Difference between revisions of "Being and Existence" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
(Import, Credit, Version Number)
 
(Apply tags)
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
{{Ready}}
 
{{For|the philosophical movement|Existentialism}}
 
{{For|the philosophical movement|Existentialism}}
 
{{For|the existence of god|Existence of God}}  
 
{{For|the existence of god|Existence of God}}  
Line 26: Line 27:
 
{{bquote|After conceiving things by our ideas, we compare these ideas and, finding that some belong together and others do not, we unite or separate them.  This is called affirming or denying, and in general judging.  
 
{{bquote|After conceiving things by our ideas, we compare these ideas and, finding that some belong together and others do not, we unite or separate them.  This is called affirming or denying, and in general judging.  
  
This judgment is also called a proposition, and it is easy to see that it must have two [[term]]s.  One term, of which one affirms or denies something, is called the [[subject (philosophy)|subject]]; the other term, which is affirmed or denied, is called the [[attribute]] or [[predicate (logic)|Praedicatum]].|x|x|Antoine Arnauld|''The Art of Thinking'' (''[[Port-Royal Logic]]''),(1662)  (translated J. Buroker 1996), Logic, II.3, page 82}}
+
This judgment is also called a proposition, and it is easy to see that it must have two [[term]]s.  One term, of which one affirms or denies something, is called the [[subject (philosophy)|subject]]; the other term, which is affirmed or denied, is called the [[attribute]] or [[predicate (logic)|Praedicatum]].|x|x|Antoine Arnauld|''The Art of Thinking'' ''([[Port-Royal Logic]])'',(1662)  (translated J. Buroker 1996), Logic, II.3, page 82}}
  
The two terms are joined by the verb "is" (or "is not", if the predicate is denied of the subject). Thus every proposition has three components: the two terms, and the "[[copula]]" that connects or separates them.  Even when the proposition has only two words, the three terms are still there.  For example "God loves humanity", really means "God is a lover of humanity", "God exists" means "God is a thing".
+
The two terms are joined by the verb "is" (or "is not," if the predicate is denied of the subject). Thus every proposition has three components: the two terms, and the "[[copula]]" that connects or separates them.  Even when the proposition has only two words, the three terms are still there.  For example "God loves humanity," really means "God is a lover of humanity," "God exists" means "God is a thing."
  
This theory of judgment dominated logic for centuries, but it has some obvious difficulties: it only considers proposition of the form "All A are B.", a form which logicians call [[universal quantifier|universal]].  It does not allow propositions of the form "Some A are B.", a form logicians call [[existential quantifier|existential]].  If neither A nor B includes the idea of existence, then "some A are B" simply adjoins A to B.  Conversely, if A or B do include the idea of existence in the way that "triangle" contains the idea "three angles equal to two right angles", then "A exists" is automatically true, and we have an [[ontological proof]] of A's existence.  (Indeed Arnauld's contemporary [[Descartes]] famously argued so, regarding the concept "God" (discourse 4,  Meditation 5). Arnauld's theory was current until the middle of the nineteenth century.  
+
This theory of judgment dominated logic for centuries, but it has some obvious difficulties: it only considers proposition of the form "All A are B.," a form which logicians call [[universal quantifier|universal]].  It does not allow propositions of the form "Some A are B.," a form logicians call [[existential quantifier|existential]].  If neither A nor B includes the idea of existence, then "some A are B" simply adjoins A to B.  Conversely, if A or B do include the idea of existence in the way that "triangle" contains the idea "three angles equal to two right angles," then "A exists" is automatically true, and we have an [[ontological proof]] of A's existence.  (Indeed Arnauld's contemporary [[Descartes]] famously argued so, regarding the concept "God" (discourse 4,  Meditation 5). Arnauld's theory was current until the middle of the nineteenth century.  
  
 
[[David Hume]] argued that the claim that a thing exists, when added to our notion of a thing, does not add anything to the concept.  For example, if we form a complete notion of Moses, and superadd to that notion the claim that Moses existed, we are not adding anything to the notion of Moses.
 
[[David Hume]] argued that the claim that a thing exists, when added to our notion of a thing, does not add anything to the concept.  For example, if we form a complete notion of Moses, and superadd to that notion the claim that Moses existed, we are not adding anything to the notion of Moses.
[[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] also argued that existence is not a "real" predicate, but gave no explanation of how this is possible, indeed his famous discussion of the subject is merely a restatement of Arnauld's doctrine that in the proposition "God is omnipotent", the verb "is" signifies the joining or separating of two concepts such as "God" and "omnipotence".
+
[[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] also argued that existence is not a "real" predicate, but gave no explanation of how this is possible, indeed his famous discussion of the subject is merely a restatement of Arnauld's doctrine that in the proposition "God is omnipotent," the verb "is" signifies the joining or separating of two concepts such as "God" and "omnipotence."
  
 
==Predicative nature of existence==  
 
==Predicative nature of existence==  
[[John Stuart Mill]] (and also Kant's pupil [[Johann Friedrich Herbart|Herbart]]) argued that the predicative nature of existence was proved by sentences like "A centaur is a poetic fiction" <ref>[[John Stuart Mill]], ''[[A System of Logic]]'', 1843 I. iv. 1.page 124</ref> or "A greatest number is impossible" (Herbart).<ref>''Uberweg'' (System of Logic) §68</ref> [[Franz Brentano]] challenged this, so also (as is better known) did [[Gottlob Frege|Frege]].  Brentano argued that we can join the concept represented by a noun phrase "an A" to the concept represented by an adjective "B" to give the concept represented by the noun phrase "a B-A". For example, we can join "a man" to "wise" to give "a wise man". But the noun phrase "a wise man" is not a sentence, whereas "some man is wise" is a sentence.  Hence the copula must do more than merely join or separate concepts.  Furthermore, adding "exists" to "a wise man", to give the complete sentence "a wise man exists" has the same effect as joining "some man" to "wise" using the copula.  So the copula has the same effect as "exists". Brentano argued that every categorical proposition can be translated into an existential one without change in meaning and that the "exists" and "does not exist" of the existential proposition take the place of the copula.  He showed this by the following examples:
+
[[John Stuart Mill]] (and also Kant's pupil [[Johann Friedrich Herbart|Herbart]]) argued that the predicative nature of existence was proved by sentences like "A centaur is a poetic fiction" <ref> John Stuart Mill, ''A System of Logic'' (London, Longmans, green, and co., 1884. OCLC 1261114)</ref> or "A greatest number is impossible" (Herbart). [[Franz Brentano]] challenged this, so also (as is better known) did [[Gottlob Frege|Frege]].  Brentano argued that we can join the concept represented by a noun phrase "an A" to the concept represented by an adjective "B" to give the concept represented by the noun phrase "a B-A."  For example, we can join "a man" to "wise" to give "a wise man."  But the noun phrase "a wise man" is not a sentence, whereas "some man is wise" is a sentence.  Hence the copula must do more than merely join or separate concepts.  Furthermore, adding "exists" to "a wise man," to give the complete sentence "a wise man exists" has the same effect as joining "some man" to "wise" using the copula.  So the copula has the same effect as "exists."  Brentano argued that every categorical proposition can be translated into an existential one without change in meaning and that the "exists" and "does not exist" of the existential proposition take the place of the copula.  He showed this by the following examples:
  
: The categorical proposition "Some man is sick", has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A sick man exists" or "There is a sick man".
+
: The categorical proposition "Some man is sick," has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A sick man exists" or "There is a sick man."  
  
: The categorical proposition "No stone is living" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A living stone does not exist" or "there is no living stone".
+
: The categorical proposition "No stone is living" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A living stone does not exist" or "there is no living stone."  
  
: The categorical proposition "All men are mortal" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "An immortal man does not exist" or "there is no immortal man".
+
: The categorical proposition "All men are mortal" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "An immortal man does not exist" or "there is no immortal man."  
  
: The categorical proposition "Some man is not learned" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A non-learned man exists" or "there is a non-learned man".
+
: The categorical proposition "Some man is not learned" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A non-learned man exists" or "there is a non-learned man."
  
Frege developed a similar view (though later) in his great work [[The Foundations of Arithmetic]], as did [[Charles Peirce]].  The Frege-Brentano view is the basis of the dominant position in [[Analytic philosophy|modern Anglo-American philosophy]]: that existence is asserted by the existential quantifier (as expressed by [[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine]]'s slogan "To be is to be the value of a variable." &mdash; ''On What There Is'', 1948).<ref>''On What There Is'' - in Review of Metaphysics (1948). Reprinted in [[Willard Van Orman Quine|W.V.O. Quine]], ''From a Logical Point of View'' (Harvard University Press, 1953)</ref>
+
Frege developed a similar view (though later) in his great work [[The Foundations of Arithmetic]], as did [[Charles Peirce]].  The Frege-Brentano view is the basis of the dominant position in [[Analytic philosophy|modern Anglo-American philosophy]]: that existence is asserted by the existential quantifier (as expressed by [[Willard Van Orman Quine|Quine]]'s slogan "To be is to be the value of a variable." &mdash; ''On What There Is'', 1948).<ref> W.V. Quine, ''On What There Is'' (Washington, D.C. : Catholic University of America, Philosophy Education Society, 1948, OCLC 43235388)</ref>
  
 
=== The semantics of existence ===  
 
=== The semantics of existence ===  
In [[mathematical logic]], there are two quantifiers, "some" and "all", though as [[Franz Brentano|Brentano]] (1838-1917) pointed out, we can make do with just one quantifier and negation.  The first of these quantifiers, "some" is also expressed as "there exists". Thus, in the sentence "There exist a man," the term "man" is asserted to be part of existence.  But we can also assert, "There exists a triangle."  Is a "triangle", an abstract idea, part of existence in the same way that a "man", a physical body, is part of existence?  Do  abstractions such as goodness, blindness, and virtue exist in the same sense that chairs, tables, and houses exist? What [[Categories (Aristotle)|categories]], or kinds of thing can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition?  
+
In [[mathematical logic]], there are two quantifiers, "some" and "all," though as [[Franz Brentano|Brentano]] (1838-1917) pointed out, we can make do with just one quantifier and negation.  The first of these quantifiers, "some" is also expressed as "there exists."  Thus, in the sentence "There exist a man," the term "man" is asserted to be part of existence.  But we can also assert, "There exists a triangle."  Is a "triangle," an abstract idea, part of existence in the same way that a "man," a physical body, is part of existence?  Do  abstractions such as goodness, blindness, and virtue exist in the same sense that chairs, tables, and houses exist? What [[Categories (Aristotle)|categories]], or kinds of thing can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition?  
  
Worse, does "existence" exist?<ref>[[Bertrand Russell]] - ''The Principles of Mathematics'' - New York, W. W. Norton & Company, 1903, second edition 1937 pages 449-450 : To exist is to have a specific relation to existence-a relation, by the way, which existence itself does not have.</ref>  
+
Worse, does "existence" exist?<ref>Bertrand Russell, ''The Principles of Mathematics'' (New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Co., 1938, OCLC 3778306)</ref>  
  
 
In some statements, existence is implied without being mentioned.  The statement "A bridge crosses the Thames at Hammersmith." cannot just be about a bridge, the Thames, and Hammersmith.  It must be about "existence" as well.  On the other hand, the statement "A bridge crosses the Styx at Limbo," has the same form, but while in the first case we understand a real bridge in the real world made of stone or brick, what "existence" would mean in the second case is less clear.
 
In some statements, existence is implied without being mentioned.  The statement "A bridge crosses the Thames at Hammersmith." cannot just be about a bridge, the Thames, and Hammersmith.  It must be about "existence" as well.  On the other hand, the statement "A bridge crosses the Styx at Limbo," has the same form, but while in the first case we understand a real bridge in the real world made of stone or brick, what "existence" would mean in the second case is less clear.
  
The [[nominalist]] approach is to argue that certain noun phrases can be "eliminated" by rewriting a sentence in a form that has the same meaning, but which does not contain the noun phrase.  Thus [[William of Ockham|Ockham]] argued that "Socrates has wisdom", which apparently asserts the existence of a reference for "wisdom", can be rewritten as "Socrates is wise", which contains only the referring phrase "Socrates". This method became widely accepted in the twentieth century by the [[Analytic philosophy|analytic school]] of philosophy.
+
The [[nominalist]] approach is to argue that certain noun phrases can be "eliminated" by rewriting a sentence in a form that has the same meaning, but which does not contain the noun phrase.  Thus [[William of Ockham|Ockham]] argued that "Socrates has wisdom," which apparently asserts the existence of a reference for "wisdom," can be rewritten as "Socrates is wise," which contains only the referring phrase "Socrates."  This method became widely accepted in the twentieth century by the [[Analytic philosophy|analytic school]] of philosophy.
  
However, this argument may be inverted by [[Philosophical realism|realists]] in arguing that since the sentence "Socrates is wise" can be rewritten as "Socrates has wisdom", this proves the existence of a hidden referent for "wise".
+
However, this argument may be inverted by [[Philosophical realism|realists]] in arguing that since the sentence "Socrates is wise" can be rewritten as "Socrates has wisdom," this proves the existence of a hidden referent for "wise."
  
 
A further problem is that human beings seem to process information about fictional characters in much the same way that they proceess information about real people.  For example, in the 2008 United States presidential election, a politician and actor named [[Fred Thompson]] ran for the office of president.  In polls, potential voters identified Fred Thompson as a "law and order" candidate.  Thompson plays a fictional character on the television series ''[[Law & Order franchise|Law and Order]]''.  There is no doubt that the people who make the comment are aware that ''Law and Order'' is fiction, but at some level, they process fiction as if it were fact.  Another example of this is the common experience of actresses who play the villain in a soap opera being accosted in public as if they are to blame for the actions of the character they play.
 
A further problem is that human beings seem to process information about fictional characters in much the same way that they proceess information about real people.  For example, in the 2008 United States presidential election, a politician and actor named [[Fred Thompson]] ran for the office of president.  In polls, potential voters identified Fred Thompson as a "law and order" candidate.  Thompson plays a fictional character on the television series ''[[Law & Order franchise|Law and Order]]''.  There is no doubt that the people who make the comment are aware that ''Law and Order'' is fiction, but at some level, they process fiction as if it were fact.  Another example of this is the common experience of actresses who play the villain in a soap opera being accosted in public as if they are to blame for the actions of the character they play.
  
A scientist might make a clear distinction about objects that exist, and assert that all objects that exist are made up of either matter or energy.  But in the layperson's [[worldview]], existence includes real, fictional, and even contradictory objects.  Thus if we reason from the statement ''[[Pegasus]] flies'' to the statement ''Pegasus exists'', we are not asserting that Pegasus is made up of atoms, but rather that Pegasus exists in a particular worldview, the worldview of classical myth.  When a mathematicians reasons from the statement "ABC is a triangle" to the statement "triangles exist", she is not asserting that triangles are made up of atoms but rather that triangles exist within a particular [[mathematical model]].
+
A scientist might make a clear distinction about objects that exist, and assert that all objects that exist are made up of either matter or energy.  But in the layperson's [[worldview]], existence includes real, fictional, and even contradictory objects.  Thus if we reason from the statement ''[[Pegasus]] flies'' to the statement ''Pegasus exists'', we are not asserting that Pegasus is made up of atoms, but rather that Pegasus exists in a particular worldview, the worldview of classical myth.  When a mathematicians reasons from the statement "ABC is a triangle" to the statement "triangles exist," she is not asserting that triangles are made up of atoms but rather that triangles exist within a particular [[mathematical model]].
  
 
==Modern approaches==
 
==Modern approaches==
Line 73: Line 74:
 
According to the "two sense" view of existence, which derives from [[Alexius Meinong]], existential statements fall into two classes.   
 
According to the "two sense" view of existence, which derives from [[Alexius Meinong]], existential statements fall into two classes.   
  
# Those asserting existence in a ''wide'' sense. These are typically of the form "N is P" for singular N, or "some S is P".  
+
# Those asserting existence in a ''wide'' sense. These are typically of the form "N is P" for singular N, or "some S is P."   
# Those asserting existence in a ''narrow'' sense. These are typically of the form "N exists" or "S's exist".
+
# Those asserting existence in a ''narrow'' sense. These are typically of the form "N exists" or "S's exist."
  
 
The problem is then evaded as follows.  "Pegasus flies" implies existence in the wide sense, for it implies that ''something'' flies.  But it does not imply existence in the narrow sense, for we deny existence in this sense by saying that Pegasus does not exist.  In effect, the world of all things divides, on this view, into those (like [[Socrates]], the planet [[Venus]], and New York City) that have existence in the narrow sense, and those (like [[Sherlock Holmes]], the goddess [[Venus (mythology)|Venus]], and [[Minas Tirith]]) that do not.
 
The problem is then evaded as follows.  "Pegasus flies" implies existence in the wide sense, for it implies that ''something'' flies.  But it does not imply existence in the narrow sense, for we deny existence in this sense by saying that Pegasus does not exist.  In effect, the world of all things divides, on this view, into those (like [[Socrates]], the planet [[Venus]], and New York City) that have existence in the narrow sense, and those (like [[Sherlock Holmes]], the goddess [[Venus (mythology)|Venus]], and [[Minas Tirith]]) that do not.
Line 83: Line 84:
 
Influenced by the views of Brentano's pupil [[Alexius Meinong]], and by [[Edmund Husserl]], Germanophone and Francophone philosophy took a different direction regarding the question of existence. [[Existentialism]] has been a major strand of [[continental philosophy]] in the twentieth century.
 
Influenced by the views of Brentano's pupil [[Alexius Meinong]], and by [[Edmund Husserl]], Germanophone and Francophone philosophy took a different direction regarding the question of existence. [[Existentialism]] has been a major strand of [[continental philosophy]] in the twentieth century.
  
==Endnotes==
+
==Notes==
 
<references/>
 
<references/>
 
== References==
 
* [[Antoine Arnauld]] and [[Pierre Nicole]] 'Logic', or ''The Art of Thinking'', (known as the ''[[Port-Royal Logic]]''), translated J. Buroker, Cambridge 1996
 
* [[John Stuart Mill|Mill, J.S.]], ''[[A System of Logic]]'', 8th edition 1908
 
* Loux, M., ''Ockham's Theory Of Terms'' (translation of book I of the ''Summa Logicae'' c-1327).
 
 
==Further reading==
 
* Plato, ''The Republic'', translated by Desmond Lee, Penguin Classics, 2003, ISBN 0140449140, ISBN-13: 978-0140449143
 
* Aristotle, ''The Metaphysics'', translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred, Penguin Classics, 1999, ISBN 0140446192, ISBN-13: 978-0140446197
 
* Heraclitus, ''Fragments'', James Hilton, forward, Brooks Hexton, translator, Penguin Classics, 2003, ISBN 0142437654, ISBN-13: 978-0142437650.
 
* ''The Meaning of Life'', Terry Eagleton, Oxford University Press, 2007, ISBN 0199210705 ISBN-13: 978-0199210701
 
* ''The Story of Philosophy'', Bryan Magee, Dorling Kindersley Lond. 1998, ISBN 0-7513-0590-1
 
  
 
== See also ==  
 
== See also ==  
Line 108: Line 97:
 
* [[Solipsism]]
 
* [[Solipsism]]
 
* [[Three marks of existence]]
 
* [[Three marks of existence]]
 +
 +
== References==
 +
*Arnauld, Antoine and Pierre Nicole. ''Logic, or, The art of thinking : containing, besides common rules, several new observations appropriate for forming judgment'', Cambridge [England] ; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN 0521482496
 +
*Mill, John Stuart ''A System of Logic'',London, Longmans, green, and co., 1884. OCLC 1261114
 +
*Loux, Michael J. ''Ockham's Theory Of Terms'' Notre Dame ; London : University of Notre Dame Press, 1974. ISBN 0268005508
 +
 +
==Further reading==
 +
* Plato, ''The Republic'', translated by Sir Henry Desmond Pritchard Lee. London ; New York : Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0140449140
 +
* Aristotle, ''The Metaphysics'', translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. London ; New York : Penguin Books, 1998. ISBN 0140446192
 +
* Heraclitus, ''Fragments'', translated by Brooks Hexton. New York : Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0142437654
 +
* Eagleton,Terry. ''The Meaning of Life''. Oxford ; New York : Oxford University Press, 2007. ISBN 0199210705
 +
* Magee, Bryan. ''The Story of Philosophy''. New York : DK Pub., 1998. ISBN 078943511X
  
 
== External links ==  
 
== External links ==  
 +
All links retrieved November 12, 2007.
 
{{wiktionary|existence}}
 
{{wiktionary|existence}}
 
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existence/ Existence] on the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
 
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existence/ Existence] on the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
Line 118: Line 120:
 
<!-- [[Category:Philosophy]] too general —>
 
<!-- [[Category:Philosophy]] too general —>
  
[[Category:Philosophical terminology]]
+
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
[[Category:Ontology]]
 
 
 
{{Link FA|eo}}
 
[[cs:Existence]]
 
[[de:Existenz]]
 
[[es:Existencia]]
 
[[eo:Ekzisto]]
 
[[fr:Existence]]
 
[[it:Esistenza]]
 
[[he:קיום]]
 
[[hu:A létező]]
 
[[nl:Bestaan]]
 
[[ja:存在]]
 
[[pl:Egzystencja]]
 
[[ru:Существование]]
 
[[simple:Existence]]
 
[[fi:Olemassaolo]]
 
[[sv:Existens]]
 
  
 
{{credit|170437594}}
 
{{credit|170437594}}

Revision as of 22:53, 12 November 2007


For the philosophical movement, see Existentialism.
For the existence of god, see Existence of God.

The study of existence is a branch of philosophy known as ontology.

Many questions arise concerning existence. For example: is what we experience and observe all there is to existence? Do abstract ideas, such as virtue, exist? Is existence orderly and knowable or chaotic and unknowable? Does there exist an external reality that is completely ontologically independent of our conceptual schemes, linguistic practices, and beliefs?

Plato, in the Republic, argued that existence was the world of ideas, and that our everyday lives are but dim shadows of this eternal reality. Aristotle considered that existence was made up of form and substance, and was discovered by the senses. Heraclitus said that existence is change. Descartes argued that we can be absolutely certain of the existence of our own conscious awareness.

Philosophers and mathematicians who study logic use the symbol ∃ to denote the existential quantifier, which asserts the existence of some object with certain properties.

Historical conceptions

In the Hindu philosophy, existence is only of one object called Brahma. All other forms of existence are manifestation of this unique reality Brahma, due to influence of an agency called Maya. To perceive the existence of the unique reality of Brahma, one has to learn to come out of the influence of Maya.

Existence can be seen as central to many systems of belief, religions, and myths. Beliefs concerning existence may posit additional properties, such as value or goodness. Divergent conceptions of existence have often resulted in tension amongst communities with differing beliefs about existence, especially when coupled with the related question of worldview.

In the western tradition of philosophy, the first comprehensive treatments of the subject are from Plato's Phaedo, Republic, and Statesman and Aristotle's Metaphysics, though earlier fragmentary writing exists. Aristotle developed a complicated theory of being, according to which only individual things, called substances fully have being, but other things such as relations, quantity, time and place (called the categories) have a derivative kind of being, dependent on individual things.

The Neo-Platonists and some early Christian philosophers argued about whether existence had any reality except in the mind of God. Some taught that existence was a snare and a delusion, that the world, the flesh, and the devil existed only to tempt weak humankind away from God.

The medieval philosopher Thomas Aquinas, perhaps following the Persian philosopher Avicenna, argued that God is pure being, and that in God essence and existence are the same. At about the same time, the nominalist philosopher William of Ockham, argued, in Book I of his Summa Totius Logicae (Treatise on all Logic, written some time before 1327) that Categories are not a form of Being in their own right, but derivative on the existence of individuals.

In early modern philosophy

The early modern treatment of the subject derives from Antoine Arnauld and Pierre Nicole's Logic, or 'The Art of Thinking', better known as the Port-Royal Logic, first published in 1662. Arnauld thought that a proposition or judgment, consists of taking two different ideas and either putting them together or rejecting them:

After conceiving things by our ideas, we compare these ideas and, finding that some belong together and others do not, we unite or separate them. This is called affirming or denying, and in general judging.

This judgment is also called a proposition, and it is easy to see that it must have two terms. One term, of which one affirms or denies something, is called the subject; the other term, which is affirmed or denied, is called the attribute or Praedicatum.

—Antoine Arnauld, The Art of Thinking (Port-Royal Logic),(1662) (translated J. Buroker 1996), Logic, II.3, page 82

The two terms are joined by the verb "is" (or "is not," if the predicate is denied of the subject). Thus every proposition has three components: the two terms, and the "copula" that connects or separates them. Even when the proposition has only two words, the three terms are still there. For example "God loves humanity," really means "God is a lover of humanity," "God exists" means "God is a thing."

This theory of judgment dominated logic for centuries, but it has some obvious difficulties: it only considers proposition of the form "All A are B.," a form which logicians call universal. It does not allow propositions of the form "Some A are B.," a form logicians call existential. If neither A nor B includes the idea of existence, then "some A are B" simply adjoins A to B. Conversely, if A or B do include the idea of existence in the way that "triangle" contains the idea "three angles equal to two right angles," then "A exists" is automatically true, and we have an ontological proof of A's existence. (Indeed Arnauld's contemporary Descartes famously argued so, regarding the concept "God" (discourse 4, Meditation 5). Arnauld's theory was current until the middle of the nineteenth century.

David Hume argued that the claim that a thing exists, when added to our notion of a thing, does not add anything to the concept. For example, if we form a complete notion of Moses, and superadd to that notion the claim that Moses existed, we are not adding anything to the notion of Moses. Kant also argued that existence is not a "real" predicate, but gave no explanation of how this is possible, indeed his famous discussion of the subject is merely a restatement of Arnauld's doctrine that in the proposition "God is omnipotent," the verb "is" signifies the joining or separating of two concepts such as "God" and "omnipotence."

Predicative nature of existence

John Stuart Mill (and also Kant's pupil Herbart) argued that the predicative nature of existence was proved by sentences like "A centaur is a poetic fiction" [1] or "A greatest number is impossible" (Herbart). Franz Brentano challenged this, so also (as is better known) did Frege. Brentano argued that we can join the concept represented by a noun phrase "an A" to the concept represented by an adjective "B" to give the concept represented by the noun phrase "a B-A." For example, we can join "a man" to "wise" to give "a wise man." But the noun phrase "a wise man" is not a sentence, whereas "some man is wise" is a sentence. Hence the copula must do more than merely join or separate concepts. Furthermore, adding "exists" to "a wise man," to give the complete sentence "a wise man exists" has the same effect as joining "some man" to "wise" using the copula. So the copula has the same effect as "exists." Brentano argued that every categorical proposition can be translated into an existential one without change in meaning and that the "exists" and "does not exist" of the existential proposition take the place of the copula. He showed this by the following examples:

The categorical proposition "Some man is sick," has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A sick man exists" or "There is a sick man."
The categorical proposition "No stone is living" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A living stone does not exist" or "there is no living stone."
The categorical proposition "All men are mortal" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "An immortal man does not exist" or "there is no immortal man."
The categorical proposition "Some man is not learned" has the same meaning as the existential proposition "A non-learned man exists" or "there is a non-learned man."

Frege developed a similar view (though later) in his great work The Foundations of Arithmetic, as did Charles Peirce. The Frege-Brentano view is the basis of the dominant position in modern Anglo-American philosophy: that existence is asserted by the existential quantifier (as expressed by Quine's slogan "To be is to be the value of a variable." — On What There Is, 1948).[2]

The semantics of existence

In mathematical logic, there are two quantifiers, "some" and "all," though as Brentano (1838-1917) pointed out, we can make do with just one quantifier and negation. The first of these quantifiers, "some" is also expressed as "there exists." Thus, in the sentence "There exist a man," the term "man" is asserted to be part of existence. But we can also assert, "There exists a triangle." Is a "triangle," an abstract idea, part of existence in the same way that a "man," a physical body, is part of existence? Do abstractions such as goodness, blindness, and virtue exist in the same sense that chairs, tables, and houses exist? What categories, or kinds of thing can be the subject or the predicate of a proposition?

Worse, does "existence" exist?[3]

In some statements, existence is implied without being mentioned. The statement "A bridge crosses the Thames at Hammersmith." cannot just be about a bridge, the Thames, and Hammersmith. It must be about "existence" as well. On the other hand, the statement "A bridge crosses the Styx at Limbo," has the same form, but while in the first case we understand a real bridge in the real world made of stone or brick, what "existence" would mean in the second case is less clear.

The nominalist approach is to argue that certain noun phrases can be "eliminated" by rewriting a sentence in a form that has the same meaning, but which does not contain the noun phrase. Thus Ockham argued that "Socrates has wisdom," which apparently asserts the existence of a reference for "wisdom," can be rewritten as "Socrates is wise," which contains only the referring phrase "Socrates." This method became widely accepted in the twentieth century by the analytic school of philosophy.

However, this argument may be inverted by realists in arguing that since the sentence "Socrates is wise" can be rewritten as "Socrates has wisdom," this proves the existence of a hidden referent for "wise."

A further problem is that human beings seem to process information about fictional characters in much the same way that they proceess information about real people. For example, in the 2008 United States presidential election, a politician and actor named Fred Thompson ran for the office of president. In polls, potential voters identified Fred Thompson as a "law and order" candidate. Thompson plays a fictional character on the television series Law and Order. There is no doubt that the people who make the comment are aware that Law and Order is fiction, but at some level, they process fiction as if it were fact. Another example of this is the common experience of actresses who play the villain in a soap opera being accosted in public as if they are to blame for the actions of the character they play.

A scientist might make a clear distinction about objects that exist, and assert that all objects that exist are made up of either matter or energy. But in the layperson's worldview, existence includes real, fictional, and even contradictory objects. Thus if we reason from the statement Pegasus flies to the statement Pegasus exists, we are not asserting that Pegasus is made up of atoms, but rather that Pegasus exists in a particular worldview, the worldview of classical myth. When a mathematicians reasons from the statement "ABC is a triangle" to the statement "triangles exist," she is not asserting that triangles are made up of atoms but rather that triangles exist within a particular mathematical model.

Modern approaches

According to Bertrand Russell's Theory of Descriptions, the negation operator in a singular sentence takes wide and narrow scope: we distinguish between "some S is not P" (where negation takes "narrow scope") and "it is not the case that 'some S is P'" (where negation takes "wide scope"). The problem with this view is that there appears to be no such scope distinction in the case of proper names. The sentences "Socrates is not bald" and "it is not the case that Socrates is bald" both appear to have the same meaning, and they both appear to assert or presuppose the existence of someone (Socrates) who is not bald, so that negation takes narrow scope.

The theory of descriptions has generally fallen into disrepute, though there have been recent attempts to revive it by Stephen Neale and Frank Jackson. According to the direct-reference view, an early version of which was originally proposed by Bertrand Russell, and perhaps earlier by Gottlob Frege, a proper name strictly has no meaning when there is no object to which it refers. This view relies on the argument that the semantic function of a proper name is to tell us which object bears the name, and thus to identify some object. But no object can be identified if none exists. Thus, a proper name must have a bearer if it is to be meaningful.

To adapt an argument of Peter Strawson's, someone who points to an apparently empty space, uttering "that's a fine red one" communicates nothing to someone who cannot see or understand what he is pointing to. Variants of the direct-reference view have been proposed by Saul Kripke, Gareth Evans, Nathan Salmon, Scott Soames, and others.

Existence in the wide and narrow senses

According to the "two sense" view of existence, which derives from Alexius Meinong, existential statements fall into two classes.

  1. Those asserting existence in a wide sense. These are typically of the form "N is P" for singular N, or "some S is P."
  2. Those asserting existence in a narrow sense. These are typically of the form "N exists" or "S's exist."

The problem is then evaded as follows. "Pegasus flies" implies existence in the wide sense, for it implies that something flies. But it does not imply existence in the narrow sense, for we deny existence in this sense by saying that Pegasus does not exist. In effect, the world of all things divides, on this view, into those (like Socrates, the planet Venus, and New York City) that have existence in the narrow sense, and those (like Sherlock Holmes, the goddess Venus, and Minas Tirith) that do not.

However, common sense suggests the non-existence of such things as fictional characters or places.

European views

Influenced by the views of Brentano's pupil Alexius Meinong, and by Edmund Husserl, Germanophone and Francophone philosophy took a different direction regarding the question of existence. Existentialism has been a major strand of continental philosophy in the twentieth century.

Notes

  1. John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic (London, Longmans, green, and co., 1884. OCLC 1261114)
  2. W.V. Quine, On What There Is (Washington, D.C. : Catholic University of America, Philosophy Education Society, 1948, OCLC 43235388)
  3. Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics (New York, NY: W.W. Norton & Co., 1938, OCLC 3778306)

See also

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Arnauld, Antoine and Pierre Nicole. Logic, or, The art of thinking : containing, besides common rules, several new observations appropriate for forming judgment, Cambridge [England] ; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, 1996. ISBN 0521482496
  • Mill, John Stuart A System of Logic,London, Longmans, green, and co., 1884. OCLC 1261114
  • Loux, Michael J. Ockham's Theory Of Terms Notre Dame ; London : University of Notre Dame Press, 1974. ISBN 0268005508

Further reading

  • Plato, The Republic, translated by Sir Henry Desmond Pritchard Lee. London ; New York : Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0140449140
  • Aristotle, The Metaphysics, translated by Hugh Lawson-Tancred. London ; New York : Penguin Books, 1998. ISBN 0140446192
  • Heraclitus, Fragments, translated by Brooks Hexton. New York : Penguin Books, 2003. ISBN 0142437654
  • Eagleton,Terry. The Meaning of Life. Oxford ; New York : Oxford University Press, 2007. ISBN 0199210705
  • Magee, Bryan. The Story of Philosophy. New York : DK Pub., 1998. ISBN 078943511X

External links

All links retrieved November 12, 2007.

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.