Descartes, Rene

From New World Encyclopedia
 
(30 intermediate revisions by 8 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Contracted}}
+
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{copyedited}}
{{epname}}
+
{{epname|Descartes, Rene}}
{{Infobox_Philosopher |
+
{{Infobox Philosopher  
  <!-- Scroll down to edit this page —>
+
| region           = Western Philosophy                                                 
  <!-- Philosopher Category —>
+
| era             = [[Seventeenth century philosophy]]  
  region         = Western Philosophers |
 
  era             = [[17th-century philosophy]]<br>(Modern Philosophy) |
 
  era_color      = #87CEEB |
 
  
  <!-- Image and Caption —>
+
| color            = #B0C4DE
  image_name     = Descartes.jpg |
+
| image_name       = Descartes.jpg  
  image_caption   = René Descartes |
+
| image_caption   = René Descartes  
 
+
| name             = René Descartes  
  <!-- Basic Information —>
+
| birth            = March 31, 1596<br/>[[La Haye en Touraine]] [now Descartes], [[Indre-et-Loire]], [[France]]
  name           = René Descartes |
+
| death            = {{Death date and age|1650|2|11|1596|3|31}}<br/>[[Stockholm]], [[Sweden]]
  dates          = [[March 31]], [[1596]] &ndash; [[February 11]], [[1650]] |
+
| school_tradition = [[Cartesianism]], [[Rationalism]], [[Foundationalism]]  
  birthplace      = [[La Haye en Touraine]], [[Indre-et-Loire]], [[France]] |
+
| main_interests  = [[Metaphysics]], [[Epistemology]], [[Science]], [[Mathematics]]  
  deathplace      = [[Stockholm]], [[Sweden]] |
+
| influences      = [[Al-Ghazali]], [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Anselm of Canterbury|Anselm]], [[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas]], [[William of Ockham|Ockham]], [[Francisco Suárez|Suarez]], [[Marin Mersenne|Mersenne]], [[Sextus Empiricus]], [[Michel de Montaigne]], [[Duns Scotus]]
  school_tradition = [[Cartesianism]], [[Continental rationalism]] |
+
| influenced      = [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]], [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], [[Antoine Arnauld|Arnauld]], [[Nicolas Malebranche|Malebranche]], [[Blaise Pascal|Pascal]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[Henry More|More]], [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], [[Edmund Husserl|Husserl]], [[Léon Brunschvicg|Brunschvicg]], [[Slavoj Žižek|Žižek]], [[Noam Chomsky|Chomsky]]
  major_works      = [[Discourse on Method]], [[Meditations on First Philosophy]], [[Principles of Philosophy]] |
+
| notable_ideas    = [[Cogito ergo sum]], [[Methodic Doubt|method of doubt]], [[Cartesian coordinate system]], [[Cartesian dualism]], [[ontological argument]] for God's existence; regarded as a founder of [[Modern philosophy]]
  main_interests  = [[Metaphysics]], [[Epistemology]], [[Science]], [[Mathematics]] |
 
  influences      = [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Anselm of Canterbury|Anselm]], [[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas]], [[William of Ockham|Ockham]], [[Francisco Suárez|Suarez]], [[Marin Mersenne|Mersenne]], [[Augustine of Hippo]], [[Michel de Montaigne]] |
 
  influenced      = [[Baruch Spinoza]], [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[Immanuel Kant]], [[Gottfried Leibniz]] |
 
  famous_ideas    = Cogito ergo sum (see quote), method of doubt, [[Cartesian coordinate system]], [[ontological argument]] for God's existence; regarded as the father of [[Modern philosophy]] |
 
  quote            = ''I think, therefore I am.''<br>-[[Discourse on Method]] ([[1637]]) |
 
 
}}
 
}}
 +
'''René Descartes''' (French {{IPA2|ʁə'ne de'kaʁt}}) (March 31, 1596 &ndash; February 11, 1650), also known as ''Renatus Cartesius'' ([[Latinisation|latinized]] form), was a highly influential [[French philosophy|French philosopher]], [[mathematician]], [[scientist]], and [[writer]]. He has been dubbed the "Father of Modern Philosophy" and the "Father of Modern Mathematics," and much of subsequent Western philosophy is a reaction to his writings, which have been closely studied from his time through the present day. His influence in mathematics is also apparent; the [[Cartesian coordinate system]] that is used in plane geometry and algebra being named for him and he was one of the key figures in the [[Scientific Revolution]].
  
'''René Descartes''' ([[International Phonetic Alphabet|IPA]]: {{IPA |/deˈkaʁt/}}, March 31, 1596&ndash; [[February 11]], [[1650]]), also known as '''Cartesius''', was a [[French people|French]] [[philosopher]], [[mathematician]] and part-time [[mercenary]] in the opening phases of the [[Thirty Years' War]]. He is noted equally for  his groundbreaking work in philosophy and mathematics. As the inventor of the [[Cartesian coordinate system]], he formulated the basis of modern geometry ([[analytic geometry]]), which in turn influenced the development of modern [[calculus]].
+
Descartes frequently sets his views apart from those of his predecessors. In the opening section of the ''[[Passions of the Soul]],'' a treatise on the [[Early Modern]] version of what are now commonly called emotions, he goes so far as to assert that he will write on his topic "as if no one had written on these matters before." Many elements of his philosophy have precedents in late [[Aristotelianism]], the revived [[Stoicism]] of the [[sixteenth century]], or in earlier philosophers like [[Augustine of Hippo|St. Augustine]]. In his natural philosophy, he differs from the [[Scholasticism|Schools]] on two major points: First, he rejects the analysis of [[corporeal substance]] into matter and form; second, he rejects any appeal to [[Teleology|ends]]—divine or natural—in explaining natural phenomena. In his [[theology]], he insists on the absolute freedom of God’s act of creation.
 
+
{{toc}}
Descartes, dubbed the "Founder of Modern Philosophy" and the "Father of Modern Mathematics," ranks as one of the most important and influential thinkers in modern western history. He inspired his contemporaries and subsequent generations of philosophers, leading them to form what we know today as [[continental rationalism]], a philosophical position which developed in [[17th century|17th]] and [[18th century]] [[Europe]].
+
Descartes was a major figure in seventeenth century continental [[rationalism]], later advocated by [[Baruch Spinoza]] and [[Gottfried Leibniz]], and opposed by the [[empiricist]] school of thought consisting of [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[George Berkeley|Berkeley]], and [[David Hume|Hume]]. Leibniz, Spinoza, and Descartes were all versed in mathematics as well as philosophy, and Descartes and Leibniz contributed greatly to science as well. As the inventor of the [[Cartesian coordinate system]], Descartes founded [[analytic geometry]], the bridge between algebra and geometry crucial to the invention of [[calculus]] and [[Mathematical analysis|analysis]]. Descartes's reflections on mind and mechanism began the strain of western thought that much later, impelled by the invention of the [[electronic computer]] and by the possibility of [[machine intelligence]], blossomed into the [[Turing test]] and related thought. His most famous statement is: ''[[Cogito ergo sum]]'' ({{lang-fr|Je pense, donc je suis}}; {{lang-en|I think, therefore I am}}), found in §7 of part I of ''[[Principles of Philosophy]]'' (Latin) and in part IV of ''[[Discourse on the Method]]'' (French).
 
 
His most famous statement is "[[Cogito ergo sum]]" ("I think, therefore I am").
 
 
 
== Biography ==
 
 
 
Descartes was born in [[La Haye en Touraine]], [[Indre-et-Loire]], [[France]], a town later renamed for him:  "La Haye-Descartes" (1802) and simply "Descartes" (1967).  At the age of eight, he entered the [[Society of Jesus|Jesuit]] [[Prytanee|College Royal Henry-Le-Grand]] at [[La Flèche]].  After graduation, he studied at the University of [[Poitiers]], earning a ''Baccalauréat'' and ''Licence'' in [[law]] in 1616.  
 
 
 
Descartes never actually practiced law, however, and in 1618 he entered the service of Prince [[Maurice of Nassau]], leader of the United Provinces of the [[Netherlands]], with the intention of following a military career. Here he met [[Isaac Beeckman]] and composed a short treatise on music entitled ''[[Compendium Musicae]]''. In 1619, Descartes travelled in Germany, and on November 10 had a vision of a new mathematical and scientific system.  In 1622 he returned to France, and during the next few years spent time in Paris and other parts of Europe. Descartes was present at the siege of [[La Rochelle]] by Cardinal [[Richelieu]] in 1627.
 
 
 
In 1628, Descartes composed ''[[Rules for the Direction of the Mind]]'' and left for Holland, where he lived, changing his address frequently, until 1649. In 1629 he began work on ''[[The World (Descartes)|The World]]''.  In 1633, [[Galileo Galilei|Galileo]] was condemned, and Descartes abandoned plans to publish ''The World''.  In 1635, Descartes' daughter [[Francine Descartes|Francine]] was born.  She was baptized on August 7, 1635 and died in 1640.  Descartes published ''[[Discourse on Method]]'', with ''Optics'', ''Meteorology'' and ''Geometry'' in 1637.  In 1641, ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]]'' was published, with the first six sets of ''Objections and Replies''.  In 1642, the second edition of ''Meditations'' was published with all seven sets of ''Objections and Replies'', followed by ''Letter to Dinet''.  In 1643, Cartesian philosophy was condemned at the [[Utrecht University|University of Utrecht]], and Descartes began his long correspondence with [[Elisabeth of Bohemia, Princess Palatine|Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia]].  Descartes published ''[[Principles of Philosophy]]'' and visited France in 1644.  In 1647, he was awarded a pension by the [[King of France]], published ''[[Comments on a Certain Broadsheet]]'', and began work on ''[[The Description of the Human Body]]''.  Descartes was interviewed by [[Frans Burman]] at [[Egmond-Binnen]] in 1648, resulting in ''[[Conversation with Burman]]''.  In 1649, Descartes went to Sweden on invitation of [[professor Eitan Olevsky]]; Descartes' ''[[Passions of the Soul]]'', which he dedicated to Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia, was published.
 
 
 
René Descartes died on February 11, 1650 in Stockholm, Sweden, where he had been invited as a teacher for Queen [[Christina of Sweden]]. The cause of death was said to be pneumonia - accustomed to working in bed till noon, he may have suffered a detrimental effect on his health due to Christina's demands for early morning study. However, letters to and from the doctor [[Eike Pies]] have recently been discovered which indicate that Descartes may have been poisoned using [[arsenic]].
 
 
 
In 1667, after his death, the [[Roman Catholic Church]] placed his works on the [[Index Librorum Prohibitorum|Index of Prohibited Books]].
 
 
 
As a [[Catholic]] in a [[Protestant]] nation, he was interred in a graveyard mainly used for unbaptized infants, in [[Adolf Fredrikskyrkan]] in Stockholm, Sweden. Later, his remains were taken to France and buried in the Church of St. Genevieve-du-Mont in Paris. A memorial erected in the 18th century remains in the Swedish church.
 
  
During the [[French Revolution]], his remains were disinterred for burial in the [[Panthéon, Paris|Panthéon]] among the great French thinkers. The village in the [[Loire Valley]] where he was born was renamed ''La Haye - Descartes''. Currently his tomb is in the church Saint Germain-des-Pres in Paris.
+
== Biography==
 +
[[Image:René Descartes i samtal med Sveriges drottning, Kristina.jpg|thumb|240px|René Descartes with Queen [[Christina of Sweden]].]]
 +
[[Image:DescartesGraduationRegistry.JPG|thumb|240px|Graduation registry for Descartes at the [[Prytanee|Collège Royal Henry-Le-Grand]], [[La Flèche]], 1616.]]
 +
[[Image:DescartesAshes.jpg|thumb|240px|The tomb of Descartes (middle, with detail of the inscription), in the church of [[Saint-Germain-des-Prés]], [[Paris]].]]
 +
Descartes was born in [[La Haye en Touraine]] (now Descartes), [[Indre-et-Loire]], [[France]]. When he was one year old, his mother Jeanne Brochard died of [[tuberculosis]]. His father Joachim was a judge in the High Court of Justice. At the age of eleven, he entered the [[Society of Jesus|Jesuit]] [[Prytanee|Collège Royal Henry-Le-Grand]] at [[La Flèche]]. After graduation, he studied at the [[University of Poitiers]], earning a ''[[Baccalauréat]]'' and ''License'' in [[law]] in 1616, in accordance with his father's wishes that he should become a lawyer.
  
== Significance ==
+
Descartes never actually practiced law, however, and in 1618, during the [[Thirty Years' War]], he entered the service of [[Maurice of Nassau]], leader of the United Provinces of the [[Netherlands]]. His reason for becoming a mercenary was to see the world and to discover the truth.
  
=== Philosophical Legacy & the 'Meditations'===
+
<blockquote>I entirely abandoned the study of letters. Resolving to seek no knowledge other than that which could be found in myself or else in the great book of the world, I spent the rest of my youth traveling, visiting courts and armies, mixing with people of diverse temperaments and ranks, gathering various experiences, testing myself in the situations which fortune offered me, and at all times reflecting upon whatever came my way so as to derive some profit from it (Descartes, ''Discourse on the Method'').</blockquote>
  
Descartes is often regarded as the first modern thinker to provide a philosophical framework for the [[natural sciences]] as these began to develop. In his ''Meditations on First Philosophy'' he attempts to arrive at a fundamental set of principles that one can know as true without any doubt. To achieve this, he employs a method called [[methodological skepticism]], or [[hyperbolic doubt]]: he denies any claim to be true that can at any time or in the least bit be doubted.  Descartes himself likens this to a bushel of apples.  If you find one rotten apple in the bushel, you must throw them all out first and then inspect the rest one by one to see if they've been ruined by this first rotten apple.
+
On November 10, 1618, while walking through [[Breda]], Descartes met [[Isaac Beeckman]], who sparked his interest in mathematics and the new physics, particularly the problem of the fall of heavy bodies. On November 10, 1619, while traveling in Germany and thinking about using mathematics to solve problems in physics, Descartes had a dream through which he "discovered the foundations of a marvelous science."<ref>Encyclopedia Britannica, [http://www.1911encyclopedia.org/Rene_Descartes René Descartes.] Retrieved August 15, 2007.</ref> This became a pivotal point in young Descartes's life and the foundation on which he developed analytic geometry. He dedicated the rest of his life to researching this connection between mathematics and nature. Descartes also studied [[Augustine of Hippo|St. Augustine's]] concept of [[free will]], the belief that human will is essentially equal to God's will; that is, that humans are naturally independent of God's will.
  
 +
In 1622, he returned to [[France]], and during the next few years spent time in Paris and other parts of Europe. He arrived in La Haye in 1623, selling all of his property, investing this remuneration in [[Bond (finance)|bonds]] which provided Descartes with a comfortable income for the rest of his life. Descartes was present at the [[siege of La Rochelle]] by Cardinal [[Armand Jean du Plessis, Cardinal Richelieu|Richelieu]] in 1627. He left for [[Holland]] in 1628, where he lived and changed his address frequently until 1649. Despite this, he managed to revolutionize mathematics and philosophy.
  
Descartes' methodological doubt is not arbitrary though.  Descartes was educated in a time when what had been considered infallibly/absolutely true, namely in physics and astronomy, was now demonstrated to be completely false.  The principal case of this being that the [[geocentric view]] of the solar system originating from [[Ptolemy]] was now debunked in favor of the [[heliocentric view]].  In other words, after approximately fifteen-hundred years of believing the Sun and other planets revolved around the Earth, it was discovered by [[Nicolaus Copernicus]] and further promulgated by [[Galileo Galilei]] that in fact, the Earth revolved around the Sun as did all other planets.  Further findings by Copernicus also dealt a blow to the accepted Aristotelian physics of the time, and especially the hylomorphic view of form and matter.  To say the least, this was very disturbing for the academic community and Descartes is very much a product of this disturbance.  This is why Descartes pursues his methodological doubt; if the new [[natural sciences]] are to succeed, they must be built on a foundation that would never break as it did for the previous views in the [[natural sciences]].  Descartes wants science's theoretical claims to not just work, but also be true infallibly, so that fifteen-hundred years in the future man would not find out he was mistaken.  Therefore, Descartes' rotten apple is the geocentric view of the solar system and Aristotelian physics.
+
In 1633, [[Galileo Galilei|Galileo]] was condemned by the [[Roman Catholic Church]], and Descartes abandoned plans to publish ''[[The World (Descartes)|Treatise on the World]],'' his work of the previous four years.
  
====First Meditation====
+
''Discourse on the Method'' was published in 1637. In it an early attempt at explaining reflexes mechanistically is made, although Descartes's theory is later proven wrong within his lifetime.
The reason Descartes' doubt goes further than just scientific claims in his ''Meditations on First Philosophy,'' is that if he and the world could have been wrong about things that seemed so obvious and true (such as the sun revolving around the earth, which if we were to look at sunrise and sunset everyday makes fairly good sense), then he and the world could be wrong about a great deal more.
 
  
 +
Descartes continued to [[René Descartes#References|publish works]] concerning both mathematics and philosophy for the rest of his life. In 1643, Cartesian philosophy was condemned at the [[Utrecht University|University of Utrecht]], and Descartes began his long correspondence with [[Elisabeth of Bohemia, Princess Palatine|Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia]]. In 1647, he was awarded a pension by the [[King of France]]. Descartes was interviewed by [[Frans Burman]] at [[Egmond-Binnen]] in 1648.
  
He gives the example of dreaming: in a dream, one's senses perceive things that seem real, but do not actually exist. Some dreams are fantastic and we are quick to dismiss them as not possibly true. But, there are also dreams that are very realistic, in which nothing extraordinary happens, and it is in these cases that Descartes argues that we cannot distinguish between dreaming and reality. And, if we cannot distinguish between dreaming and reality, then how do we know when we are dreaming and when we are not?
+
René Descartes died on February 11, 1650, in [[Stockholm]], [[Sweden]], where he had been invited as a teacher for Queen [[Christina of Sweden]]. The cause of death was said to be [[pneumonia]]—accustomed to working in bed until noon, he may have suffered a detrimental effect on his health due to Christina's demands for early morning study (the lack of sleep could have severely compromised his immune system). Others believe that Descartes may have contracted pneumonia as result of nursing a French ambassador, Dejion A. Nopeleen, ill with the aforementioned disease, back to health.<ref>Oregon State University [http://oregonstate.edu/instruct/phl302/philosophers/descartes.html Rene Descartes.] Retrieved May 20, 2007.</ref>
 +
In 1663, the [[Pope Alexander VII|Pope]] placed his works on the [[Index Librorum Prohibitorum|Index of Prohibited Books]].
  
 +
As a [[Roman Catholic]] in a [[Protestant]] nation, he was interred in a graveyard mainly used for unbaptized infants in [[Adolf Fredrikskyrkan]] in Stockholm. Later, his remains were taken to France and buried in the church of [[Sainte-Geneviève-du-Mont]] in [[Paris]]. His memorial erected in the eighteenth century remains in the Swedish church.
  
Descartes' doubt goes even further though, as he explains that even in dreams two plus two equals four.  Therefore, what if there were some malicious, omnipotent demon whose whole purpose was to deceive me in everything I perceive or think. If we suppose this demon to exist, then we cannot even know if two plus two equals four since the demon could even be deceiving us about this.  And, for Descartes, we must suppose this demon to exist, otherwise we have not thrown out all of the rotten apples from the bushel.
+
During the [[French Revolution]], his remains were disinterred for burial in the [[Panthéon, Paris|Panthéon]] among the great French thinkers. The village in the [[Loire Valley]] where he was born was renamed ''La Haye—Descartes'' in 1802, which was shortened to "Descartes" in 1967. Currently his tomb is in the church of [[Saint-Germain-des-Prés]] in Paris, except for his cranium, which is in the [[Musée de l'Homme]].
  
 +
== Philosophical work==
 +
Descartes is often regarded as the first modern thinker to provide a philosophical framework for the [[natural sciences]] as they began to develop. He attempts to arrive at a fundamental set of principles that one can know as true without any doubt. To achieve this, he employs a method called methodological skepticism: he rejects any idea that can be doubted, and then reestablishes them in order to acquire a firm foundation for genuine knowledge.<ref>Rebecca Copenhaver, [http://www.lclark.edu/~rebeccac/forms.html Forms of skeptisism.] Retrieved June 6, 2008.</ref>
 +
Initially, Descartes arrives at only a single principle: Thought exists. Thought cannot be separated from the thinker, therefore, the thinker exists (''Discourse on the Method'' and ''Principles of Philosophy''). Most famously, this is known as ''[[cogito ergo sum]]'' (Latin: "I think, therefore I am"), or more aptly, "''[[Dubito, ergo cogito, ergo sum]]''" (Latin: "I doubt, therefore I think, therefore I am"). Therefore, Descartes concluded, if he doubted, then something or someone must be doing the doubting, therefore the very fact that he doubted proved his existence.<ref>''The British Journal of Psychiatry,'' [http://bjp.rcpsych.org/cgi/content/full/181/3/258Ten books: Chosen by Raj Persaud.] Retrieved November 4, 2007.</ref>
  
Another way to interpret Descartes' call upon the malicious demon is that Descartes is trying to argue that our very human nature may be constructed in such a way that even in such seemingly obvious things as simple math, we err.
+
[[Image:DescartesMeditations.png|thumb|240px|Cover of Meditationes written by René Descartes]]
 +
Descartes concludes that he can be certain that he exists because he thinks. But in what form? He perceives his body through the use of the senses; however, these have previously been proven unreliable. So Descartes concludes that the only indubitable knowledge is that he is a ''thinking thing''. Thinking is his essence as it is the only thing about him that cannot be doubted. Descartes defines "thought" ''(cogitatio)'' as "what happens in me such that I am immediately conscious of it, insofar as I am conscious of it." Thinking is, thus, every activity of a person of which he is immediately [[Consciousness|conscious]].
  
 +
To further demonstrate the limitations of the senses, Descartes proceeds with what is known as the ''Wax Argument''. He considers a piece of wax: His senses inform him that it has certain characteristics, such as shape, texture, size, color, smell, and so forth. When he brings the wax towards a flame, these characteristics change completely. However, it seems that it is still the same thing: It is still a piece of wax, even though the data of the senses inform him that all of its characteristics are different. Therefore, in order to properly grasp the nature of the wax, he cannot use the senses: He must use his mind. Descartes concludes:
  
Descartes' ultimate goal then, is to move from this doubt into an infallible foundation of knowledge if it is at all possible.  In doing so, he must eliminate the possibility that we are being deceived by a malicious demon (or that our nature is such that it is given to error), that we cannot distinguish between dreaming and being awake, and that we have within us the power to avoid future error while accepting only truth.
+
<blockquote>
 +
Thus what I thought I had seen with my eyes, I actually grasped solely with the faculty of judgment, which is in my mind.</blockquote>
  
====Second Meditation====
+
In this manner, Descartes proceeds to construct a system of knowledge, discarding [[perception]] as unreliable and instead admitting only [[deductive reasoning|deduction]] as a method. In the third and fifth ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy|Meditation]],'' he offers an [[ontological proof]] of a [[benevolent]] [[God]] (through both the [[ontological argument]] and [[trademark argument]]). Because God is benevolent, he can have some faith in the account of reality his senses provide him, for God has provided him with a working mind and [[sensory system]] and does not desire to deceive him; however, this is a contentious argument, as his very notion of a benevolent God from which he developed this argument is easily subject to the same kind of doubt as his perceptions. From this supposition, however, he finally establishes the possibility of acquiring knowledge about the world based on deduction ''and'' perception. In terms of [[epistemology]] therefore, he can be said to have contributed such ideas as a rigorous conception of [[foundationalism]] and the possibility that [[reason]] is the only reliable method of attaining knowledge.
After all of this doubt in the first ''Meditation'' Descartes arrives at a single principle: if I am being deceived, then surely "I" must exist. Literally, he writes, "I am; I exist—this is certain." The more commonly known phrasing is the Latin, ''cogito ergo sum,'' ("I think, therefore I am").  This formulation though is from the ''Discourse on Method'' and should not be utilized when considering the ''Meditations.''
 
  
 +
In Descartes's system, knowledge takes the form of ideas, and philosophical investigation is the contemplation of these ideas. This concept would influence subsequent [[internalism|internalist]] movements, as Descartes's epistemology requires that a connection made by conscious awareness will distinguish knowledge from falsity. As a result of his Cartesian doubt, he sought for knowledge to be "incapable of being destroyed," in order to construct an unshakable ground upon which all other knowledge can be based. The first item of unshakable knowledge that Descartes argues for is the aforementioned ''cogito,'' or thinking thing.
  
The reason Descartes finds this idea indubitable is because even if there were a malicious demon deceiving me at every step, the "me," or "I," must exist at all of those steps in order to be deceived.  In the very process of doubting everything, including whether I exist or not, I must affirm that "I" exist, or else there would be no doubting even going on.  Therefore, Descartes concludes that he can be certain that he exists. But in what form?
+
Descartes also wrote a response to [[External world skepticism#Motivations for external world skepticism|skepticism about the existence of the external world]]. He argues that [[sensory perception]]s come to him involuntarily, and are not willed by him. They are external to his senses, and according to Descartes, this is evidence of the existence of something outside of his mind, and thus, an external world. Descartes goes on to show that the things in the external world are material by arguing that God would not deceive him as to the ideas that are being transmitted, and that God has given him the "propensity" to believe that such ideas are caused by material things.
  
 +
== Dualism ==
 +
Descartes suggested that the body works like a [[machine]], that it has the material properties of extension and motion, and that it follows the laws of physics. The [[mind]] (or [[soul]]), on the other hand, was described as a nonmaterial entity that lacks extension and motion, and does not follow the laws of physics. Descartes argued that only humans have minds, and that the mind interacts with the body at the [[pineal gland]]. This form of [[dualism]] proposes that the mind controls the body, but that the body can also influence the otherwise rational mind, such as when people act out of passion. Most of the previous accounts of the relationship between mind and body had been uni-directional.
  
Descartes looks at his hands and body and decides that at this point he cannot conclude that he is these things, as he perceives he has hands and a body through the senses and these are still doubtable. Descartes only wants to claim knowledge of what he can clearly and distinctly understand.  And, at this point, since his senses are doubtful, he concludes only that he is a thinking thing. A thing that, "...doubts, understands, affirms, denies, wills, refuses, and that also imagines and senses" (AT 28). [[thought|Thinking]] is his essence as it is the only thing about him that cannot be doubted.
+
Descartes suggested that the pineal gland is "the seat of the soul" for several reasons. First, the soul is unitary, and unlike many areas of the brain the pineal gland appears to be unitary (microscopic inspection reveals it is formed of two hemispheres). Second, Descartes observed that the pineal gland was located near the [[ventricular system|ventricles]]. He believed the [[cerebrospinal fluid|animal spirits]] of the ventricles acted through the nerves to control the body, and that the pineal gland influenced this process. Finally, Descartes incorrectly believed that only humans have pineal glands, just as, in his view, only humans have minds. This led him to the belief that animals cannot feel pain, and Descartes's practice of [[vivisection]] (the dissection of live animals) became widely practiced throughout Europe until the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]].
  
 +
Cartesian dualism set the agenda for philosophical discussion of the [[mind-body problem]] for many years after Descartes's death. The question of how a nonmaterial mind can influence a material body, without invoking supernatural explanations, remains an [[enigma]] to this day.
  
It may seem curious at this point, but Descartes proceeds in his second 'Meditation' with a consideration of a piece of wax.  Descartes' senses inform him that it has certain characteristics, such as shape, texture, size, color, smell, and so forth. However, when he brings the wax towards a flame, these characteristics change completely.  However, it seems that it is still the same thing: it is still a piece of wax, even though the data of the senses inform him that all of its characteristics are different.  Furthermore, hypothetically speaking then, the wax could exhibit an almost infinite number of characteristics that my imagination could never come up with (especially concerning size and shape).  This means that regardless of whether Descartes really is holding any wax, he can clearly and distinctly perceive it insomuch as it is an extended thing which is understood by the mind.  In other words, in order to properly grasp the nature of the wax, he cannot use the senses: he must use his mind. Descartes concludes:
+
Modern scientists have criticized Cartesian dualism, as well as its influence on subsequent philosophers.
:"Thus what I thought I had seen with my eyes, I actually grasped solely with the faculty of judgment, which is in my mind" (AT 31).
 
  
 +
== Mathematical legacy ==
 +
Descartes' theory provided the basis for the [[calculus]] of [[Isaac Newton|Newton]] and [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]], by applying [[infinitesimal calculus]] to the [[tangent line problem]], thus permitting the evolution of that branch of modern mathematics.<ref>Jan Gullberg, ''Mathematics From The Birth Of Numbers'' (W. W. Norton, 1997, ISBN 0-393-04002-X).</ref> This appears even more astounding considering that the work was just intended as an ''example'' to his ''Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison, et chercher la verité dans les sciences'' (''Discourse on the Method to Rightly Conduct the Reason and Search for the Truth in Sciences,'' better known under the shortened title ''Discours de la méthode'').
  
As Descartes continues, he realizes that there is something unique about this extended "stuff": it is radically different than himself as a "thinking thing." At this point he does not call either a substance, but he has at least determined some essential differences between an extended thing and a thinking thing.  And, Descartes counts this towards helping him better know what "I" a "thinking thing" am, as "I" can now know what I am not.
+
[[Descartes' rule of signs]] is also a commonly used method in modern mathematics to determine possible quantities of positive and negative zeros of a function.
  
 +
Descartes invented [[analytic geometry]], and discovered the law of conservation of momentum. He outlined his views on the universe in his [[Principles of Philosophy]].
  
The idea that all material things are known through the mind and as extended things has a great impact on the scientific community as well, as it opens up the door for science to analyze "nature" in a mathematical way using the new [[Analytic Geometry]] Descartes helped formulate.  Furthermore, it serves as a ground for science, so that it can be considered indubitable, as ultimately all calculations and observances are known through the deductive process of the mind, and hence not left to chance. Descartes mentions none of this in the ''Meditations'', but as written earlier, this was always part of the goal in writing the ''Meditations''.
+
Descartes also made contributions to the field of [[optics]]. He showed by using geometric construction and the [[law of refraction]] (also known as Descartes's law) that the angular radius of a [[rainbow]] is 42 degrees (that is, the angle subtended at the eye by the edge of the rainbow and the ray passing from the sun through the rainbow's center is 42 °).<ref>P.A. Tipler and G. Mosca, ''Physics For Scientists And Engineers'' (W. H. Freeman, 2004, ISBN 0-7167-4389-2).</ref> He also independently discovered the [[law of reflection]], and his essay on optics was the first published mention of this law.<ref>Encarta, [http://encarta.msn.com/encyclopedia_761555262/Rene_Descartes.html#s3 René Descartes.] Retreieved August 15, 2007.</ref>
  
 +
One of Descartes' most enduring legacies was his development of [[Cartesian geometry]], the algebraic system taught in schools today. He also created [[exponential notation]], indicated by numbers written in what is now referred to as [[superscript]] (such as x²).
  
In this manner, Descartes proceeds to construct a system of knowledge, discarding [[perception]] as unreliable and instead admitting only [[deduction]] as a method. Halfway through the ''Meditations'', he also claims to prove the existence of a benevolent [[God]], who, being benevolent, has provided him with a working mind and [[sensory system]], and who cannot desire to deceive him, and thus, finally, he establishes the possibility of acquiring knowledge about the world based on deduction <i>and</i> perception.
+
== Bibliography ==
 +
'''Collected works'''
 +
* 1983. ''Oeuvres de Descartes'' in 11 vols. Adam, Charles, and Tannery, Paul, eds. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin.
  
=== Mathematical legacy ===
+
'''Collected English translations'''
Rene Descartes said "Nature can be divined through numbers."
+
* 1988. ''The Philosophical Writings Of Descartes'' in 3 vols. Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R., Kenny, A., and Murdoch, D., trans. Cambridge University Press; vol 1, 1985, ISBN 978-0521288071; vol. 2, 1985, ISBN 978-0521288088; vol. 3, 1991, ISBN 978-0521423502)
 +
* 1988, ''Descartes Selected Philosophical Writings.'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988. ISBN 0521358124 ISBN 9780521358125 ISBN 0521352649 ISBN 9780521352642.
  
[[mathematics | Mathematicians]] consider Descartes of the utmost importance for his discovery of analytic geometry. Up to Descartes's times, [[geometry]], dealing with lines and shapes, and [[algebra]], dealing with numbers, appeared as completely different subsets of mathematics. Descartes showed how to translate many problems in geometry into problems in algebra, by using a coordinate system to describe the problem.
+
'''Single works'''
 +
* 1618. ''Compendium Musicae''.
 +
* 1628. ''Rules for the Direction of the Mind''.
 +
* 1630–1633. ''Le Monde'' ([[The World (Descartes)|''The World'']]) and ''L'Homme'' ''(Man)''. Descartes's first systematic presentation of his natural philosophy. ''Man'' was first published in Latin translation in 1662; ''The World'' in 1664.
 +
* 1637. ''[[Discourse on the Method]]'' ("Discours de la Methode"). An introduction to ''Dioptrique'', ''Des Météores'' and ''La Géométrie''. Original in French, because intended for a wider public.
 +
* 1637. ''[[La Géométrie]]''. Smith, David E., and Lantham, M. L., trans., 1954. ''The Geometry of René Descartes''. Dover.
 +
* 1641. ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]]''. Cottingham, J., trans., 1996. Cambridge University Press. Latin original. Alternative English title: ''Metaphysical Meditations''. Includes six ''Objections and Replies''. A second edition published the following year, includes an additional ‘’Objection and Reply’’ and a ''Letter to Dinet''. [http://www.wright.edu/cola/descartes/intro.html HTML Online Latin-French-English Edition]
 +
* 1644. ''Les Principes de la philosophie''. Miller, V. R. and R. P., trans., 1983. ''Principles of Philosophy''. Reidel.
 +
* 1647. ''Comments on a Certain Broadsheet''.
 +
* 1647. ''[[The Description of the Human Body]]''.
 +
* 1648. ''Conversation with Burman''.
 +
* 1649. ''[[Passions of the Soul]]''. Voss, S. H., trans., 1989. Indianapolis: Hackett. Dedicated to Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia.
 +
* 1657. ''Correspondence''. Published by Descartes's literary executor Claude Clerselier. The third edition, in 1667, was the most complete; Clerselier omitted, however, much of the material pertaining to mathematics.
  
Descartes's theory provided the basis for the calculus of [[Isaac Newton|Newton]] and [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]], by applying [[infinitesimal calculus]] to the [[tangent problem]], thus permitting the evolution of that branch of modern mathematics {{ref|tangent_problem}}. This appears even more astounding when one keeps in mind that the work was just intended as an ''example'' to his ''Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison, et chercher la verité dans les sciences'' (''Discourse on the Method to Rightly Conduct the Reason and Search for the Truth in Sciences'', known better under the shortened title ''Discours de la méthode'').
+
==Notes==
 +
<references/>
  
Descartes also made contributions in the field of [[Optics]], for instance, he showed by geometrical construction using the [[Law of Refraction]] that the angular radius of a rainbow is 42° (i.e. the angle subtended at the eye by the edge of the rainbow and the ray passing from the sun through the rainbow's centre is 42°). {{ref|rainbow}}
+
==References==
 
+
*Boyer, Carl. 1985. ''A History of Mathematics.'' Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-02391-3.  
== Writings by Descartes==
+
*Clarke, Desmond. 2006. ''Descartes: A Biography.'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-82301-3.
 
+
*Costabel, Pierre. 1987. ''René Descartes - Exercices pour les éléments des solides.'' Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. ISBN 2-13-040099-X 
* ''[[Discourse on Method]]'' (1637): an introduction to "Dioptrique', on the "Météores' and 'La Géométrie'; a work for the grand public, written in French.
+
*Cottingham, John. 1992. ''The Cambridge Companion to Descartes.'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-36696-8.
* ''[[La Géométrie]]'' (1637)
+
*Farrell, John. 2006. “Demons of Descartes and Hobbes.” In ''Paranoia and Modernity: Cervantes to Rousseau.'' Cornell University Press.  
* ''[[Meditations on First Philosophy]]'' (1641), also known as 'Metaphysic meditations', with  a series of six objections. This work was written in Latin, language of the learned.
+
*Garber, Daniel. 1992. ''Descartes's Metaphysical Physics.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-28219-8.
* ''Les Principes de la philosophie'' (1644), work rather destined for the students.  
+
*Garber, Daniel, and Michael Ayers. 1998. ''The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy.'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-53721-5.
* ''The Singing Epitaph'' (1646).
+
*Gaukroger, Stephen. 1995. ''Descartes: An Intellectual Biography.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-823994-7.  
 
+
*Grayling, A.C. 2005. ''Descartes: The Life and times of a Genius.'' New York: Walker Publishing Co., Inc. ISBN 0-8027-1501-X.  
== Trivia ==
+
*Keeling, S. V. 1968. ''Descartes.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press.  
 
+
*Melchert, Norman. 2002. ''The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy.'' New York: McGraw Hill. ISBN 0-19-517510-7.
It is claimed that during the 1640s Descartes travelled with an artificial female companion called Francine, named after his daughter.   This may be a myth linked with his statements about the nature of the [[mind]], or an early [[automaton]], or [[Gynoid]].
+
*Sorrell, Tom. 1987. ''Descartes.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-287636-8.
 
+
*Schäfer, Rainer. 2006. ''Zweifel und Sein—Der Ursprung des modernen Selbstbewusstseins in Descartes' cogito.'' Wuerzburg: Koenigshausen & Neumann. ISBN 3-8260-3202-0.
Descartes was ranked #49 on [[Michael H. Hart]]'s [[The 100|list of the most influential figures in history]].
 
 
 
== References ==
 
 
 
# {{note|tangent_problem}} {{Book reference|Author=Jan Gullberg|Year=1997|Title=Mathematics From The Birth Of Numbers|Publisher=W. W. Norton & Company|ID=ISBN 0-393-04002-X}}
 
# {{note|rainbow}} {{Book reference|Author=P A Tipler, G Mosca|Year=2004|Title=Physics For Scientists And Engineers Extended Version|Publisher=W H Freeman and Company|ID=ISBN 0-7167-4389-2}}
 
 
 
== See also ==
 
*[[Dualistic interactionism]]
 
*[[Baruch Spinoza]]
 
*[[3587 Descartes|Asteroid 3587 Descartes]], named after the philosopher
 
*[[Defect (geometry)]]
 
*[[Analytic geometry]]
 
*[[Cartesian coordinate system]]
 
  
 
== External links ==
 
== External links ==
 +
All links retrieved December 7, 2022.
 +
*[http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/04744b.htm CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: Rene Descartes].
 +
*[http://www.borishennig.de/texte/descartes/diss/cartes_04b.pdf Conscientia in Descartes].
  
{{wikiquote}}
 
{{wikisource author}}
 
 
*[http://www.shvoong.com/books/philosophy/55185-discourse-method/ A summary of his book "A Discourse On Method"]
 
* {{fr}} [http://www.incipitblog.com/index.php/2005/06/01/rene-descartes-discours-de-la-methode-1637/ French Audio Book (mp3)] : excerpt about animals/machines from Discourse On the Method
 
*[http://gutenberg.net/etext/59 Discourse On the Method] &ndash; at [[Project Gutenberg]]
 
*[http://gutenberg.net/etext/4391 Selections from the Principles of Philosophy] &ndash; at [[Project Gutenberg]]
 
*[http://www-groups.dcs.st-and.ac.uk/~history/Mathematicians/Descartes.html Detailed biography  of Descartes]
 
*[http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/04744b.htm CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: Rene Descartes]
 
*[http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/ READABLE versions of Descartes's Meditations and Discourse on the Method.]
 
*[http://www.borishennig.de/texte/descartes/diss/cartes_04b.pdf Conscientia in Descartes]
 
*[http://descartes.sourceforge.net/ descartes], an open source function plotter named after the inventor of Cartesian coordinates
 
*[http://www.biblioweb.org/-DESCARTES-Rene-.html Biography, Bibliography, Analysis] (in French)
 
 
*Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
 
*Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-epistemology/ Descartes' Epistemology]
+
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-epistemology/ Descartes' Epistemology].
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ethics/ Descartes' Ethics]
+
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ethics/ Descartes' Ethics].
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-works/ Descartes' Life and Works]
+
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-works/ Descartes' Life and Works].
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-modal/ Descartes' Modal Metaphysics]
+
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-modal/ Descartes' Modal Metaphysics].
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ontological/ Descartes' Ontological Argument]
+
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ontological/ Descartes' Ontological Argument].
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pineal-gland/ Descartes and the Pineal Gland]
+
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pineal-gland/ Descartes and the Pineal Gland].
 
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
 
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
 +
 +
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 +
[[Category:philosophy]]
 +
[[Category:Philosophers]]
 
{{Philosophy (navigation)}}
 
{{Philosophy (navigation)}}
 
+
{{Credit|Rene_Descartes|27529711|Rene_Descartes|168741837}}
[[Category:17th century mathematicians]]
 
[[Category:Christian philosophers]]
 
[[Category:French mathematicians]]
 
[[Category:French philosophers]]
 
[[Category:History of neuroscience]]
 
[[Category:Rationalists|Descartes, Rene]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[category:Philosophy]]
 
 
 
{{Credit|27529711}}
 

Latest revision as of 04:02, 8 December 2022

Western Philosophy
Seventeenth century philosophy
Descartes.jpg
Name: René Descartes
Birth: March 31, 1596
La Haye en Touraine [now Descartes], Indre-et-Loire, France
Death: February 11 1650 (aged 53)
Stockholm, Sweden
School/tradition: Cartesianism, Rationalism, Foundationalism
Main interests
Metaphysics, Epistemology, Science, Mathematics
Notable ideas
Cogito ergo sum, method of doubt, Cartesian coordinate system, Cartesian dualism, ontological argument for God's existence; regarded as a founder of Modern philosophy
Influences Influenced
Al-Ghazali, Plato, Aristotle, Anselm, Aquinas, Ockham, Suarez, Mersenne, Sextus Empiricus, Michel de Montaigne, Duns Scotus Spinoza, Hobbes, Arnauld, Malebranche, Pascal, Locke, Leibniz, More, Kant, Husserl, Brunschvicg, Žižek, Chomsky

René Descartes (French IPA: [ʁə'ne de'kaʁt]) (March 31, 1596 – February 11, 1650), also known as Renatus Cartesius (latinized form), was a highly influential French philosopher, mathematician, scientist, and writer. He has been dubbed the "Father of Modern Philosophy" and the "Father of Modern Mathematics," and much of subsequent Western philosophy is a reaction to his writings, which have been closely studied from his time through the present day. His influence in mathematics is also apparent; the Cartesian coordinate system that is used in plane geometry and algebra being named for him and he was one of the key figures in the Scientific Revolution.

Descartes frequently sets his views apart from those of his predecessors. In the opening section of the Passions of the Soul, a treatise on the Early Modern version of what are now commonly called emotions, he goes so far as to assert that he will write on his topic "as if no one had written on these matters before." Many elements of his philosophy have precedents in late Aristotelianism, the revived Stoicism of the sixteenth century, or in earlier philosophers like St. Augustine. In his natural philosophy, he differs from the Schools on two major points: First, he rejects the analysis of corporeal substance into matter and form; second, he rejects any appeal to ends—divine or natural—in explaining natural phenomena. In his theology, he insists on the absolute freedom of God’s act of creation.

Descartes was a major figure in seventeenth century continental rationalism, later advocated by Baruch Spinoza and Gottfried Leibniz, and opposed by the empiricist school of thought consisting of Hobbes, Locke, Berkeley, and Hume. Leibniz, Spinoza, and Descartes were all versed in mathematics as well as philosophy, and Descartes and Leibniz contributed greatly to science as well. As the inventor of the Cartesian coordinate system, Descartes founded analytic geometry, the bridge between algebra and geometry crucial to the invention of calculus and analysis. Descartes's reflections on mind and mechanism began the strain of western thought that much later, impelled by the invention of the electronic computer and by the possibility of machine intelligence, blossomed into the Turing test and related thought. His most famous statement is: Cogito ergo sum (French: Je pense, donc je suis; English: I think, therefore I am), found in §7 of part I of Principles of Philosophy (Latin) and in part IV of Discourse on the Method (French).

Biography

René Descartes with Queen Christina of Sweden.
Graduation registry for Descartes at the Collège Royal Henry-Le-Grand, La Flèche, 1616.
The tomb of Descartes (middle, with detail of the inscription), in the church of Saint-Germain-des-Prés, Paris.

Descartes was born in La Haye en Touraine (now Descartes), Indre-et-Loire, France. When he was one year old, his mother Jeanne Brochard died of tuberculosis. His father Joachim was a judge in the High Court of Justice. At the age of eleven, he entered the Jesuit Collège Royal Henry-Le-Grand at La Flèche. After graduation, he studied at the University of Poitiers, earning a Baccalauréat and License in law in 1616, in accordance with his father's wishes that he should become a lawyer.

Descartes never actually practiced law, however, and in 1618, during the Thirty Years' War, he entered the service of Maurice of Nassau, leader of the United Provinces of the Netherlands. His reason for becoming a mercenary was to see the world and to discover the truth.

I entirely abandoned the study of letters. Resolving to seek no knowledge other than that which could be found in myself or else in the great book of the world, I spent the rest of my youth traveling, visiting courts and armies, mixing with people of diverse temperaments and ranks, gathering various experiences, testing myself in the situations which fortune offered me, and at all times reflecting upon whatever came my way so as to derive some profit from it (Descartes, Discourse on the Method).

On November 10, 1618, while walking through Breda, Descartes met Isaac Beeckman, who sparked his interest in mathematics and the new physics, particularly the problem of the fall of heavy bodies. On November 10, 1619, while traveling in Germany and thinking about using mathematics to solve problems in physics, Descartes had a dream through which he "discovered the foundations of a marvelous science."[1] This became a pivotal point in young Descartes's life and the foundation on which he developed analytic geometry. He dedicated the rest of his life to researching this connection between mathematics and nature. Descartes also studied St. Augustine's concept of free will, the belief that human will is essentially equal to God's will; that is, that humans are naturally independent of God's will.

In 1622, he returned to France, and during the next few years spent time in Paris and other parts of Europe. He arrived in La Haye in 1623, selling all of his property, investing this remuneration in bonds which provided Descartes with a comfortable income for the rest of his life. Descartes was present at the siege of La Rochelle by Cardinal Richelieu in 1627. He left for Holland in 1628, where he lived and changed his address frequently until 1649. Despite this, he managed to revolutionize mathematics and philosophy.

In 1633, Galileo was condemned by the Roman Catholic Church, and Descartes abandoned plans to publish Treatise on the World, his work of the previous four years.

Discourse on the Method was published in 1637. In it an early attempt at explaining reflexes mechanistically is made, although Descartes's theory is later proven wrong within his lifetime.

Descartes continued to publish works concerning both mathematics and philosophy for the rest of his life. In 1643, Cartesian philosophy was condemned at the University of Utrecht, and Descartes began his long correspondence with Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia. In 1647, he was awarded a pension by the King of France. Descartes was interviewed by Frans Burman at Egmond-Binnen in 1648.

René Descartes died on February 11, 1650, in Stockholm, Sweden, where he had been invited as a teacher for Queen Christina of Sweden. The cause of death was said to be pneumonia—accustomed to working in bed until noon, he may have suffered a detrimental effect on his health due to Christina's demands for early morning study (the lack of sleep could have severely compromised his immune system). Others believe that Descartes may have contracted pneumonia as result of nursing a French ambassador, Dejion A. Nopeleen, ill with the aforementioned disease, back to health.[2] In 1663, the Pope placed his works on the Index of Prohibited Books.

As a Roman Catholic in a Protestant nation, he was interred in a graveyard mainly used for unbaptized infants in Adolf Fredrikskyrkan in Stockholm. Later, his remains were taken to France and buried in the church of Sainte-Geneviève-du-Mont in Paris. His memorial erected in the eighteenth century remains in the Swedish church.

During the French Revolution, his remains were disinterred for burial in the Panthéon among the great French thinkers. The village in the Loire Valley where he was born was renamed La Haye—Descartes in 1802, which was shortened to "Descartes" in 1967. Currently his tomb is in the church of Saint-Germain-des-Prés in Paris, except for his cranium, which is in the Musée de l'Homme.

Philosophical work

Descartes is often regarded as the first modern thinker to provide a philosophical framework for the natural sciences as they began to develop. He attempts to arrive at a fundamental set of principles that one can know as true without any doubt. To achieve this, he employs a method called methodological skepticism: he rejects any idea that can be doubted, and then reestablishes them in order to acquire a firm foundation for genuine knowledge.[3] Initially, Descartes arrives at only a single principle: Thought exists. Thought cannot be separated from the thinker, therefore, the thinker exists (Discourse on the Method and Principles of Philosophy). Most famously, this is known as cogito ergo sum (Latin: "I think, therefore I am"), or more aptly, "Dubito, ergo cogito, ergo sum" (Latin: "I doubt, therefore I think, therefore I am"). Therefore, Descartes concluded, if he doubted, then something or someone must be doing the doubting, therefore the very fact that he doubted proved his existence.[4]

Cover of Meditationes written by René Descartes

Descartes concludes that he can be certain that he exists because he thinks. But in what form? He perceives his body through the use of the senses; however, these have previously been proven unreliable. So Descartes concludes that the only indubitable knowledge is that he is a thinking thing. Thinking is his essence as it is the only thing about him that cannot be doubted. Descartes defines "thought" (cogitatio) as "what happens in me such that I am immediately conscious of it, insofar as I am conscious of it." Thinking is, thus, every activity of a person of which he is immediately conscious.

To further demonstrate the limitations of the senses, Descartes proceeds with what is known as the Wax Argument. He considers a piece of wax: His senses inform him that it has certain characteristics, such as shape, texture, size, color, smell, and so forth. When he brings the wax towards a flame, these characteristics change completely. However, it seems that it is still the same thing: It is still a piece of wax, even though the data of the senses inform him that all of its characteristics are different. Therefore, in order to properly grasp the nature of the wax, he cannot use the senses: He must use his mind. Descartes concludes:

Thus what I thought I had seen with my eyes, I actually grasped solely with the faculty of judgment, which is in my mind.

In this manner, Descartes proceeds to construct a system of knowledge, discarding perception as unreliable and instead admitting only deduction as a method. In the third and fifth Meditation, he offers an ontological proof of a benevolent God (through both the ontological argument and trademark argument). Because God is benevolent, he can have some faith in the account of reality his senses provide him, for God has provided him with a working mind and sensory system and does not desire to deceive him; however, this is a contentious argument, as his very notion of a benevolent God from which he developed this argument is easily subject to the same kind of doubt as his perceptions. From this supposition, however, he finally establishes the possibility of acquiring knowledge about the world based on deduction and perception. In terms of epistemology therefore, he can be said to have contributed such ideas as a rigorous conception of foundationalism and the possibility that reason is the only reliable method of attaining knowledge.

In Descartes's system, knowledge takes the form of ideas, and philosophical investigation is the contemplation of these ideas. This concept would influence subsequent internalist movements, as Descartes's epistemology requires that a connection made by conscious awareness will distinguish knowledge from falsity. As a result of his Cartesian doubt, he sought for knowledge to be "incapable of being destroyed," in order to construct an unshakable ground upon which all other knowledge can be based. The first item of unshakable knowledge that Descartes argues for is the aforementioned cogito, or thinking thing.

Descartes also wrote a response to skepticism about the existence of the external world. He argues that sensory perceptions come to him involuntarily, and are not willed by him. They are external to his senses, and according to Descartes, this is evidence of the existence of something outside of his mind, and thus, an external world. Descartes goes on to show that the things in the external world are material by arguing that God would not deceive him as to the ideas that are being transmitted, and that God has given him the "propensity" to believe that such ideas are caused by material things.

Dualism

Descartes suggested that the body works like a machine, that it has the material properties of extension and motion, and that it follows the laws of physics. The mind (or soul), on the other hand, was described as a nonmaterial entity that lacks extension and motion, and does not follow the laws of physics. Descartes argued that only humans have minds, and that the mind interacts with the body at the pineal gland. This form of dualism proposes that the mind controls the body, but that the body can also influence the otherwise rational mind, such as when people act out of passion. Most of the previous accounts of the relationship between mind and body had been uni-directional.

Descartes suggested that the pineal gland is "the seat of the soul" for several reasons. First, the soul is unitary, and unlike many areas of the brain the pineal gland appears to be unitary (microscopic inspection reveals it is formed of two hemispheres). Second, Descartes observed that the pineal gland was located near the ventricles. He believed the animal spirits of the ventricles acted through the nerves to control the body, and that the pineal gland influenced this process. Finally, Descartes incorrectly believed that only humans have pineal glands, just as, in his view, only humans have minds. This led him to the belief that animals cannot feel pain, and Descartes's practice of vivisection (the dissection of live animals) became widely practiced throughout Europe until the Enlightenment.

Cartesian dualism set the agenda for philosophical discussion of the mind-body problem for many years after Descartes's death. The question of how a nonmaterial mind can influence a material body, without invoking supernatural explanations, remains an enigma to this day.

Modern scientists have criticized Cartesian dualism, as well as its influence on subsequent philosophers.

Mathematical legacy

Descartes' theory provided the basis for the calculus of Newton and Leibniz, by applying infinitesimal calculus to the tangent line problem, thus permitting the evolution of that branch of modern mathematics.[5] This appears even more astounding considering that the work was just intended as an example to his Discours de la méthode pour bien conduire sa raison, et chercher la verité dans les sciences (Discourse on the Method to Rightly Conduct the Reason and Search for the Truth in Sciences, better known under the shortened title Discours de la méthode).

Descartes' rule of signs is also a commonly used method in modern mathematics to determine possible quantities of positive and negative zeros of a function.

Descartes invented analytic geometry, and discovered the law of conservation of momentum. He outlined his views on the universe in his Principles of Philosophy.

Descartes also made contributions to the field of optics. He showed by using geometric construction and the law of refraction (also known as Descartes's law) that the angular radius of a rainbow is 42 degrees (that is, the angle subtended at the eye by the edge of the rainbow and the ray passing from the sun through the rainbow's center is 42 °).[6] He also independently discovered the law of reflection, and his essay on optics was the first published mention of this law.[7]

One of Descartes' most enduring legacies was his development of Cartesian geometry, the algebraic system taught in schools today. He also created exponential notation, indicated by numbers written in what is now referred to as superscript (such as x²).

Bibliography

Collected works

  • 1983. Oeuvres de Descartes in 11 vols. Adam, Charles, and Tannery, Paul, eds. Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin.

Collected English translations

Single works

  • 1618. Compendium Musicae.
  • 1628. Rules for the Direction of the Mind.
  • 1630–1633. Le Monde (The World) and L'Homme (Man). Descartes's first systematic presentation of his natural philosophy. Man was first published in Latin translation in 1662; The World in 1664.
  • 1637. Discourse on the Method ("Discours de la Methode"). An introduction to Dioptrique, Des Météores and La Géométrie. Original in French, because intended for a wider public.
  • 1637. La Géométrie. Smith, David E., and Lantham, M. L., trans., 1954. The Geometry of René Descartes. Dover.
  • 1641. Meditations on First Philosophy. Cottingham, J., trans., 1996. Cambridge University Press. Latin original. Alternative English title: Metaphysical Meditations. Includes six Objections and Replies. A second edition published the following year, includes an additional ‘’Objection and Reply’’ and a Letter to Dinet. HTML Online Latin-French-English Edition
  • 1644. Les Principes de la philosophie. Miller, V. R. and R. P., trans., 1983. Principles of Philosophy. Reidel.
  • 1647. Comments on a Certain Broadsheet.
  • 1647. The Description of the Human Body.
  • 1648. Conversation with Burman.
  • 1649. Passions of the Soul. Voss, S. H., trans., 1989. Indianapolis: Hackett. Dedicated to Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia.
  • 1657. Correspondence. Published by Descartes's literary executor Claude Clerselier. The third edition, in 1667, was the most complete; Clerselier omitted, however, much of the material pertaining to mathematics.

Notes

  1. Encyclopedia Britannica, René Descartes. Retrieved August 15, 2007.
  2. Oregon State University Rene Descartes. Retrieved May 20, 2007.
  3. Rebecca Copenhaver, Forms of skeptisism. Retrieved June 6, 2008.
  4. The British Journal of Psychiatry, books: Chosen by Raj Persaud. Retrieved November 4, 2007.
  5. Jan Gullberg, Mathematics From The Birth Of Numbers (W. W. Norton, 1997, ISBN 0-393-04002-X).
  6. P.A. Tipler and G. Mosca, Physics For Scientists And Engineers (W. H. Freeman, 2004, ISBN 0-7167-4389-2).
  7. Encarta, René Descartes. Retreieved August 15, 2007.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Boyer, Carl. 1985. A History of Mathematics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-02391-3.
  • Clarke, Desmond. 2006. Descartes: A Biography. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-82301-3.
  • Costabel, Pierre. 1987. René Descartes - Exercices pour les éléments des solides. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France. ISBN 2-13-040099-X
  • Cottingham, John. 1992. The Cambridge Companion to Descartes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-36696-8.
  • Farrell, John. 2006. “Demons of Descartes and Hobbes.” In Paranoia and Modernity: Cervantes to Rousseau. Cornell University Press.
  • Garber, Daniel. 1992. Descartes's Metaphysical Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-28219-8.
  • Garber, Daniel, and Michael Ayers. 1998. The Cambridge History of Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-53721-5.
  • Gaukroger, Stephen. 1995. Descartes: An Intellectual Biography. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-823994-7.
  • Grayling, A.C. 2005. Descartes: The Life and times of a Genius. New York: Walker Publishing Co., Inc. ISBN 0-8027-1501-X.
  • Keeling, S. V. 1968. Descartes. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Melchert, Norman. 2002. The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. New York: McGraw Hill. ISBN 0-19-517510-7.
  • Sorrell, Tom. 1987. Descartes. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-287636-8.
  • Schäfer, Rainer. 2006. Zweifel und Sein—Der Ursprung des modernen Selbstbewusstseins in Descartes' cogito. Wuerzburg: Koenigshausen & Neumann. ISBN 3-8260-3202-0.

External links

All links retrieved December 7, 2022.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.