertheless is expected to experience [[authenticity (philosophy)|authenticity]] by standing in the openness of "being" in the midst of "beings." Here, the sense of "being" to be experienced is pre-conceptual and non-propositional in the everyday situation of human life; and the causal relationship of difference between God as "Self-subsistent Being" ''(ipsum esse subsistens)'' and the created world of "beings" ''(ens)'' in Aquinas' metaphysics is superseded by the distinction between "being" ''(Sein)'' and "beings" ''(Seiendes)'' in Heidegger's phenomenological ontology in pursuit of the meaning of "being." For Heidegger, the word "existence" ''(Existenz)'' is simply synonymous with ''Dasein'': "The 'essence' of ''Dasein'' lies in its existence."<ref>Martin Heidegger, ''Being and Time,'' tr. John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), 67.</ref>
  
==Diversity of the Sense of Being==
+
==Being and existence in analytic philosophy==
As was noted above, being is broader than existence, with the result that there are diverse senses of being according to its kinds. Material beings exist in the space-time world and they exist in the sense of physical reality which is detectable by physical senses or physical instruments. They deserve to be considered to "exist." By contrast, [[ideas]] and values such as [[love]], [[justice]], [[good and evil|good]] do not exist in the same sense of being physically sensible material. Although they are be beings, do they really exist? In which sense do they exist is subject to philosophical discussion. For Platonist those ideas and values really exist in an incorporeal realm of the world. The sense of the existence of time, space, numbers, principles is also subject to philosophical discussion.
+
===Actualism===
 +
Many [[analytic philosophy|analytic philosophers]] in the twentieth century such as [[Gottlob Frege]], [[Bertrand Russell]], and [[W.V. Quine]], believed that [[being]] and existence are identical, that is, that what there is, is precisely what exists. It is basically so-called "actualism," and it maintains that there is no kind of being beyond actual existence. The identity of being and existence also means that every predicative proposition can be translated into an existential one without changing meaning. For example, adding "exists" to "a wise man" to give the complete sentence "A wise man exists" has the same effect as joining "some man" to "wise" using the copula to say "Some man is wise." So, the "exists" of the existential proposition takes the place of the copula. This view is the basis of the dominant position in modern Anglo-American analytic philosophy: that existence is asserted by the existential quantifier.  
  
Some philosophers elaborated on the existence of human beings. [[Existentialism|Existentialists]], for example, explored complex elements involved in human existence, which include [[freedom]], [[authenticity]]/inauthenticity, [[anxiety]], [[death]], [[good and evil]], [[justice]], [[afterlife]], and [[faith]].
+
===Possibilism===
 +
Of course, there is a school called "possibilism," which distinguishes between being and existence, that is, between what there is and what exists, saying that the latter comprises a relatively small portion of the former. According to this, although there are things that actually exist, there are also things that do not exist: they are what there merely are, not having ''existence'' or ''actuality,'' which only things that actually exist have. Such things are non-existent possible things like Santa Claus, unicorns, aliens, and people that were never born. They could have actually existed, but as it happens, they simply do not. To this possibilist realm of the non-existent, some of the followers of [[Alexius Meinong]] such as Terence Parsons would add impossible objects like square circles and wooden iron, which have contradictory properties.  
  
[[Heidegger]], who took the question of being ([[ontology]]) as the primary subject of philosophy in the twentieth century, analyzed how a human being interprets the meaning of his existence. A human being does not exist in the same sense as a material thing exits, and instead man constantly interprets the meaning of his existence. In his ''Being and Time,'' Heidegger developed the analysis of [[Dasein]] (human being in a rough sense) as [[hermeneutics|hermeneutic]] [[phenomenology]].
+
===Adjusted possibilism===
 +
But, scholars such as [[Quine]], for whom there is no distinction between being and existence, have critiqued possibilism, by saying that we cannot embrace non-actual possible objects since there is no real criterion of identity for them: "No entity without identity."<ref>W.V. Quine, ''Ontological Relativity and Other Essays'' (New York: Columbia University Press, 1969), 23.</ref> This critique from Quine has given rise to an adjusted version of possibilism, which now agrees that being and existence are identical, saying that everything there is exists, but which nevertheless insists that not everything that exists is ''actual'', that is, that there ''exist'' things that fail to be actual. This, however, looks like a word game, simply renaming being as "existence" and existence as "actuality." Thus, a more advanced version of possibilism, which takes Quine's objection more seriously, has been developed by [[David Kellogg Lewis]].  
  
Existentialists such as [[Kierkegaard]], [[Nietzsche]], [[Karl Jaspers]], [[Sartre]] all highlighted unique modes of human existence and tried to explicate them.
+
===Modal realism===
 +
While agreeing with the adjusted version just mentioned above that being and existence are identical, but that actuality is to be distinguished from existence, [[David Kellogg Lewis|Lewis]] has a new understanding of actuality, treating it in terms of ''relation''. Thus, according to Lewis, when people say that there are things that exist but are not actual, it means that there are things that are spatiotemporally unrelated to the world, although they exist in a full-fledged sense in other worlds. The word "actual," then, is an ''indexical,'' whose reference on any given occasion of utterance is determined by the context or world in which the utterance occurs. So, when one utter, "New York City is actual" (or more naturally, "New York City actually exists"), its truthfulness is made not because actuality is some intrinsic property of New York City but rather because New York City occupies the same world as the speaker. Lewis' version of possibilism is sometimes called "modal realism," and it is quite Quinean.
  
== Multiple senses of being in a paired set of concepts ==
+
==Different realms of reality==
Being is often paired with another concept and the sense of being differs according to what it is paired with. The pairs listed below are some of those often discussed in the history of philosophy. These pairs, however, often overlap and they are not mutually exclusive.
+
The issue on whether or not there are different worlds or realms of reality is not new. Ancient [[Greek philosophy]] observed that there are concrete, material [[being]]s in the spatiotemporal world in the sense of physical reality which is detectable by physical senses or physical instruments, while there are also [[idea]]s and [[values]] such as [[love]], [[justice]], and [[good and evil|good]] which however are not of the same physically sensible material. For [[Plato]], those ideas and values in an incorporeal realm of the world are real beings because they are self-existent and immutable, while material beings in the corporeal world are merely their ephemeral "shadows" far from real beings. For [[Aristotle]], by contrast, only individual things called [[substance]]s in the spatiotemporal world are fully existent beings, and other beings, called [[category|categories]], such as relation, quantity, time and place, and Plato's ideas and values, have a derivative kind of being, dependent on those individual things. In the Middle Ages, based upon a biblical metaphysics of creation, the notion of existence was established to show the emergence of the created world, distinguishable from being in general and also from essence.
 +
 +
The Plato-Aristotle tension above was echoed in the Medieval controversy between realism and [[nominalism]]. The approach of realists was to argue that the sentence "[[Socrates]] is wise," which contains a noun reference only for "Socrates," can be rewritten as "Socrates has wisdom," which apparently proves the existence of a reference for "wisdom" as well. This argument, however, was inverted by nominalists such as [[William of Ockham]] in arguing that "Socrates has wisdom" can be rewritten as "Socrates is wise," which contains a reference only for "Socrates." The nominalist method has basically been inherited in analytic philosophy, which holds that there is hardly any kind of being beyond actual existence.
  
===Being and becoming===
+
==Teleology, being, and existence==
 +
The [[teleology|teleological]] nature of reality was discussed by [[Plato]] and [[Aristotle]]. Plato identified the Idea of the Good as the ultimate cause or measure in the whole of reality, saying that things that are gain their usefulness or value from it. Aristotle maintained that each [[substance]] has its final cause, which guides it throughout various changes it goes through to reach what it is. According to him, the final cause is virtually identical with the formal and efficient causes because all these can be attributed to the form of each substance, which is immanent in it, although [[God]] as "pure form" is the ultimate final, formal, and efficient cause, towards which all things tend. This teleological approach does not believe that the final causes of different substances are incompatible with one other, but rather that they are for one another. Hence, "extrinsic finality," through which the harmonious relationship of different individuals is made possible, is distinguished from the "intrinsic finality" of each individual, through which it is directed towards what it is.<ref>[https://www.newadvent.org/cathen/14474a.htm Teleology] ''The Catholic Encyclopedia''. Retrieved May 26, 2021.</ref> Aristotle's teleology was inherited to the creationist [[theology]] of [[Thomas Aquinas]] and others in the [[Catholic Church]].
  
Being, when it is contrasted with becoming, means immutability, permanence, or constant. For example, [[Plato]] found the primary sense of being in this sense. He asserted that the Ideas are "real" existence and material beings are ephemeral "shadows" of these Ideas for the reason that Ideas are immutable, permanent existence whereas material beings can decay and change. [[Aristotle]]'s concept of "[[substance]]" ("ousia") is also another example.
+
With the coming of the modern period, [[philosophy|philosophers]] began to question teleology. [[Francis Bacon]] and [[René Descartes]] cautioned against the abusive attribution of Aristotelian final causes to various things and events. One of the few exceptions was [[Gottfried Leibniz]]' notion of "pre-established harmony" of monads programmed by God. [[Immanuel Kant]] rejected not only the [[Aristotelianism|Aristotelian]] teleology of nature, but also the possibility of traditional [[metaphysics]] itself. Kant limited teleology to the subjective realm of [[mind]] and explored its possibility within the realms of [[ethics]] and [[aesthetics]]. Although [[Hegel]] temporally revived teleology in his speculative metaphysics, most post-Hegelian philosophers were not interested in [[ontology]] with its teleology of nature.  
  
Some philosophers, on the contrary, found the primary sense of being in change and process. [[Heraclitus]], for example, held this view and symbolized being as "fire." The existence of fire lies in its dynamic process of emission of energy. Likewise, for Heraclitus, being primarily means becoming, change, and dynamic process. [[Thomas Aquinas]] also applied this dynamic concept of being to [[God]]'s existence. Aquinas tried to present God's activity by this active concept of being.
+
[[Analytic philosophy|Analytic philosophers]] refused metaphysics itself and limited the question of teleology to the realm of conceptual analysis of [[language]]s. However, in the twentieth century, [[Martin Heidegger]] brought back ontology as a central question of philosophy. Combining the two trends of thought of his time, [[phenomenology]] and [[hermeneutics]], Heidegger developed ontology as a hermeneutic phenomenology. Within the framework of hermeneutic phenomenology, which still incorporated the Kantian [[skepticism]] of speculative metaphysics, he discussed the teleology of [[being]], conceptualizing the interconnected mode of human existence as "being-in-the-world" (''In-der-Welt-sein'').  
  
===Being and phenomena ===
+
Also with the emergence and development of existentialism, the question of the purposiveness, value, and relatedness of being has been addressed in a new way. [[Martin Buber]], for example, dealt with it in the context of the "I-Thou" relationship. [[Gabriel Marcel]] came up with the mutual, communal activity of being. However, although Buber and Marcel were theists, existentialism in general has often been critiqued of being fundamentally humanistic. Therefore, any teleology or theory of value developed by existentialism, no matter how insightful it may sound, has tended to be blamed for being self-made. At the same time, traditional Aristotelian teleology has been criticized of not being able to successfully establish the true relations not only amongst different individual substances but also between them and God because of the Aristotelian notion of God as self-contained "pure form" or "unmoved mover." To address these possible weaknesses of both existentialism and Aristotelianism, Schubert Ogden proposed to link the experiencing human subject in existentialism and the experiencing God of dipolarity in [[process thought]], hoping that the linkage of existentialist humanism and process theism in this regard would bring in a situation in which the unity of the whole of reality is realized centering on God's aim.<ref>Schubert Ogden, ''The Reality of God and Other Essays'' (Dallas, TX: Southern Methodist University Press, 1992).</ref>
  
Being, when it is contrasted with phenomena, means true reality in contrast to mere appearances or what appears to sense perception. Plato, for example, inquired into the true reality of being in contrast to what appears to our five senses. For Plato, the true reality of being are permanent, immutable Ideas. Thing are beautiful, for example, by virtue of the Idea of beauty which is the true reality. What appears to our five senses is a less real, ephemeral appearance.
+
==Existence as individuation or embodiment==
 +
The world of phenomena is the world where many particular things exist. Each particular thing is considered to have been developed or determined from its corresponding category or universal idea. The universal idea, then, is considered to have been individuated or embodied in that particular thing.
  
=== Being and thought ===
+
===Catholic philosophy===
 +
Medieval Catholic philosophy dealt with the issue of individuation. According to [[Thomas Aquinas]], the cause of individuation is matter, because different [[horse]]s, for example, result when their common universal idea of "horseness" is individuated by matter in each of them. It is just like today many different cars of the same model come into existence when its common mold is stamped to materials, which therefore turn out to be the cause of individuation. Aquinas called matter with this function ''"materia quantitate signata"'' ("matter signed in quantity"). According to [[Duns Scotus]], however, formless matter, which is itself indeterminate, cannot serve to make "horseness" into this horse or that horse. Although horseness itself may be common and repeatable, the horseness of this horse is to be distinguished from that of that horse. Scotus held, therefore, that individuation is caused by a determination called a ''haecceitas'' ("thisness"). It is not a bare particular in the sense of a [[substance]] but rather a non-qualitative property of a substance. It is something like a form. [[Francisco Suárez]], a [[Spain|Spanish]] [[Jesuit]] philosopher in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth century, went one step further, by maintaining that the principle of individuation is ''both'' this matter and this [[form]] of a substance in union, although the form is the chief principle: ''adaequatum individuationis principium esse hanc materiam et hanc formam inter se unitas, inter quae praecipuum principium est forma''.<ref>Francisco Suárez, ''Disputationes Metaphysicae: Disputationes IV, V, VI, VII (Latin Edition)'' (Independently published, 2020, ISBN 979-8637680733).</ref>
  
Being, when it is contrasted with thought, means the objective reality that is outside of the cognitive subject. Thought refers to ideas in the mind and being to spatio-temporal, extra-mental existence. This contrast was used by modern philosophers who had an [[epistemology|epistemological]] concern. The contrast of being and thought appeared within the question of how ideas or thoughts in the mind can be a real representation of the objective reality which exists outside of the mind.
+
===Religion===
 
+
In many [[religion]]s such as [[Hinduism]], [[Taoism]], [[Confucianism]], and [[Christianity]], [[enlightenment (concept)|enlightened]] people are considered to be individual embodiments of universal [[truth]]. Concrete existence is understood to have an intricate relationship with truth. [[Daoism]], for example, sees [[Lao Tzu]] as the embodiment of ''[[Tao]]''. In Christianity, [[Jesus]] said, "I am the way and the truth and the life. No one comes to the Father except through me." ([[Gospel of John|John]] 14:6). Here, truth is even understood not as some kind of property or object one can possess or lose, but as existence itself. So, Jesus did not say, "I have the truth," but "I am the truth." [[Christian Theology|Christian theology]] identifies him as the [[Logos]] Incarnate. ''Avatamsaka Sutra'' in [[Buddhism]] describes the world as the manifestation of truth.
=== Is (being) and ought ===
 
 
 
Being or "is," when it is contrasted with ought, means factuality in contrast to normativeness. Kant, for example, distinguished prescriptive statements in [[morality]], which use "ought" or "should," in contrast to natural, descriptive statements which describes what they factually are.
 
 
 
=== Being and essence ===
 
 
 
Being, when it is contrasted with essence, means actual existence. Essence of a being is what it is and whether it in fact exists or not is a separate question. [[Anselms]], for example, argued that God is a unique being whose essence is its existence while essence (what it is) and existence are separable for all beings other than God. He developed "[[arguments for the existence of God|ontological proof of the existence of God]]" based upon this identity of being and essence in God. Biblical concept of God as "I am who I am" expresses this identity.
 
 
 
=== Being and beings ===
 
 
 
Being, when it is contrasted with beings, means existence in the sense of event or fact of to-be. Beings mean particular entities that exist, but being means the fact of existence itself. Heidegger, for example, stressed upon this distinction in order to highlight the concept of being or to-be as a dynamic activity.
 
 
 
== Interdependency of being ==
 
 
 
Beings can exist in the web of interconnected relations to other beings. The relationship between God and human beings, those among human beings, those between human beings and material things, and those among material things are not the same. [[Martin Buber]], for example, conceptually distinguished God-man relationship as "I-thou" relationship from relationships among material things in the world.
 
 
 
[[Aristotle]] viewed the world as a [[teleology|teleologically]] organized organic whole, where all beings are mutually connected by multiple purposes. Medieval [[scholasticism|scholastics]] viewed this interconnectedness within a [[creationism|creationist]] perspective. [[Leibniz]] viewed this interconnectedness within the idea of "pre-established harmony," and [[Heidegger]] conceptualized the interconnected mode of human existence as "being-in-the-world."
 
 
 
== Historical conceptions ==
 
Existence can be seen as central to many systems of belief, religions, and myths. [[Belief]]s concerning existence may posit additional properties, such as ''value'' or ''goodness.'' Divergent conceptions of existence have often resulted in tension amongst communities with differing beliefs about existence, especially when coupled with the related question of [[World_view|worldview]].
 
 
 
In the western tradition of philosophy, the first comprehensive treatments of the subject are from [[Plato]]'s ''[[Phaedo]],'' ''[[The Republic (Plato)|Republic]],'' and ''[[Statesman (dialogue)|Statesman]]'' and [[Aristotle]]'s ''[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]],'' though earlier fragmentary writings exist. Aristotle developed a theory of being, according to which only individual things called [[substances]] are fully beings, but other things such as relations, quantity, time and place (called the [[Categories (Aristotle)|categories]]) have a derivative kind of being, dependent on individual things.
 
 
 
The medieval philosopher [[Thomas Aquinas]], perhaps following the Persian philosopher [[Avicenna]], argued that God is pure being, and that in God [[essence]] and existence are the same. At about the same time, the [[nominalist]] philosopher [[William of Ockham]], argued, in Book I of his [[Sum of Logic|Summa Totius Logicae]] (''Treatise on all Logic,'' written some time before 1327) that Categories are not a form of Being in their own right, but derivative on the existence of individuals.
 
 
 
In [[Hinduism|Hindu]] philosophy, existence is only of one object called [[Brahma]]. All other forms of existence are manifestations of this unique reality Brahma, due to influence of an agency called [[Maya]]. To perceive the existence of the unique reality of Brahma, one has to learn to come out of the influence of Maya.
 
 
 
==Predicative nature of existence==
 
[[John Stuart Mill]] (and also Kant's pupil [[Johann Friedrich Herbart|Herbart]]) argued that the predicative nature of existence was proved by sentences like "A centaur is a poetic fiction" <ref> John Stuart Mill. ''A System of Logic.'' (London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1884. OCLC 1261114)</ref> or "A greatest number is impossible" (Herbart). [[Franz Brentano]] challenged this, so also (as is better known) did [[Gottlob Frege|Frege]]. Brentano argued that we can join the concept represented by a noun phrase "an A" to the concept represented by an adjective "B" to give the concept represented by the noun phrase "a B-A." For example, we can join "a man" to "wise" to give "a wise man." But the noun phrase "a wise man" is not a sentence, whereas "some man is wise" is a sentence. Hence the copula must do more than merely join or separate concepts. Furthermore, adding "exists" to "a wise man," to give the complete sentence "a wise man exists" has the same effect as joining "some man" to "wise" using the copula. So the copula has the same effect as "exists." Brentano argued that every categorical proposition can be translated into an existential one without change in meaning and that the "exists" and "does not exist" of the existential proposition take the place of the copula. He showed this by the following examples:
 
 
 
: The categorical proposition "Some man is sick," has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A sick man exists" or "There is a sick man."
 
 
 
: The categorical proposition "No stone is living" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A living stone does not exist" or "there is no living stone."  
 
 
 
: The categorical proposition "All men are mortal" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "An immortal man does not exist" or "there is no immortal man."
 
 
 
: The categorical proposition "Some man is not learned" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A non-learned man exists" or "there is a non-learned man."
 
 
 
Frege developed a similar view (though later) in his great work [[The Foundations of Arithmetic]], as did [[Charles Peirce]]. The Frege-Brentano view is the basis of the dominant position in [[Analytic philosophy|modern Anglo-American philosophy]]: that existence is asserted by the existential quantifier (as expressed by [[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine]]'s slogan "To be is to be the value of a variable." &mdash; ''On What There Is.'' 1948).<ref> W.V. Quine. ''On What There Is.'' (Washington, DC: Catholic University of America, Philosophy Education Society, 1948, OCLC 43235388)</ref>
 
 
 
=== The semantics of existence ===
 
In [[mathematical logic]], there are two quantifiers, "some" and "all," though as [[Franz Brentano|Brentano]] (1838-1917) pointed out, we can make do with just one quantifier and negation. The first of these quantifiers, "some" is also expressed as "there exists." Thus, in the sentence "There exist a man," the term "man" is asserted to be part of existence. But we can also assert, "There exists a triangle." Is a "triangle," an abstract idea, part of existence in the same way that a "man," a physical body, is part of existence? Do abstractions such as goodness, blindness, and virtue exist in the same sense that chairs, tables, and houses exist? What [[Categories (Aristotle)|categories]], or kinds of thing can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition?
 
 
 
Worse, does "existence" exist?<ref>Bertrand Russell. ''The Principles of Mathematics.'' (New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Co., 1938, OCLC 3778306)</ref>
 
 
 
In some statements, existence is implied without being mentioned. The statement "A bridge crosses the Thames at Hammersmith." cannot just be about a bridge, the Thames, and Hammersmith. It must be about "existence" as well. On the other hand, the statement "A bridge crosses the Styx at Limbo," has the same form, but while in the first case we understand a real bridge in the real world made of stone or brick, what "existence" would mean in the second case is less clear.
 
 
 
The [[nominalist]] approach is to argue that certain noun phrases can be "eliminated" by rewriting a sentence in a form that has the same meaning, but which does not contain the noun phrase. Thus [[William of Ockham|Ockham]] argued that "Socrates has wisdom," which apparently asserts the existence of a reference for "wisdom," can be rewritten as "Socrates is wise," which contains only the referring phrase "Socrates." This method became widely accepted in the twentieth century by the [[Analytic philosophy|analytic school]] of philosophy.
 
 
 
However, this argument may be inverted by [[Philosophical realism|realists]] in arguing that since the sentence "Socrates is wise" can be rewritten as "Socrates has wisdom," this proves the existence of a hidden referent for "wise."
 
 
 
A further problem is that human beings seem to process information about fictional characters in much the same way that they process information about real people. An example of this is the common experience of actresses who play the villain in a soap opera being accosted in public as if they are to blame for the actions of the character they play.
 
 
 
A scientist might make a clear distinction about objects that exist, and assert that all objects that exist are made up of either matter or energy. But in the layperson's [[worldview]], existence includes real, fictional, and even contradictory objects. Thus if we reason from the statement ''[[Pegasus]] flies'' to the statement ''Pegasus exists,'' we are not asserting that Pegasus is made up of atoms, but rather that Pegasus exists in a particular worldview, the worldview of classical myth. When a mathematician reasons from the statement "ABC is a triangle" to the statement "triangles exist," she is not asserting that triangles are made up of atoms but rather that triangles exist within a particular [[mathematical model]].
 
 
 
==Modern approaches in the analytic philosophy==
 
According to [[Bertrand Russell]]'s [[Theory of Descriptions]], the negation operator in a singular sentence takes wide and narrow scope: we distinguish between "some S is not P" (where negation takes "narrow scope") and "it is not the case that 'some S is P'" (where negation takes "wide scope"). The problem with this view is that there appears to be no such scope distinction in the case of proper names. The sentences "Socrates is not bald" and "it is not the case that Socrates is bald" both appear to have the same meaning, and they both appear to assert or presuppose the existence of someone (Socrates) who is not bald, so that negation takes narrow scope.
 
 
 
The theory of descriptions has generally fallen into disrepute, though there have been recent attempts to revive it by [[Stephen Neale]] and [[Frank Cameron Jackson|Frank Jackson]]. According to the [[Direct reference|direct-reference]] view, an early version of which was originally proposed by [[Bertrand Russell]], and perhaps earlier by [[Gottlob Frege]], a proper name strictly has no meaning when there is no object to which it refers. This view relies on the argument that the semantic function of a proper name is to tell us ''which'' object bears the name, and thus to identify some object. But no object can be identified if none exists. Thus, a proper name must have a bearer if it is to be meaningful.
 
 
 
To adapt an argument of [[P. F. Strawson|Peter Strawson]]'s, someone who points to an apparently empty space, uttering "that's a fine red one" communicates nothing to someone who cannot see or understand what he is pointing to. Variants of the direct-reference view have been proposed by [[Saul Kripke]], [[Gareth Evans (philosopher)|Gareth Evans]], [[Nathan Salmon]], [[Scott Soames]], and others.
 
 
 
===Existence in the wide and narrow senses===
 
According to the "two sense" view of existence, which derives from [[Alexius Meinong]], existential statements fall into two classes. 
 
 
 
# Those asserting existence in a ''wide'' sense. These are typically of the form "N is P" for singular N, or "some S is P." 
 
# Those asserting existence in a ''narrow'' sense. These are typically of the form "N exists" or "S's exist."
 
 
 
The problem is then evaded as follows. "Pegasus flies" implies existence in the wide sense, for it implies that ''something'' flies. But it does not imply existence in the narrow sense, for we deny existence in this sense by saying that Pegasus does not exist. In effect, the world of all things divides, on this view, into those (like [[Socrates]], the planet [[Venus]], and New York City) that have existence in the narrow sense, and those (like [[Sherlock Holmes]], the goddess [[Venus (mythology)|Venus]], and [[Minas Tirith]]) that do not.
 
 
 
However, common sense suggests the non-existence of such things as [[fictional character]]s or places.
 
 
 
== See also ==
 
* ''[[Cogito ergo sum]]''
 
* [[Cosmological argument]]
 
* [[Existence proof]]
 
* [[Gödel's ontological proof]]
 
* [[Meaning of life (philosophy)|Meaning of life]]
 
* [[Metaphysics]]
 
* [[Ontology]]
 
* [[Solipsism]]
 
* [[Three marks of existence]]
 
  
 
==Notes==
 
==Notes==
Line 131: Line 63:
  
 
== References==  
 
== References==  
 
+
*Aristotle. ''The Metaphysics.'' Translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. London: Penguin Books, 1998. ISBN 0140446192
*Aristotle. ''The Metaphysics,'' translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. London ; New York: Penguin Books, 1998. ISBN 0140446192
+
*Arnauld, Antoine, and Pierre Nicole. ''Logic, or, The Art of Thinking: Containing, Besides Common Rules, Several New Observations Appropriate for Forming Judgment.'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN 0521482496
*Arnauld, Antoine and Pierre Nicole. ''Logic, or, The art of thinking: containing, besides common rules, several new observations appropriate for forming judgment.'' Cambridge [England] ; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN 0521482496
+
*Eagleton, Terry. ''The Meaning of Life.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. ISBN 0199210705
*Eagleton, Terry. ''The Meaning of Life.'' Oxford ; New York: Oxford University Press, 2007. ISBN 0199210705  
+
*Edwards, Paul (ed.). ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy.'' New York: Macmillan, 1967. ISBN 978-0028949901
*Heraclitus, ''Fragments'', translated by Brooks Hexton. New York : Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0142437654
+
*Heidegger, Martin. ''Being and Time''. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper & Row, 1962. ISBN 0060638508
*Kahn, Charles H. "On the Terminology for Copula and Existence." In ''Islamic Philosophy and the Classical Tradition: Essays Presented by His Friends and Pupils to Richard Waltzer on His Seventieth Birthday'', edited by S. M. Stern, Albert Hourani, and Vivian Brown. London: Bruno Cassier, 1972.
+
*Heraclitus. ''Fragments''. Translated by Brooks Hexton. New York: Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0142437654
*Kahn, Charles H. "Why Existence Does Not Emerge as a Distinct Concept in Greek Philosophy?" In ''Philosophies of Existence: Ancient and Medieval'', edited by Parviz Morewedge. New York: Fordham University Press, 1982. ISBN 082321060X
 
 
*Loux, Michael J. ''Ockham's Theory Of Terms.'' London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974. ISBN 0268005508
 
*Loux, Michael J. ''Ockham's Theory Of Terms.'' London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974. ISBN 0268005508
 
*Magee, Bryan. ''The Story of Philosophy.'' New York: DK Pub., 1998. ISBN 078943511X
 
*Magee, Bryan. ''The Story of Philosophy.'' New York: DK Pub., 1998. ISBN 078943511X
 
*Mill, John Stuart. ''A System of Logic.'' London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1884.
 
*Mill, John Stuart. ''A System of Logic.'' London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1884.
*Plato. ''The Republic,'' translated by Sir Henry Desmond Pritchard Lee. London ; New York: Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0140449140
+
*Morewedge, Parviz (ed.). ''Philosophies of Existence: Ancient and Medieval.'' New York: Fordham University Press, 1982. ISBN 082321060X
*Prior, Arthur Norman. "Existence." In ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', edited by Paul Edwards. New York: Macmillan, 1967. ISBN 0028949900
+
*Ogden, Schubert. ''The Reality of God and Other Essays''. Dallas, TX: Southern Methodist University Press, 1992. ISBN 087074318X
*Quine, W.V. ''On What There Is.'' Washington, DC: Catholic University of America, Philosophy Education Society, 1948.
+
*Plato. ''The Republic.'' Translated by Sir Henry Desmond Pritchard Lee. London: Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0140449140
 +
*Quine, W.V. ''Ontological Relativity and Other Essays''. New York: Columbia University Press, 1969. ISBN 0231033079
 +
*Quine, W.V. ''From a Logical Point of View''. Harvard University Press, 1980. ISBN 978-0674323513
 +
*Stern, S.M., Albert Hourani, and Vivian Brown (eds.). ''Islamic Philosophy and the Classical Tradition: Essays Presented by His Friends and Pupils to Richard Waltzer on His Seventieth Birthday.'' University of South Carolina Press, 1972. ISBN 978-0872492714
 +
*Suárez, Francisco. ''Disputationes Metaphysicae: Disputationes IV, V, VI, VII (Latin Edition)'' Independently published, 2020. ISBN 979-8637680733.
  
 
== External links ==  
 
== External links ==  
All links retrieved November 12, 2007.
+
All links retrieved September 26, 2023.  
{{wiktionary|existence}}
+
 
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existence/ Existence] on the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
+
*[https://www.ontology.co/existence.htm The Concept of Existence: History and Definitions by Leading Philosophers] ''The Concept of Existence: Definitions by Major Philosophers''.
* [http://www.formalontology.it/existence.htm Existence. Definitions from leading philosophers]
+
*[https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existence/ Existence] ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''.  
* [http://www.interragation.com A documentary project about the meaning of life.]
+
 
===General Philosophy Sources===
+
===General philosophy sources===
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
 
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
*[http://www.epistemelinks.com/  Philosophy Sources on Internet EpistemeLinks]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
*[http://www.earlham.edu/~peters/gpi/index.htm Guide to Philosophy on the Internet]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
 
 
 
 
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
Line 164: Line 98:
 
{{Philosophy (navigation)}}
 
{{Philosophy (navigation)}}
  
{{credit|170437594}}
+
{{credit|Existence|170437594}}

Latest revision as of 10:29, 26 September 2023

The Being according to Parmenidesis like the mass of a sphere.

Being and existence in philosophy are related and somewhat overlapping with respect to their meanings. Classical Greek had no independent word of "existence." The word "existence," as distinguished from the word "being," arose in the Middle Ages. Influenced by Islamic philosophy that recognized the contingency of the created world as compared with God the Creator, Christian philosophers such as Thomas Aquinas used the Latin word "existere" ("to exist" or "to appear") as distinct from "esse" ("to be") or "essentia" ("essence"). The Medieval distinction between essence and existence in the world, however, was critiqued by later theologians and philosophers for various reasons.

Modern existentialism maintained the distinction between essence and existence, but reversed the Medieval priority of essence over existence. The German philosopher Martin Heidegger, who critiqued the Thomistic theory of the causal relationship of difference between God and the world as well as its related theory of the distinction between essence and existence, dealt with the question of being in a very new way that involved the human being as Dasein ("being-there"), which to him is synonymous with existence.

The majority of analytic philosophers have rejected the distinction of being and existence. But, for philosophers and theologians who consider the distinction between being and existence an important one, there are two significant issues: teleology and individuation or embodiment. For what purpose do individual things exist? How do things become individual embodiments of their corresponding universals? A notable approach to the first issue was proposed by the American theologian Schubert Ogden, who combined existentialism with process theism to explain the unity of reality centering on God's aim. The Spanish Jesuit Francisco Suárez approached the second issue by proposing that the form and matter of a substance in union determine the individuality of that embodied substance.

Relationship of being and existence

Greek philosophy

History shows a rather complex relationship between being and existence. The classical Greek equivalent of the English verb "be" was "einai," but there seems to have been no classical Greek equivalent of the English verb "exist." It was only in the Middle Ages that the Latin word "exsistere" was made from a combination of "ex" ("out of") and "sistere" ("to cause to stand") to mean "to exist," "to appear," or "to emerge." The reason why classical Greek did not have any distinct concept of "exist" was that in Greek philosophy from Parmenides to Aristotle the primary project was a veridical one of articulating truthfulness in reality through copula sentences of the form "X is Y."[1] The theory of predication was central, and the theory of existence peripheral. So, even when Greek philosophers wanted to express the concept of existence, they did so only in the predicative form; "X exists" was expressed as "X is something." Thus, the word "einai" ("be") had to be used more widely than its predicative meaning. It was in the context of this wider use of "einai" ("be") that Aristotle referred to the concept of existence as "hoti esti" ("that it is") as distinguished from "ti esti" ("what it is"), which would mean essence.

Of course, in late Greek philosophy the old Greek verb "hyparkein" (originally, "to make a beginning") started to be used non-technically to mean "to exist"; but, it and its early Latin rendering "exsistere" still continued somewhat ambiguously to retain the predicative meaning as well, and furthermore the use of the noun exsistentia ("existence") was not popular yet.

Medieval Christian philosophy

Eventually, however, the concept of "existentia" ("existence") was established amongst Medieval Christian philosophers such as St. Thomas Aquinas as a technical term contrasted with "essentia" ("essence"), an abstract form of the presumed present participle of "esse" ("to be"). While essence apparently meant "what a thing is," existence meant "that a thing exists." According to Charles H. Khan, this development of the modern sense of existence occurred under the influence of Islamic philosophy, which distinguished existence (wujud) from essence (mahiat) in its radical revision of Greek ontology in light of a biblical metaphysics of creation within Islam which distinguished the created world (contingency) from God (necessity).[1] Aquinas adopted this, maintaining that the essence and existence of each and every contingent, finite creature are distinct, while essence and existence are identical within God, who is therefore preeminent over the world. According to him, God causes each and every finite creature to "exist" with its "essence."

Aquinas, however, indicated this causal relationship of difference between God and the world in terms of the "analogia entis" ("analogy of being"), referring to God and each finite creature as "ipsum esse subsistens" (Self-subsistent Being) and "ens" (being), respectively. This means that in spite of the development of "existentia" ("existence") as a new word with a distinctive meaning in the Middle Ages, still the term "esse" ("to be") was used more generally to cover the meaning of existence as well. Modern existentialism's emphasis upon the priority of existence over essence was still alien.

Later criticisms of the Thomistic position

The Thomistic distinction between essence and existence in the created world was criticized by later theologians and philosophers for various reasons. Critics include Duns Scotus, Francisco Suárez, René Descartes, Gottfried Leibniz, David Hume, and Immanuel Kant. But, especially existentialim's criticism was notable because of its attempt to reverse the order of priority between essence and existence. Søren Kierkegaard denied the importance of the objective essence of a thing in favor of the subjective appropriation of it. He, thus, held that there is no truth in objective knowledge of essence itself, and that the truth about reality is revealed only in the human subject's "passion of the infinite" as a believer. In talking about the essence and existence of a human being, Jean-Paul Sartre, for whom existentialism meant an atheistic humanism, went so far as to say that because there is no Creator, existence precedes essence.

The most notable critic, however, was the German philosopher Martin Heidegger. According to Heidegger, Aquinas' theory of the causal relationship of difference between God and the world through the analogy of being, and his related theory of the distinction between essence and existence in the world, are far from answering the fundamental question of the meaning of being, which was not answered in the long philosophical tradition in the West anyway because being itself was taken for granted as self-evident or undefinable. Therefore, in order to let the human being constantly pursue the question of "being" (Sein), Heidegger referred to that human being as "Dasein" (literally "being-there"), who, as a "being-in-the-world" (In-der-Welt-sein) thrown out to the temporal and phenomenological world of "beings" (Seiendes), is faced with angst and mortality there, but who nevertheless is expected to experience authenticity by standing in the openness of "being" in the midst of "beings." Here, the sense of "being" to be experienced is pre-conceptual and non-propositional in the everyday situation of human life; and the causal relationship of difference between God as "Self-subsistent Being" (ipsum esse subsistens) and the created world of "beings" (ens) in Aquinas' metaphysics is superseded by the distinction between "being" (Sein) and "beings" (Seiendes) in Heidegger's phenomenological ontology in pursuit of the meaning of "being." For Heidegger, the word "existence" (Existenz) is simply synonymous with Dasein: "The 'essence' of Dasein lies in its existence."[2]

Being and existence in analytic philosophy

Actualism

Many analytic philosophers in the twentieth century such as Gottlob Frege, Bertrand Russell, and W.V. Quine, believed that being and existence are identical, that is, that what there is, is precisely what exists. It is basically so-called "actualism," and it maintains that there is no kind of being beyond actual existence. The identity of being and existence also means that every predicative proposition can be translated into an existential one without changing meaning. For example, adding "exists" to "a wise man" to give the complete sentence "A wise man exists" has the same effect as joining "some man" to "wise" using the copula to say "Some man is wise." So, the "exists" of the existential proposition takes the place of the copula. This view is the basis of the dominant position in modern Anglo-American analytic philosophy: that existence is asserted by the existential quantifier.

Possibilism

Of course, there is a school called "possibilism," which distinguishes between being and existence, that is, between what there is and what exists, saying that the latter comprises a relatively small portion of the former. According to this, although there are things that actually exist, there are also things that do not exist: they are what there merely are, not having existence or actuality, which only things that actually exist have. Such things are non-existent possible things like Santa Claus, unicorns, aliens, and people that were never born. They could have actually existed, but as it happens, they simply do not. To this possibilist realm of the non-existent, some of the followers of Alexius Meinong such as Terence Parsons would add impossible objects like square circles and wooden iron, which have contradictory properties.

Adjusted possibilism

But, scholars such as Quine, for whom there is no distinction between being and existence, have critiqued possibilism, by saying that we cannot embrace non-actual possible objects since there is no real criterion of identity for them: "No entity without identity."[3] This critique from Quine has given rise to an adjusted version of possibilism, which now agrees that being and existence are identical, saying that everything there is exists, but which nevertheless insists that not everything that exists is actual, that is, that there exist things that fail to be actual. This, however, looks like a word game, simply renaming being as "existence" and existence as "actuality." Thus, a more advanced version of possibilism, which takes Quine's objection more seriously, has been developed by David Kellogg Lewis.

Modal realism

While agreeing with the adjusted version just mentioned above that being and existence are identical, but that actuality is to be distinguished from existence, Lewis has a new understanding of actuality, treating it in terms of relation. Thus, according to Lewis, when people say that there are things that exist but are not actual, it means that there are things that are spatiotemporally unrelated to the world, although they exist in a full-fledged sense in other worlds. The word "actual," then, is an indexical, whose reference on any given occasion of utterance is determined by the context or world in which the utterance occurs. So, when one utter, "New York City is actual" (or more naturally, "New York City actually exists"), its truthfulness is made not because actuality is some intrinsic property of New York City but rather because New York City occupies the same world as the speaker. Lewis' version of possibilism is sometimes called "modal realism," and it is quite Quinean.

Different realms of reality

The issue on whether or not there are different worlds or realms of reality is not new. Ancient Greek philosophy observed that there are concrete, material beings in the spatiotemporal world in the sense of physical reality which is detectable by physical senses or physical instruments, while there are also ideas and values such as love, justice, and good which however are not of the same physically sensible material. For Plato, those ideas and values in an incorporeal realm of the world are real beings because they are self-existent and immutable, while material beings in the corporeal world are merely their ephemeral "shadows" far from real beings. For Aristotle, by contrast, only individual things called substances in the spatiotemporal world are fully existent beings, and other beings, called categories, such as relation, quantity, time and place, and Plato's ideas and values, have a derivative kind of being, dependent on those individual things. In the Middle Ages, based upon a biblical metaphysics of creation, the notion of existence was established to show the emergence of the created world, distinguishable from being in general and also from essence.

The Plato-Aristotle tension above was echoed in the Medieval controversy between realism and nominalism. The approach of realists was to argue that the sentence "Socrates is wise," which contains a noun reference only for "Socrates," can be rewritten as "Socrates has wisdom," which apparently proves the existence of a reference for "wisdom" as well. This argument, however, was inverted by nominalists such as William of Ockham in arguing that "Socrates has wisdom" can be rewritten as "Socrates is wise," which contains a reference only for "Socrates." The nominalist method has basically been inherited in analytic philosophy, which holds that there is hardly any kind of being beyond actual existence.

Teleology, being, and existence

The teleological nature of reality was discussed by Plato and Aristotle. Plato identified the Idea of the Good as the ultimate cause or measure in the whole of reality, saying that things that are gain their usefulness or value from it. Aristotle maintained that each substance has its final cause, which guides it throughout various changes it goes through to reach what it is. According to him, the final cause is virtually identical with the formal and efficient causes because all these can be attributed to the form of each substance, which is immanent in it, although God as "pure form" is the ultimate final, formal, and efficient cause, towards which all things tend. This teleological approach does not believe that the final causes of different substances are incompatible with one other, but rather that they are for one another. Hence, "extrinsic finality," through which the harmonious relationship of different individuals is made possible, is distinguished from the "intrinsic finality" of each individual, through which it is directed towards what it is.[4] Aristotle's teleology was inherited to the creationist theology of Thomas Aquinas and others in the Catholic Church.

With the coming of the modern period, philosophers began to question teleology. Francis Bacon and René Descartes cautioned against the abusive attribution of Aristotelian final causes to various things and events. One of the few exceptions was Gottfried Leibniz' notion of "pre-established harmony" of monads programmed by God. Immanuel Kant rejected not only the Aristotelian teleology of nature, but also the possibility of traditional metaphysics itself. Kant limited teleology to the subjective realm of mind and explored its possibility within the realms of ethics and aesthetics. Although Hegel temporally revived teleology in his speculative metaphysics, most post-Hegelian philosophers were not interested in ontology with its teleology of nature.

Analytic philosophers refused metaphysics itself and limited the question of teleology to the realm of conceptual analysis of languages. However, in the twentieth century, Martin Heidegger brought back ontology as a central question of philosophy. Combining the two trends of thought of his time, phenomenology and hermeneutics, Heidegger developed ontology as a hermeneutic phenomenology. Within the framework of hermeneutic phenomenology, which still incorporated the Kantian skepticism of speculative metaphysics, he discussed the teleology of being, conceptualizing the interconnected mode of human existence as "being-in-the-world" (In-der-Welt-sein).

Also with the emergence and development of existentialism, the question of the purposiveness, value, and relatedness of being has been addressed in a new way. Martin Buber, for example, dealt with it in the context of the "I-Thou" relationship. Gabriel Marcel came up with the mutual, communal activity of being. However, although Buber and Marcel were theists, existentialism in general has often been critiqued of being fundamentally humanistic. Therefore, any teleology or theory of value developed by existentialism, no matter how insightful it may sound, has tended to be blamed for being self-made. At the same time, traditional Aristotelian teleology has been criticized of not being able to successfully establish the true relations not only amongst different individual substances but also between them and God because of the Aristotelian notion of God as self-contained "pure form" or "unmoved mover." To address these possible weaknesses of both existentialism and Aristotelianism, Schubert Ogden proposed to link the experiencing human subject in existentialism and the experiencing God of dipolarity in process thought, hoping that the linkage of existentialist humanism and process theism in this regard would bring in a situation in which the unity of the whole of reality is realized centering on God's aim.[5]

Existence as individuation or embodiment

The world of phenomena is the world where many particular things exist. Each particular thing is considered to have been developed or determined from its corresponding category or universal idea. The universal idea, then, is considered to have been individuated or embodied in that particular thing.

Catholic philosophy

Medieval Catholic philosophy dealt with the issue of individuation. According to Thomas Aquinas, the cause of individuation is matter, because different horses, for example, result when their common universal idea of "horseness" is individuated by matter in each of them. It is just like today many different cars of the same model come into existence when its common mold is stamped to materials, which therefore turn out to be the cause of individuation. Aquinas called matter with this function "materia quantitate signata" ("matter signed in quantity"). According to Duns Scotus, however, formless matter, which is itself indeterminate, cannot serve to make "horseness" into this horse or that horse. Although horseness itself may be common and repeatable, the horseness of this horse is to be distinguished from that of that horse. Scotus held, therefore, that individuation is caused by a determination called a haecceitas ("thisness"). It is not a bare particular in the sense of a substance but rather a non-qualitative property of a substance. It is something like a form. Francisco Suárez, a Spanish Jesuit philosopher in the late sixteenth and early seventeenth century, went one step further, by maintaining that the principle of individuation is both this matter and this form of a substance in union, although the form is the chief principle: adaequatum individuationis principium esse hanc materiam et hanc formam inter se unitas, inter quae praecipuum principium est forma.[6]

Religion

In many religions such as Hinduism, Taoism, Confucianism, and Christianity, enlightened people are considered to be individual embodiments of universal truth. Concrete existence is understood to have an intricate relationship with truth. Daoism, for example, sees Lao Tzu as the embodiment of Tao. In Christianity, Jesus said, "I am the way and the truth and the life. No one comes to the Father except through me." (John 14:6). Here, truth is even understood not as some kind of property or object one can possess or lose, but as existence itself. So, Jesus did not say, "I have the truth," but "I am the truth." Christian theology identifies him as the Logos Incarnate. Avatamsaka Sutra in Buddhism describes the world as the manifestation of truth.

Notes

  1. 1.0 1.1 Charles H. Kahn, "Why Existence Does Not Emerge as a Distinct Concept in Greek Philosophy?" in Philosophies of Existence: Ancient and Medieval, ed. Parviz Morewedge (New York: Fordham University Press, 1982).
  2. Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, tr. John Macquarrie & Edward Robinson (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), 67.
  3. W.V. Quine, Ontological Relativity and Other Essays (New York: Columbia University Press, 1969), 23.
  4. Teleology The Catholic Encyclopedia. Retrieved May 26, 2021.
  5. Schubert Ogden, The Reality of God and Other Essays (Dallas, TX: Southern Methodist University Press, 1992).
  6. Francisco Suárez, Disputationes Metaphysicae: Disputationes IV, V, VI, VII (Latin Edition) (Independently published, 2020, ISBN 979-8637680733).

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Aristotle. The Metaphysics. Translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. London: Penguin Books, 1998. ISBN 0140446192
  • Arnauld, Antoine, and Pierre Nicole. Logic, or, The Art of Thinking: Containing, Besides Common Rules, Several New Observations Appropriate for Forming Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN 0521482496
  • Eagleton, Terry. The Meaning of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. ISBN 0199210705
  • Edwards, Paul (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York: Macmillan, 1967. ISBN 978-0028949901
  • Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Translated by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. New York: Harper & Row, 1962. ISBN 0060638508
  • Heraclitus. Fragments. Translated by Brooks Hexton. New York: Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0142437654
  • Loux, Michael J. Ockham's Theory Of Terms. London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974. ISBN 0268005508
  • Magee, Bryan. The Story of Philosophy. New York: DK Pub., 1998. ISBN 078943511X
  • Mill, John Stuart. A System of Logic. London: Longmans, Green, and Co., 1884.
  • Morewedge, Parviz (ed.). Philosophies of Existence: Ancient and Medieval. New York: Fordham University Press, 1982. ISBN 082321060X
  • Ogden, Schubert. The Reality of God and Other Essays. Dallas, TX: Southern Methodist University Press, 1992. ISBN 087074318X
  • Plato. The Republic. Translated by Sir Henry Desmond Pritchard Lee. London: Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0140449140
  • Quine, W.V. Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press, 1969. ISBN 0231033079
  • Quine, W.V. From a Logical Point of View. Harvard University Press, 1980. ISBN 978-0674323513
  • Stern, S.M., Albert Hourani, and Vivian Brown (eds.). Islamic Philosophy and the Classical Tradition: Essays Presented by His Friends and Pupils to Richard Waltzer on His Seventieth Birthday. University of South Carolina Press, 1972. ISBN 978-0872492714
  • Suárez, Francisco. Disputationes Metaphysicae: Disputationes IV, V, VI, VII (Latin Edition) Independently published, 2020. ISBN 979-8637680733.

External links

All links retrieved September 26, 2023.

General philosophy sources


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.