Difference between revisions of "Pre-Socratic philosophy" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
 
(18 intermediate revisions by 8 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
I am developing this article. —[[User:Keisuke Noda|Keisuke Noda]] 04:25, 6 Oct 2005 (UTC)
+
{{Copyedited}}{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{submitted}}
 +
[[Category:Public]]
 +
Pre-Socratics or '''pre-Socratic philosophers''' were the earliest Western philosophers, active during the fifth and sixth centuries <small>B.C.E.</small> in [[ancient Greece]]. These philosophers tried to discover [[principles]] that could uniformly, consistently, and comprehensively explain all natural phenomena and the events in human life without resorting to [[Mythology|mythology]]. They initiated a new method of explanation known as [[philosophy]] which has continued in use until the present day, and developed their thoughts primarily within the framework of [[cosmology]] and [[cosmogony]]. [[Socrates]] was a pivotal philosopher who shifted the central focus of philosophy from cosmology to ethics and morality. Although some of these earlier philosophers were contemporary with, or even younger than Socrates, they were considered pre-Socratics (or early Greek Philosophers) according to the classification defined by [[Aristotle]].
 +
{{toc}}
 +
The pre-Socratic style of thought is often called [[Natural philosophy|natural philosophy]], but their concept of nature was much broader than ours, encompassing spiritual and mythical as well as aesthetic and physical elements. They brought human thought to a new level of abstraction; raised a number of central questions of [[ontology]], which are still relevant today; and cultivated the human spirit so as to open our eyes to the eternal [[truth]]. Primary sources for their philosophical discourses have all been lost except in a fragmentary form, and the best source is Aristotle. Although Aristotle’s interpretation of their thought dominated for centuries, modern scholars have gone beyond Aristotle to identify the original and unique contributions of the pre-Socratics.
  
Western philosophy began with philosophers in [[Ancient Greece|ancient Greece]]. Those philosophers who opened the paths of philosophy before Socrates are in group called Pre-Socratics or Pre-Socratics philosophers. Some philosophers were contemporary to or after Socrates, but they are also included in the group, since they kept the same line of thought. Those thinkers tried to find the principle that can uniformly and consistently explain all phenomena in nature and events in human life without appealing to [[Mythology|mythology]]. Their style of though is often called [[Natural philosophy|natural philosophy]], but their concept of nature is much broader than ours. It encompasses ethical, spiritual, mythical, and cosmological elements as well as physical ones. Within their thoughts, we can find insights into the questions of  [[Metaphysics|metaphysics]]. Pre-Socratics are basically metaphysicians who inquire into the question of the principles of being.
+
== Studies of Pre-Socratics ==
  
== Studies on Pre-Socratics ==
+
The study of ancient thinkers is restricted by a lack of primary sources. Their original writings were lost and only fragments of their thoughts, words, and ideas have been preserved in the works of other authors. The main secondary sources are works by Aristotle, and his contemporary [[doxographers]] [[Theophrastus]], [[Plato]], [[Diogenes]], and [[Herodotus]]. These fragments have been gathered and indexed by H. Diels and W. Kranz in their ''Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker'', now the standard source for the writings of the pre-Socratics. This book introduced the term "pre-Socratics" which has come to be widely used among scholars of philosophy.
  
Works by twentieth century philosophers such as [[Heidegger]] and [[Werner Jaeger]] contributed to re-discover the significance of those ancient thinkers and the originality of their thoughts.
+
The characterization and assessment of pre-Socratics and their thought owes much to Aristotle. Aristotle attempted to establish a comprehensive thought system that could integrate the views of his predecessors. His vision of philosophy as an all-encompassing system of thought led him to evaluate their ideas. Aristotle classified pre-Socratics primarily based upon his [[Aristotle|theory of four causes]], setting a standard for the interpretation of pre-Socratic thought. Pre-Socratic insights that were not compatible with Aristotle’s framework of interpretation were simply left out. Works by twentieth century philosophers such as [[Heidegger]] and [[Werner Jaeger]] went beyond Aristotle and contributed to a rediscovery of the significance and the originality of pre-Socratic thought.  
  
Studies of ancient thinkers are restricted by lack of [[Sources, primary and seconday|primary sources]]. Their writings were lost and fragments of their thoughts, words, and ideas have been preserved in the works of other authors such as [[Aristotle]], [[Plato]], [[Diogenes]], and [[Herodotus]].
+
== Philosophy and Myth ==
  
Characterization and assessment of Pre-Socratics and their views owe much to Aristotle. Aristotle tried to establish a comprehensive and systematic thought that can integrate views of his predecessors. This vision for philosophy or a conception of philosophy as the comprehensive system of thought lead him to the needs of evaluating views of thinkers before him.
+
Prior to the appearance of philosophers, [[Mythology|myth]] explained the circumstances of human life. When people wondered about where they came from, why and how evil came into existence, why there was fortune and misfortune in life, and how they could attain peace and happiness, they found an answer in mythology.  
  
Based upon his [[Aristotle, Theory of Four Causes in|theories of four causes]], Aristotle placed Pre-Socratics as those who explained phenomena by means of a [[Aristotle, Theory of Four Causes in|material cause]].
+
In [[ancient Greece]], poets like [[Homer]] and [[Hesiod]] created mystic epics that explained the origin of the world, genealogy of the gods, the origin of evil, responsibility and punishment, destiny and chance, and life after death. Myth was the cradle of philosophy. In the process of distinguishing their thoughts from myths, pre-Socratics gradually developed their own style and form of knowledge. Pre-Socratic thought, however, still contained mythical elements and was expressed in poetry similar to that of Homer.  
  
Those fragments have been gathered and indexed by H. Diels and W. Kranz in their [[Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker]]. This is a current standard source for Pre-Socratics. The name "Pre-Socratics" came to be widely used among philosophical scholarships by this work.  
+
Philosopher means “lover of wisdom.” Ancient wise men, whom Aristotle called “those who speak about gods,” were certainly “lovers of wisdom.” They can, however, be distinguished from philosophers who seek to define [[Principle|principles]] by which they can uniformly, consistently, and comprehensively explain phenomena. Mythology is story telling based upon uncritical social beliefs and the arbitrary will of the gods; philosophy is an explanation based upon reason and principle. Aristotle distinguished “those who speak of gods” from philosophers, who tried to rationally justify their claims using self-examination, self-reflection, and a critical attitude.  
  
== Philosophy and Myth ==
+
[[Orphism]] was another major source of pre-Socratic philosophy. Orphics came into Greece in the sixth century <small>B.C.E.</small> bringing their [[cosmology]], a belief in [[reincarnation]], and an [[Asceticism|ascetic]] life style. They contributed to the development of pre-Socratic philosophy, particularly that of [[Pythagoras and Pythagoreans]]. Orpheusians’ belief in the immortality of soul and its reincarnation was transmitted through the Pythagoreans to Plato (see Plato’s works such as Gorgias, Phaidon, and Republic).
 +
 
 +
Among the pre-Socratics, [[Xenophanes]] made a unique contribution to Greek philosophy by developing a [[monotheism|monotheistic]] view of god. He criticized [[anthropomorphism|anthropomorphic]] views of gods in Greek mythology as mere projections of human culture and disqualified them. The Gods of Greek mythology committed all kinds of immoral acts including stealing, deception, and adultery. Xenophanes presented god as a single, eternal, and immutable ultimate reality. His view is not [[monism|monistic]] but [[monotheism|monotheistic]], and his philosophical orientation more [[Theology|theological]] than [[Metaphysics|metaphysical]], which distinguishes him from [[Parmenides]].
 +
 
 +
While Aristotle is correct in distinguishing between philosophy and mythology, we must also keep in mind their continuity. We can justify making a distinction between rational discourse and poetic and intuitive mythical discourse, with one qualification. We should note that insights and ideas from mythology exist in the philosophical discourses of post pre-Socratic philosophers such as Plato. As [[Husserl]] and [[Kierkegaard]] realized, one may hold certain beliefs underneath rational thinking. [[Nietzsche]] and [[Schopenhauer]] pointed out that, underneath rational discourse, human reason has unnoticed irrational drives.
 +
 
 +
The distinction between philosophy and mythology, reason and belief, and poetic intuition and critical reasoning can be justified only in a limited sense. While Pre-Socratics took a step towards rationality, elements of mythology were still running in their thoughts. The concept of pure and neutral rationality is an ideal of [[Philosophy, Modern|modern philosophy]] rather than a reality, and it met with serious objections during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Pre-Socratics exhibited a unique style of thought containing both rational and mythical elements.
 +
 
 +
== Phases of Pre-Socratic Philosophy: Approaches to the Question of Being ==
 +
 
 +
Pre-Socratics approached the question of being primarily using two sets of questions: first, whether the [[ultimate reality]] can be conceived of through a model based upon sensible element(s) or intelligible element(s); second, whether the ultimate reality is immutable or ever changing. This classification schema, however, is not exhaustive and some pre-Socratics (like the [[Sophists]]) were not metaphysicians. The term “pre-Socratics” does not designate any particular school or position, but simply all early Greek philosophers who were not under the influence of Socrates.
 +
 
 +
The first set of questions is whether the ultimate reality (ousia) is conceived of based on a model of sensible elements or one of intelligible elements; in other words, visible materialistic elements or invisible intelligible elements. Milesians and [[Pythagoras and Pythagoreans|Pythagoreans]] were divided by their response to this question. Earlier Milesians such as [[Thales]], [[Anaximander]], and [[Anaximenes]] approached being from a sensible or materialistic aspect, and Pythagoreans approached being from an intelligible or non-sensible aspect. This distinction between sensible and intelligible became the foundation for the distinction between matter and form, which Aristotle fully developed later on.
 +
 
 +
The second set of questions is the question of whether the ultimate reality (ousia) is [[Identity and Change|unchanging or changing]]. [[Heraclites]] conceived of being as an ever-changing process or becoming, and [[Parmenides]] conceived of being as unchanging or identical. The question of [[Being and Becoming|being and becoming]] has become one of the perennial questions in the history of philosophy.
 +
 
 +
The concepts of being and becoming and immutability and change posed questions to Greek thinkers. While the Parmenidean argument of being was logically appealing, the Heraclitian view of the change and diversity of phenomena was experientially undeniable.
 +
[[Pluralism|Pluralists]] and [[Atomists]] responded differently to this question. Pluralists such as [[Empedocles]] and [[Anaxagoras]] identified the essence of being with a number of immutable elements and explained changes by their combinations. Atomists such as [[Leucippus]] and [[Democritus]] identified the unchanging being with countless numbers of small indivisible elements called [[Atom|atoms]] (means “indivisible”) and explained changes by their combinations and movements.
 +
 
 +
[[Sophists]], professional [[Rhetoric|rhetoricians]], who were described by Plato in his dialogues, are customarily included with the pre-Socratics.
 +
 
 +
== The Milesians and the Pythagoreans ==
 +
 
 +
=== The Milesians: Inquiry into the Principles of Being ===
 +
 
 +
The birthplace of Greek philosophy is [[Ionia]] in [[Asia Minor]]. The earliest Greek thinkers lived in cities such as Miletus, Colophon, and Ephesus in this area. [[Thales]], [[Anaximander]], and [[Anaximenes]] are grouped together as “the Milesians.” These thinkers sought the [[Principle|ultimate principle]] which governs all phenomena in the element or elements of nature. For this reason, they are often called [[Philosophy, Natural|natural philosophers]]. This nomenclature, however, needs to be carefully understood.
 +
 
 +
The Milesians did not try to find laws of nature or basic elements in nature as modern natural scientists do. Their concern was to find the ultimate principle that governs all beings and phenomena. Their inquiry was [[Metaphysics|metaphysical]] in the sense that it was directed towards the discovery of the principles of being. This stance of inquiry into ultimate principles distinguishes them from the attitude of natural scientists, who are trying to find the laws and mechanisms of nature.
 +
 
 +
The Milesians conceived of the world as one. In spite of the diverse appearances of phenomena, they thought that there was one unique being which was the [[ultimate reality]] and that all phenomenal diversity was its manifestation. In the background of their thought, there is a distinction between [[Phenomena|appearance]] and [[Essence|essence]], and [[Phenomena|phenomena]] and [[Reality|ultimate reality (ousia)]].
 +
 
 +
=== Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes ===
  
Prior to an appearance of philosophers, there were [[Mythology|myth]]. When people wonder about the cause and reason of fortune and misfortune in life, where they are from, why and how evil came into the world, and how they can attain peace and happiness, they found explanation in mythology. Those who talked about gods were in a sense “lovers of wisdom”(philosopher) as Aristotle called them.
+
[[Thales]] of Miletus (c. 624 - 546 <small>B.C.E.</small>) is known as the first philosopher. This view was established by [[Aristotle]] who called Thales the “father of philosophy”(Metaphysics 1:3, 983 b20). Thales identified the ultimate reality (ousia) with “water.” Like other thinkers of antiquity, he did not consider “water” to be a pure physical chemical compound. Water carried a sense of mystery and divinity. To put it another way, Thales conceived of the ultimate reality, which in itself has divine characteristics such as [[Oneness|oneness]], indestructibility, immutability, [[Origin|originality]], as a sensible and visible element.
  
In [[Ancient Greece|ancient Greece]], [[Homer]] and[[Hesiod]] explained the origin of the world, genealogy of gods, the origin of evil, responsibilities and punishments, destiny and chance, and a life after death. They answered to those fundamental philosophical questions which have been lingering even today in a form of mystic poetic [[Philosophy of language|lanuages]].  
+
Other thinkers identified the ultimate reality with different material elements. [[Anaximander]](c. 610 - 545 <small>B.C.E.</small>) of [[Miletus]] identified it with the “boundless” or “undefined”(to Apeiron). [[Anaximenes]](c. 585 - 528 <small>B.C.E.</small>) of Miletus equated it with “air.” As noted earlier, these material elements should not be understood within the context of modern science. Philosophers of antiquity thought within more mystic frameworks. Characteristics common to these material elements such as water, undefined matter, and air are flexibility, a lack of specific forms and shapes, and the potential of taking various forms and shapes.  
  
[[Orpheus|Orphics]] came into Greece in sixth century. They brought its own [[cosmology]], a belief for [[reincarnation]], and [[Asceticism|ascetic]] life style. Orpheusians’ belief for the immortality of soul and its reincarnation left traces in [[Plato, Works of|Plato’s works]] such as Gorgias, Phaidon, and Republic. Poetic intuition and mystic stories gave impacts on thinkers of the time.
+
=== Pythagoras and Pythagoreans ===
  
Ancient wise men, whom Aristotle called “those who speak about gods,” are certainly “lovers of wisdom” (philosopher). They are, however, distinguished from [[Philosophy|philosophers]] for the reason that philosophers tried to find the [[Principle|principles]] by which they can uniformly and consistently explain phenomena. While mythology is a story-telling based upon uncritical social beliefs, philosophy is an explanation based upon reason and the principle. Aristotle distinguished philosophers from “those who speak of gods” for the reason that philosophers tried to give rational justification for their claim based upon self-examining, self-reflective, and critical attitude.
+
[[Pythagoras and pythagoreans|Pythagoras]] was born in Ionia, moved to southern Italy, and formed a religious group. His followers were called Pythagoreans and lived an ascetic life. Pythagoreans believed in the transmigration of souls, probably through the influence of Orphism.
  
To distinguish rational discourse from poetic and mythical intuitive discourse may be justifiable with a qualification. We should notice that insights and ideas in mythology have been living in philosophical discourses as we can see in Plato’s works. It raises a question of [[rationality]], a question of how rational is rational discourse is. As [[Husserl]] and [[Kierkegaard]] realized, one may hold certain belief underneath rational thinking. As [[Nietzsche]] and [[Shopenhauer]] pointed out, human reason has an unnoticed irrational drives underneath rational discourse.
+
While the Milesians defined the ultimate reality as something to de determined or understood, Pythagoreans used determining principles to define reality. For Pythagoreans, the principle of being is seen in what gives form and shape rather than what is formed and shaped. According to the terminology of Aristotle, Pythagoreans equated the principle with [[form]] as opposed to [[matter]]. Pythagoreans identified numbers as the unchanging, determining principle and found numerical harmony both in the cosmos and healthy human life. They developed a unique thought based upon the integration of the mathematical, the religious, the aesthetic, and the ethical. Various Pythagorean insights are found in Plato.
  
Distinction between philosophy and mythology, reason and belief, and poetic intuition and critical reasoning is justifiable only in a limited sense. While Pre-Socratics took a step of rationality, mythological elements are still running in their thoughts. We can find those elements in the philosophy of [[Plato]] as well. Concept of pure and neutral rationality is rather an idea and ideal of [[Philosophy, Modern|modern philosophy]] and it met serious objections in the nineteenth and twentieth century.
+
== Heraclitus and Eleatics ==
  
== Approaches to the Question of Being ==
+
Heraclitus conceived of being as a process or an event, and represented its essence as “fire.” Fire exists not as a stable object but as a process of burning. The moment it stops the process of changing, it ceases to exist. His well-known phrase, “No one can enter the same river again” expresses his thought that every being exists in the process of change. The river is already changing at the moment one steps into it. The water is moving past and the river bed is changing, and the river can never be the same as it was a moment ago.
  
Pre-Socratics approached to the question of being from two sets of perspectives. The fist set is the question of whether the [[Ultimate Reality|ultimate reality (ousia)]] is conceived of based on a model of sensible element or intelligible element, or to put in a general term, visible materialistic element or invisible intelligible element. Milesians and Pythagoreans were divided by their views for this question. Milesians approached being from sensible or materialistic aspect, and Pythagoreans approached being from intelligible or non-sensible aspect. This distinction of sensible and intelligible became a foundation for the distinction of matter and form, which Aristotle developed later in a full scale.
+
Parmenides held an opposite position. He separated phenomena [[appearance]] and [[essence]], and ascribed changes to matters of appearance. The world looks diverse and changes, but the essence is permanent, immutable, and eternal. Parmenides identified essence with being, and argued that we cannot even think without presupposing the existence and permanence of being; even the principle of changes must presuppose the existence of this principle itself. [[Zeno of Elea]] followed the path of Parmenides and presented a number of [[paradoxes]] such as [[Achilles and the Tortoise]].  
  
The second set is a question of whether [[Ultimate Reality|ultimate reality (ousia)]] is [[Identity and Change|unchanging or changing]]. [[Heraclites]] conceived being as ever changing process or becoming and [[Parmenides]] conceived it as unchanging or identical. The question of [[Being and Becoming|being and becoming]], [[Being and Becoming|being and process]] have become one of perennial questions in the history of philosophy.
+
Both Heraclites and Parmenides brought Greek philosophy to a higher level of abstraction and presented a number of central questions of ontology. They presented the task of reconciling two views on the question of existence: being and becoming, immutability and change, oneness and diversity. The Parmenidean view of the permanence and immutability of the ultimate reality was logically plausible. However, phenomena are apparently diverse and changing. Pluralists and atomists responded to this question differently.  
  
== The Milesians ==
+
== Pluralists and Atomists ==
  
=== Inquiry into the Principles of Being ===
+
[[Empedocles]] and [[Anaxagoras]] presented pluralist views. Empedocles identified the ultimate reality with four elements: air, water, fire, and earth. He defined these four elements as immutable and permanent, and explained changes and diversity by combinations of them. Anaxagoras, another pluralist, identified the ultimate reality with an infinite number of “seeds.”
  
Birthplace of Greek philosophy is [[Ionia]] in [[Asia minor]]. Earliest Greek thinkers lived in cities such as Miletus, Colophon, and Ephesus in this area. [[Thales]], [[Anaximander]], and [[Anaximenes]] are called in group the Milesians. Those thinkers identified the [[Principle|ultimate principle]] which govern all phenomena in an element or elements in nature. For this reason, they are often called [[Philosophy, Natural|natural philosophers]]. This naming, however, needs to be carefully understood.  
+
Leucippus and Democritus identified the ultimate reality with countless numbers of immutable, permanent elements called “atoms” and presented a purely mechanical materialism. Atoms were different in form, size, and shape but qualitatively identical. Quantitative differences and physical movements of atoms could explain all the qualitative diversity of the world, and mental and spiritual phenomena. These two philosophers reduced all phenomena to physical phenomena and presented a pure mechanical materialism, which was rare in Greek philosophy.  
  
The Milesians did not try to find laws of nature or basic element in nature as natural scientists do. Their concern is to find the ultimate principle that governs all beings and phenomena, not principles operating in nature. Their inquiry was [[Metaphysics|metaphysical]] in the sense that it was directed to the discovery of the principles of being. This stance of inquiry and concern for the ultimate principles distinguish themselves from an attitude of natural scientists who are trying to find laws and mechanism of nature.
+
== Sophists ==
  
The Milesians conceived the world as [[One|one]]. In spite of diverse appearances of phenomena, they thought that there was one identical being which is the [[ultimate reality]] and all phenomenal diversity is its manifestation. In the background of their thoughts, there is a distinction between [[Phenomena|appearance]] and [[Essence|essence]] or [[Phenomena|phenomena]] and [[Reality|ultimate reality (ousia)]].  
+
[[Sophists]], professional [[Rhetoric|rhetoricians]] contemporary to or younger than Socrates, are customarily included as Pre-Socratics. The term Sophists does not designate any particular individual but a group of professional teachers of rhetoric, active in the Greek political environment. Some explicitly presented [[moral relativism]] and a secularist concept of [[happiness]]. Socrates challenged them and Plato depicted their arguments in his dialogues.
  
=== Materiality of Being ===
+
== List of philosophers and schools==  
 +
The traditional corpus of pre-Socratic philosophers and movements (there are minor variations) is shown below:
  
[[Thales]] of Miletus (c. 624-546 B.C.) is known as the first philosopher. This view was established by [[Aristotle]] who called Thales as the “father of philosophy.([[Metaphysics]] vol. 1, Chap. 3, 983b20). Thales identified the ultimate reality (ousia) with “water.” Like other thinkers of antiquity, material is not pure physical chemical compound. It carries a sense of mystery and divinity. To put it in another way, Thales conceived the ultimate reality, which in itself has divine characters such as [[One|one]], indestructible, immutable, [[Origin|original]], in the world of sensible and visible.
+
* [[Milesians]]
 +
:[[Thales]] (c. 585 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Anaximander]] (610-547 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Anaximenes of Miletus]] (585-525 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Pythagoras and Pythagoreans]]
 +
:Pythagoras (582-496 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:Alcmaeon of Croton
 +
:Archytas (428-347 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Heraclitus]] (535-475 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Eleatics]]
 +
:[[Xenophanes]] (570-470 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Parmenides]] (510-440 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Zeno of Elea]] (490-430 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:Philolaus (480-405 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:Melissus of Samos (c. 470 <small>B.C.E.</small> - Unknown)
 +
*Pluralists
 +
:[[Empedocles]] (490-430 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Anaxagoras]] (500-428 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Atomism]]
 +
:[[Leucippus]] (fifth century <small>B.C.E.</small>, dates unknown)
 +
:[[Democritus]] (460-370 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Sophists]]
 +
:[[Protagoras]] (481-420 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Gorgias]] (483-375 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Thrasymachus]]
 +
:[[Callicles]]
 +
:[[Critias]]
 +
:Prodicus (c. 465-390 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Hippias]] (485-415 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:Antiphon (person) (480-411 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:Anonymous Iamblichi
 +
*Diogenes of Apollonia (c .460 <small>B.C.E.</small> - Unknown)
  
Other thinkers identified the ultimate reality with different material element. [[Anximander]](c. 610-545 B.C.E.) of [[Miletus]] identified it with the “boundless” or “undefined matter”(to Apeiron). [[Anaximenes]](c. 585-528 B.C.E.) of Miletus did it with “air.” As noted earlier, these material elements should not be understood within the contexts modern sciences. Philosophers of antiquity think within more mystic frameworks of thought. Common characteristics to these materialistic elements such as water, undefined matter, and air are flexibility and a lack of specific forms and shapes. They have a potential of taking various forms and shapes. They are in themselves what are to be determined, shaped, and formed.  Identifying what is undefined with the ultimate reality is a big step from a perspective to see phenomenal appearances as the sole reality.  
+
==Other groups==
 +
This list includes several men, particularly the [[Seven Sages of Greece|Seven Sages]], who appear to have been practical politicians and sources of epigrammatic wisdom, rather than speculative thinkers or [[philosophy|philosophers]] in the modern sense.
  
== The Pythagoreans ==
+
*[[Seven Sages of Greece]]
 +
:[[Solon]] (c. 594 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Chilon of Sparta]] (c. 560 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Thales]] (c. 585 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Bias of Priene]] (c. 570 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Cleobulus of Rhodes]] (c. 600 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Pittacus of Mitylene]] (c. 600 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
:[[Periander]] (625-585 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Aristeas]] of [[Proconessus]] (c. seventh century <small>B.C.E.</small>, dates unknown)
 +
*[[Pherecydes of Syros]] (c. 540 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Anacharsis]] (c. 590 <small>B.C.E.</small>)
 +
*[[Theano (mathematician)]] (c. fifth century <small>B.C.E.</small>, dates unknown)
  
While the Milesians identified the ultimate reality with what are to be determined, Pythagoreans identified it with determining principles or what determine others. With Pythagoreans, the principle of being is seen in what gives forms and shapes rather than what is formed and shaped. In the terminology of Aristotle, Pythagoreans identified the principle in the sense of arche or origin with form as opposed to matter.
+
==References==
 +
=== Texts ===
 +
*Diels, H. and Kranz, W. (eds). ''Die Fragmente der Vorsocratiker.'' Berlin: Weidmannsche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1960. (This is the standard text for pre-Socratics; abbr. DK)
 +
*Freeman, K. (ed). ''Ancilla to the pre-Socratic Philosophers.'' Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983. (A complete translation of the fragments in Diels and Kranz.)
  
=== Pythagoras ===
+
=== Others ===
  
Major thinker is [[Pythagoras]]. He was born in Ionia and moved to southern Italy. formed a religious group in southern Italy. Pythagoras
+
*Barnes, Jonathan. ''The Presocratic Philosophers'', vol. 1. London: Routledge, 1979.
 +
*Burnet, John. ''Early Greek Philosophy.'' New York: Meridian Books, 1957.
 +
*De Vogel, C.J. ''Greek Philosophy.'' Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1963.
 +
*Furley, David and R. E. Allen (eds). ''Studies in Presocratic Philosophy.'' New York: Humanities Press, 1970.
 +
*Hicks, R. D. ''Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers'', 2 vols. The Loeb Classical Library, 1925.
 +
*Kirk, G. S., Raven, J. E. and M. Schofield. ''The Presocratic Philosophers'', 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
 +
*Nahm, Milton C. ''Selections from Early Greek Philosophy.'' Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc., 1962.
  
== Heraclites and Eleatics ==
 
  
=== Heraclitus ===
+
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved November 30, 2022.
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/g/greekphi.htm Presocratics in Greek philosophy from The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/doxography-ancient/ Doxography of Ancient Philosophy from The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/320/320Lecture.html History of Ancient Philosophy by Prof. S. Marc Cohen, University of Washington]
 +
*[http://history.hanover.edu/project.php#ancient Ancient Texts in Hanover Historical Texts Project]
  
=== Eleatics ===
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
  
== Anaxagoras, Democritus, and Anaxagoras ==
 
  
 +
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
  
== Resources ==
+
{{Credit|44410237}}

Latest revision as of 22:19, 30 November 2022


Pre-Socratics or pre-Socratic philosophers were the earliest Western philosophers, active during the fifth and sixth centuries B.C.E. in ancient Greece. These philosophers tried to discover principles that could uniformly, consistently, and comprehensively explain all natural phenomena and the events in human life without resorting to mythology. They initiated a new method of explanation known as philosophy which has continued in use until the present day, and developed their thoughts primarily within the framework of cosmology and cosmogony. Socrates was a pivotal philosopher who shifted the central focus of philosophy from cosmology to ethics and morality. Although some of these earlier philosophers were contemporary with, or even younger than Socrates, they were considered pre-Socratics (or early Greek Philosophers) according to the classification defined by Aristotle.

The pre-Socratic style of thought is often called natural philosophy, but their concept of nature was much broader than ours, encompassing spiritual and mythical as well as aesthetic and physical elements. They brought human thought to a new level of abstraction; raised a number of central questions of ontology, which are still relevant today; and cultivated the human spirit so as to open our eyes to the eternal truth. Primary sources for their philosophical discourses have all been lost except in a fragmentary form, and the best source is Aristotle. Although Aristotle’s interpretation of their thought dominated for centuries, modern scholars have gone beyond Aristotle to identify the original and unique contributions of the pre-Socratics.

Studies of Pre-Socratics

The study of ancient thinkers is restricted by a lack of primary sources. Their original writings were lost and only fragments of their thoughts, words, and ideas have been preserved in the works of other authors. The main secondary sources are works by Aristotle, and his contemporary doxographers Theophrastus, Plato, Diogenes, and Herodotus. These fragments have been gathered and indexed by H. Diels and W. Kranz in their Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, now the standard source for the writings of the pre-Socratics. This book introduced the term "pre-Socratics" which has come to be widely used among scholars of philosophy.

The characterization and assessment of pre-Socratics and their thought owes much to Aristotle. Aristotle attempted to establish a comprehensive thought system that could integrate the views of his predecessors. His vision of philosophy as an all-encompassing system of thought led him to evaluate their ideas. Aristotle classified pre-Socratics primarily based upon his theory of four causes, setting a standard for the interpretation of pre-Socratic thought. Pre-Socratic insights that were not compatible with Aristotle’s framework of interpretation were simply left out. Works by twentieth century philosophers such as Heidegger and Werner Jaeger went beyond Aristotle and contributed to a rediscovery of the significance and the originality of pre-Socratic thought.

Philosophy and Myth

Prior to the appearance of philosophers, myth explained the circumstances of human life. When people wondered about where they came from, why and how evil came into existence, why there was fortune and misfortune in life, and how they could attain peace and happiness, they found an answer in mythology.

In ancient Greece, poets like Homer and Hesiod created mystic epics that explained the origin of the world, genealogy of the gods, the origin of evil, responsibility and punishment, destiny and chance, and life after death. Myth was the cradle of philosophy. In the process of distinguishing their thoughts from myths, pre-Socratics gradually developed their own style and form of knowledge. Pre-Socratic thought, however, still contained mythical elements and was expressed in poetry similar to that of Homer.

Philosopher means “lover of wisdom.” Ancient wise men, whom Aristotle called “those who speak about gods,” were certainly “lovers of wisdom.” They can, however, be distinguished from philosophers who seek to define principles by which they can uniformly, consistently, and comprehensively explain phenomena. Mythology is story telling based upon uncritical social beliefs and the arbitrary will of the gods; philosophy is an explanation based upon reason and principle. Aristotle distinguished “those who speak of gods” from philosophers, who tried to rationally justify their claims using self-examination, self-reflection, and a critical attitude.

Orphism was another major source of pre-Socratic philosophy. Orphics came into Greece in the sixth century B.C.E. bringing their cosmology, a belief in reincarnation, and an ascetic life style. They contributed to the development of pre-Socratic philosophy, particularly that of Pythagoras and Pythagoreans. Orpheusians’ belief in the immortality of soul and its reincarnation was transmitted through the Pythagoreans to Plato (see Plato’s works such as Gorgias, Phaidon, and Republic).

Among the pre-Socratics, Xenophanes made a unique contribution to Greek philosophy by developing a monotheistic view of god. He criticized anthropomorphic views of gods in Greek mythology as mere projections of human culture and disqualified them. The Gods of Greek mythology committed all kinds of immoral acts including stealing, deception, and adultery. Xenophanes presented god as a single, eternal, and immutable ultimate reality. His view is not monistic but monotheistic, and his philosophical orientation more theological than metaphysical, which distinguishes him from Parmenides.

While Aristotle is correct in distinguishing between philosophy and mythology, we must also keep in mind their continuity. We can justify making a distinction between rational discourse and poetic and intuitive mythical discourse, with one qualification. We should note that insights and ideas from mythology exist in the philosophical discourses of post pre-Socratic philosophers such as Plato. As Husserl and Kierkegaard realized, one may hold certain beliefs underneath rational thinking. Nietzsche and Schopenhauer pointed out that, underneath rational discourse, human reason has unnoticed irrational drives.

The distinction between philosophy and mythology, reason and belief, and poetic intuition and critical reasoning can be justified only in a limited sense. While Pre-Socratics took a step towards rationality, elements of mythology were still running in their thoughts. The concept of pure and neutral rationality is an ideal of modern philosophy rather than a reality, and it met with serious objections during the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Pre-Socratics exhibited a unique style of thought containing both rational and mythical elements.

Phases of Pre-Socratic Philosophy: Approaches to the Question of Being

Pre-Socratics approached the question of being primarily using two sets of questions: first, whether the ultimate reality can be conceived of through a model based upon sensible element(s) or intelligible element(s); second, whether the ultimate reality is immutable or ever changing. This classification schema, however, is not exhaustive and some pre-Socratics (like the Sophists) were not metaphysicians. The term “pre-Socratics” does not designate any particular school or position, but simply all early Greek philosophers who were not under the influence of Socrates.

The first set of questions is whether the ultimate reality (ousia) is conceived of based on a model of sensible elements or one of intelligible elements; in other words, visible materialistic elements or invisible intelligible elements. Milesians and Pythagoreans were divided by their response to this question. Earlier Milesians such as Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes approached being from a sensible or materialistic aspect, and Pythagoreans approached being from an intelligible or non-sensible aspect. This distinction between sensible and intelligible became the foundation for the distinction between matter and form, which Aristotle fully developed later on.

The second set of questions is the question of whether the ultimate reality (ousia) is unchanging or changing. Heraclites conceived of being as an ever-changing process or becoming, and Parmenides conceived of being as unchanging or identical. The question of being and becoming has become one of the perennial questions in the history of philosophy.

The concepts of being and becoming and immutability and change posed questions to Greek thinkers. While the Parmenidean argument of being was logically appealing, the Heraclitian view of the change and diversity of phenomena was experientially undeniable. Pluralists and Atomists responded differently to this question. Pluralists such as Empedocles and Anaxagoras identified the essence of being with a number of immutable elements and explained changes by their combinations. Atomists such as Leucippus and Democritus identified the unchanging being with countless numbers of small indivisible elements called atoms (means “indivisible”) and explained changes by their combinations and movements.

Sophists, professional rhetoricians, who were described by Plato in his dialogues, are customarily included with the pre-Socratics.

The Milesians and the Pythagoreans

The Milesians: Inquiry into the Principles of Being

The birthplace of Greek philosophy is Ionia in Asia Minor. The earliest Greek thinkers lived in cities such as Miletus, Colophon, and Ephesus in this area. Thales, Anaximander, and Anaximenes are grouped together as “the Milesians.” These thinkers sought the ultimate principle which governs all phenomena in the element or elements of nature. For this reason, they are often called natural philosophers. This nomenclature, however, needs to be carefully understood.

The Milesians did not try to find laws of nature or basic elements in nature as modern natural scientists do. Their concern was to find the ultimate principle that governs all beings and phenomena. Their inquiry was metaphysical in the sense that it was directed towards the discovery of the principles of being. This stance of inquiry into ultimate principles distinguishes them from the attitude of natural scientists, who are trying to find the laws and mechanisms of nature.

The Milesians conceived of the world as one. In spite of the diverse appearances of phenomena, they thought that there was one unique being which was the ultimate reality and that all phenomenal diversity was its manifestation. In the background of their thought, there is a distinction between appearance and essence, and phenomena and ultimate reality (ousia).

Thales, Anaximander, Anaximenes

Thales of Miletus (c. 624 - 546 B.C.E.) is known as the first philosopher. This view was established by Aristotle who called Thales the “father of philosophy”(Metaphysics 1:3, 983 b20). Thales identified the ultimate reality (ousia) with “water.” Like other thinkers of antiquity, he did not consider “water” to be a pure physical chemical compound. Water carried a sense of mystery and divinity. To put it another way, Thales conceived of the ultimate reality, which in itself has divine characteristics such as oneness, indestructibility, immutability, originality, as a sensible and visible element.

Other thinkers identified the ultimate reality with different material elements. Anaximander(c. 610 - 545 B.C.E.) of Miletus identified it with the “boundless” or “undefined”(to Apeiron). Anaximenes(c. 585 - 528 B.C.E.) of Miletus equated it with “air.” As noted earlier, these material elements should not be understood within the context of modern science. Philosophers of antiquity thought within more mystic frameworks. Characteristics common to these material elements such as water, undefined matter, and air are flexibility, a lack of specific forms and shapes, and the potential of taking various forms and shapes.

Pythagoras and Pythagoreans

Pythagoras was born in Ionia, moved to southern Italy, and formed a religious group. His followers were called Pythagoreans and lived an ascetic life. Pythagoreans believed in the transmigration of souls, probably through the influence of Orphism.

While the Milesians defined the ultimate reality as something to de determined or understood, Pythagoreans used determining principles to define reality. For Pythagoreans, the principle of being is seen in what gives form and shape rather than what is formed and shaped. According to the terminology of Aristotle, Pythagoreans equated the principle with form as opposed to matter. Pythagoreans identified numbers as the unchanging, determining principle and found numerical harmony both in the cosmos and healthy human life. They developed a unique thought based upon the integration of the mathematical, the religious, the aesthetic, and the ethical. Various Pythagorean insights are found in Plato.

Heraclitus and Eleatics

Heraclitus conceived of being as a process or an event, and represented its essence as “fire.” Fire exists not as a stable object but as a process of burning. The moment it stops the process of changing, it ceases to exist. His well-known phrase, “No one can enter the same river again” expresses his thought that every being exists in the process of change. The river is already changing at the moment one steps into it. The water is moving past and the river bed is changing, and the river can never be the same as it was a moment ago.

Parmenides held an opposite position. He separated phenomena appearance and essence, and ascribed changes to matters of appearance. The world looks diverse and changes, but the essence is permanent, immutable, and eternal. Parmenides identified essence with being, and argued that we cannot even think without presupposing the existence and permanence of being; even the principle of changes must presuppose the existence of this principle itself. Zeno of Elea followed the path of Parmenides and presented a number of paradoxes such as Achilles and the Tortoise.

Both Heraclites and Parmenides brought Greek philosophy to a higher level of abstraction and presented a number of central questions of ontology. They presented the task of reconciling two views on the question of existence: being and becoming, immutability and change, oneness and diversity. The Parmenidean view of the permanence and immutability of the ultimate reality was logically plausible. However, phenomena are apparently diverse and changing. Pluralists and atomists responded to this question differently.

Pluralists and Atomists

Empedocles and Anaxagoras presented pluralist views. Empedocles identified the ultimate reality with four elements: air, water, fire, and earth. He defined these four elements as immutable and permanent, and explained changes and diversity by combinations of them. Anaxagoras, another pluralist, identified the ultimate reality with an infinite number of “seeds.”

Leucippus and Democritus identified the ultimate reality with countless numbers of immutable, permanent elements called “atoms” and presented a purely mechanical materialism. Atoms were different in form, size, and shape but qualitatively identical. Quantitative differences and physical movements of atoms could explain all the qualitative diversity of the world, and mental and spiritual phenomena. These two philosophers reduced all phenomena to physical phenomena and presented a pure mechanical materialism, which was rare in Greek philosophy.

Sophists

Sophists, professional rhetoricians contemporary to or younger than Socrates, are customarily included as Pre-Socratics. The term Sophists does not designate any particular individual but a group of professional teachers of rhetoric, active in the Greek political environment. Some explicitly presented moral relativism and a secularist concept of happiness. Socrates challenged them and Plato depicted their arguments in his dialogues.

List of philosophers and schools

The traditional corpus of pre-Socratic philosophers and movements (there are minor variations) is shown below:

  • Milesians
Thales (c. 585 B.C.E.)
Anaximander (610-547 B.C.E.)
Anaximenes of Miletus (585-525 B.C.E.)
Pythagoras (582-496 B.C.E.)
Alcmaeon of Croton
Archytas (428-347 B.C.E.)
Xenophanes (570-470 B.C.E.)
Parmenides (510-440 B.C.E.)
Zeno of Elea (490-430 B.C.E.)
Philolaus (480-405 B.C.E.)
Melissus of Samos (c. 470 B.C.E. - Unknown)
  • Pluralists
Empedocles (490-430 B.C.E.)
Anaxagoras (500-428 B.C.E.)
Leucippus (fifth century B.C.E., dates unknown)
Democritus (460-370 B.C.E.)
Protagoras (481-420 B.C.E.)
Gorgias (483-375 B.C.E.)
Thrasymachus
Callicles
Critias
Prodicus (c. 465-390 B.C.E.)
Hippias (485-415 B.C.E.)
Antiphon (person) (480-411 B.C.E.)
Anonymous Iamblichi
  • Diogenes of Apollonia (c .460 B.C.E. - Unknown)

Other groups

This list includes several men, particularly the Seven Sages, who appear to have been practical politicians and sources of epigrammatic wisdom, rather than speculative thinkers or philosophers in the modern sense.

  • Seven Sages of Greece
Solon (c. 594 B.C.E.)
Chilon of Sparta (c. 560 B.C.E.)
Thales (c. 585 B.C.E.)
Bias of Priene (c. 570 B.C.E.)
Cleobulus of Rhodes (c. 600 B.C.E.)
Pittacus of Mitylene (c. 600 B.C.E.)
Periander (625-585 B.C.E.)
  • Aristeas of Proconessus (c. seventh century B.C.E., dates unknown)
  • Pherecydes of Syros (c. 540 B.C.E.)
  • Anacharsis (c. 590 B.C.E.)
  • Theano (mathematician) (c. fifth century B.C.E., dates unknown)

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

Texts

  • Diels, H. and Kranz, W. (eds). Die Fragmente der Vorsocratiker. Berlin: Weidmannsche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1960. (This is the standard text for pre-Socratics; abbr. DK)
  • Freeman, K. (ed). Ancilla to the pre-Socratic Philosophers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983. (A complete translation of the fragments in Diels and Kranz.)

Others

  • Barnes, Jonathan. The Presocratic Philosophers, vol. 1. London: Routledge, 1979.
  • Burnet, John. Early Greek Philosophy. New York: Meridian Books, 1957.
  • De Vogel, C.J. Greek Philosophy. Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1963.
  • Furley, David and R. E. Allen (eds). Studies in Presocratic Philosophy. New York: Humanities Press, 1970.
  • Hicks, R. D. Diogenes Laertius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 2 vols. The Loeb Classical Library, 1925.
  • Kirk, G. S., Raven, J. E. and M. Schofield. The Presocratic Philosophers, 2nd ed. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press, 1983.
  • Nahm, Milton C. Selections from Early Greek Philosophy. Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc., 1962.


External links

All links retrieved November 30, 2022.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.