Difference between revisions of "Martin Heidegger" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
(replacing bio infobox with philosopher infobox)
m
Line 1: Line 1:
{{epname}}{{Infobox_Philosopher |
+
{{Infobox_Philosopher |
 
   <!-- Scroll down to edit this page —>
 
   <!-- Scroll down to edit this page —>
 
   <!-- Philosopher Category —>
 
   <!-- Philosopher Category —>
Line 20: Line 20:
 
   notable_ideas    = [[Dasein]], [[Gestell]] |
 
   notable_ideas    = [[Dasein]], [[Gestell]] |
 
}}
 
}}
 +
 
'''Martin Heidegger''' ([[September 26]], [[1889]] &ndash; [[May 26]], [[1976]]) was a [[Germany|German]] [[philosopher]].
 
'''Martin Heidegger''' ([[September 26]], [[1889]] &ndash; [[May 26]], [[1976]]) was a [[Germany|German]] [[philosopher]].
He studied at the [[Albert-Ludwigs-Universität|University of Freiburg]] under [[Edmund Husserl]], the founder of [[phenomenology]], and became a professor there in [[1928]]. He influenced many other major philosophers, and his own students at various times included [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]], [[Hans Jonas]], [[Emmanuel Levinas]], [[Hannah Arendt]], [[Leo Strauss]], [[Xavier Zubiri]] and [[Karl Löwith]]. [[Maurice Merleau-Ponty]], [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], [[Jacques Derrida]], [[Jean-Luc Nancy]], and [[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]] also studied his work more or less closely.  Beyond his relation to phenomenology, Heidegger is regarded as a major or indispensable influence on [[existentialism]], [[deconstruction]], [[hermeneutics]] and [[postmodernism]].  He attempted to reorient Western philosophy away from metaphysical and epistemological and toward [[ontology|ontological]] questions, that is, questions concerning the meaning [[being]], or what it means to be.
+
An influence on many other major philosophers, his own students at various times included [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]], [[Hans Jonas]], [[Emmanuel Levinas]], [[Hannah Arendt]], [[Xavier Zubiri]] and [[Karl Löwith]]. [[Maurice Merleau-Ponty]], [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], [[Jacques Derrida]], [[Michel Foucault]], [[Jean-Luc Nancy]], and [[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]] also studied his work more or less closely.  Beyond his relation to [[phenomenology]], Heidegger is regarded as a major or indispensable influence on [[existentialism]], [[deconstruction]], [[hermeneutics]] and [[postmodernism]].  He attempted to reorient Western philosophy away from [[Metaphysics|metaphysical]] and [[Epistemology|epistemological]] and toward [[ontology|ontological]] questions, that is, questions concerning the meaning of [[being]], or what it means "to-be". Much controversy has surrounded his status as a prominent academic member of the [[Nazi Party]].  
  
== Early Life and Education ==
+
==Biography==
 +
Heidegger was born in a rural [[Roman Catholic]] family in [[Messkirch|Messkirch]], Germany. His father was the sexton of the village church. His family could not afford to send him to university and he entered a Jesuit seminary instead. After studying Theology at the [[Albert-Ludwigs-Universität|University of Freiburg]] from 1909 to 1911, he switched to Philosophy, receiving his PhD in 1914 with a thesis on [[Psychologism]], and the ''venia legendi'' in Philosophy with a [[Habilitation]] thesis on [[Duns Scotus]] in 1916.  1916-17, he was an unsalaried [[Privatdozent]], then served as a soldier during the last year of [[World War I]], working behind a desk and never leaving Germany. After the war, he served as a salaried senior assistant to [[Edmund Husserl]] at the [[University of Freiburg]] until 1923.  During this time, he built his mountain cabin, the ''Hütte'', in [[Todtnauberg]] in the nearby [[Schwarzwald]]. In 1923, he was elected to an extraordinary Professorship (full professor but without a Chair) in Philosophy at the equally reputable but very [[Protestant]] [[University of Marburg]].  At Marburg his colleagues included [[Rudolf Bultmann]], [[Ernst Friedländer]], [[Nicolai Hartmann]], and [[Paul Natorp]], and his notable students, [[Hans-Georg Gadamer]], [[Karl Löwith]], [[Gerhard Krüger]], [[Leo Strauss]], and [[Hannah Arendt]]. When Husserl retired in 1928, Heidegger, having published ''Sein und Zeit'' the previous year, accepted Freiburg's election to be his successor, in spite of a counter-offer by Marburg. Heidegger remained at Freiburg for the rest of his life, declining a number of later offers including one from Berlin, the most prestigious German university of the day. In 1933, he became a member of the [[NSDAP]] (Nazi party), to which he had been close since 1931, and was appointed [[Rector]] of the University. His inaugural address, his "Rektoratsrede," became notorious. He resigned the Rectorship in 1934, but never resigned from the Nazi party. In 1945/47, the French Occupation Authority forbade him to teach because of his Nazi past, a decision rescinded in 1951 when he became Professor [[emeritus]] with all privileges. He then taught on regularly from 1951 and 1958, and until 1967 by invitation. He died in 1976, was given a Roman Catholic funeral, and is buried in the Meßkirch cemetery.
  
Heidegger was born to a rural family in [[Messkirch|Meßkirch]], Germany, and raised to be a clergyman. He was influenced as a teenager by [[Aristotle]] mediated through Christian [[theology]]. The concept of [[being]], in this traditional sense, dating back to [[Plato]], was his first exposure to an idea he would plant at the core of his most famous work ''[[Being and Time]]'' (1927). His family was not wealthy enough to send him to university and he required a scholarship, which itself required he study for the religious order. Mathematics was also his early major. During his time as a student he left theology for philosophy as he gradually found other academic funding. He wrote his doctorate thesis on a text then thought to be by [[Duns Scotus]], a 14th century ethical and religious thinker, but later attributed to [[Thomas of Erfurt]].
+
==Personal and Family Life==
 +
In 1917, Heidegger married [[Elfriede Heidegger|Elfriede Petri]], in a Protestant wedding. She has been blamed for being a negative influence on him, by virtue of her strong anti-Semitic and Nazi sympathies. Heidegger had several extramarital affairs, including two very important ones with Jewish women who were his students, [[Hannah Arendt]] and [[Elisabeth Blochmann]], with whom he remained in contact for the rest of his life (except during World War II). Only with the recent publication of the letters between Martin and Elfriede Heidegger in 2005 did it become known that the Heidegger marriage was an "[[Open marriage|open]]" one, in that Elfriede likewise had affairs, including one with the family doctor who fathered her first son, [[Hermann Heidegger]].
  
Heidegger was originally a [[phenomenology|phenomenologist]]. To oversimplify, phenomenologists approach philosophy by attempting to perceive experience unmediated by prior knowledge and abstract theoretical assumptions. Husserl was its founder and major exponent. In fact, Heidegger studied under [[Husserl]] and it was this that persuaded him to become a phenomenologist. Heidegger became interested in the question of being (or what it means to be). His famous work ''Being and Time'' is characterized as phenomenological ontology. The idea of [[being]] dates back to [[Parmenides]] and has traditionally served as one of the key thoughts of Western philosophy. The question of being was revived by Heidegger after being eclipsed by the metaphysical tradition from [[Plato]] to [[Descartes]], and more recently in the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]]. He tried to ground [[being]] in [[time]], and thus discover its real essence or meaning, that is, its intelligibility for us.
+
==Philosophy==
 +
Heidegger is one of the most significant philosophers of the 20th century, and his ideas have penetrated into many areas. His discussion of [[ontology]] has led to his being often cited as one of the founders of existentialism and his ideas inspired major philosophical work, e.g., Sartre, who adopts many of Heidegger's ideas (although Heidegger insisted that Sartre misunderstood him). His philosophical work was taken up throughout [[Germany]], [[France]], and [[Japan]] and has gained, since the 1970s at least, a fair following in North America as well. Heidegger's work was scorned and dismissed, however, by many of his contemporaries, such as the [[Vienna Circle]], [[Theodor Adorno]], and Anglo-American philosophers such as [[Bertrand Russell]] and [[Alfred Ayer]].  
  
Thus Heidegger began where being began &mdash; in [[Greek philosophy|ancient Greek thought]], resurrecting a lost, under-appreciated issue in contemporary philosophy. Heidegger's great opening was to take Plato seriously again, and at the same time undermine the entire Platonic world by challenging the core of Platonism &mdash; treating being not as timeless and transcendent, but as immanent in [[time]] and [[history]]. This is partially why Platonists such as [[George Grant]] regard Heidegger as a great thinker, even if they disagree with his analysis of Being and conception of [[Platonic]] thought. Although Heidegger was a supremely creative and original thinker, he also borrowed heavily from [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] and [[Soren Kierkegaard]], the latter of whom goes mostly unacknowledged by Heidegger.  Heidegger can be compared to Aristotle, who took Plato's dialogues and systematically presented them as treatises and concepts. Similarly, Heidegger extracted Nietzsche's unpublished fragments and interpreted them as the culminating expression of Western metaphysics. Heidegger's published lectures during [[1936]] on ''Nietzsche’s Will to Power as Art'' are less scholarly commentaries than original philosophical works in their own right. Heidegger's concepts of angst and [[Dasein|Da-sein]] draw on Kierkegaard's notions of anxiety, the importance of subjective relation to the truth, existence in the face of death, the temporality of existence, and the importance of passionate affirmation of one's individual being-in-the-world.
+
Heidegger's refusal to recognize concepts such as the [[fact-value distinction]], his criticisms of logic, modern science, and [[technology]], and his refusal to include an "ethical" dimension to his theory, and claiming that doing so amounted to a fundamental misunderstanding of his thought, often puzzled and confused philosophers. Thus he has been attacked on these philosophical points and in regards to his political and personal behavior.
  
Martin Heidegger is regarded as one of the most significant philosophers of the 20th century. His prominence is rivaled only by [[Wittgenstein]], and his ideas have seeped into an incredibly large number of research areas. It is because of Heidegger's discussion of ontology that he is often cited as one of the founders of existentialism and his ideas inspired some great philosophical works, such as by the philosopher Sartre who adopts many of his ideas from Heidegger (although Heidegger insists that Sartre misunderstood his works). His philosophical work was taken up throughout [[Germany]], [[France]], and [[Japan]] and has gained, since the 1970s at least, a strong following in North America as well; it was scorned as rubbish, however, by contemporaries such as the [[Vienna Circle]], [[Theodor Adorno]], and British philosophers such as [[Bertrand Russell]] and [[Alfred Ayer]].  
+
His philosophy also has been read as opening up the possibility for dialogue with traditions of thought outside the western philosophy, particularly East Asian thinking. This is an ambigous aspect of Heidegger's philosophy, because his notions such "language as the house of being" precisely seem to rule out such a possiblity. Eastern and western thought literally and metaphorically don't speak the same language. However certain elements in Heidegger's latter work, paticularly the dialogue between A Japanese and an Inquirer, do show an interest in such a dialogue occurring. Heidegger himself had contact with a number of leading Japanese intellectuals of his time in the [[Kyoto School]]. Further more it has also been claimed that a number of elements within Heidegger's thought bear a close parallel to eastern philosophical ideas, particularly with [[Zen]] Buddhism and [[Daoism]].
  
Heidegger's refusal to adopt current concepts such as the [[fact-value distinction]], his criticism of modern science and [[technology]], and his refusal to offer an "ethical" component to his theory, claiming such a suggestion was a fundamental misunderstanding of his thought, often puzzled and confused philosophers. Attacking him seemed like the only thing to do, especially since his private behavior was morally and politically ambiguous.
+
===Influences===
 +
Heidegger was influenced as a teenager by [[Aristotle]] mediated through Christian [[theology]]. The concept of [[being]], which in the traditional sense can be dated back to [[Plato]], made up his first exposure to an idea that he would later plant at the core of his most famous work ''[[Being and Time]]'' (1927). Originally, he would have to be called a [[phenomenology|phenomenologist]]. The phenomenological approach to philosophy can be briefly sketched as an attempt to perceive experience unmediated by any prior knowledge and thus as a way of trying to reach the thing itself, bypassing every abstract theoretical assumption of it. [[Edmund Husserl]] was a founder and major exponent of this philosophical branch, and also Heidegger's teacher and mentor. In spite of some disagreements over method phenomenology no doubt held a special place for Heidegger throughout the evolution of his thinking, even though he became more and more interested in the specific question of being (or what it means to be). He himself characterizes his famous work ''Being and Time'' as phenomenological ontology. The idea of [[being]] can at the very least be tracked back to [[Parmenides]] and has traditionally served as one of the key thoughts of Western philosophy. The question of being was so to speak revived by Heidegger after being eclipsed by the metaphysical tradition from [[Plato]] to [[Descartes]], and even more recently during the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]]. Heidegger sought to explain [[being]] in terms of [[time]], and thus to discover its real essence or meaning, that is, its intelligibility for us.
  
== Philosophy ==
+
In this manner Heidegger began where being began &mdash; in [[Greek philosophy|ancient Greek thought]], resurrecting a lost and under-appreciated issue in contemporary philosophy. Heidegger's great opening was to take Plato seriously again, and at the same time undermine the entire Platonic world by challenging the core of Platonism &mdash; treating being not as timeless and transcendent, but instead as embedded in [[time]] and [[history]]. This is partially why Platonists tend to regard Heidegger as a great thinker, even if they disagree with his analysis of Being and his conception of [[Platonic]] thought. Although Heidegger was a supremely creative and original thinker, he at the same time borrowed heavily from [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] and [[Søren Kierkegaard]], the latter of whom is mostly referred to in footnotes.  Heidegger can be compared to Aristotle, who took Plato's dialogues and systematically presented them as treatises and conceptual structures. Similarly, Heidegger extracted Nietzsche's unpublished fragments and interpreted them as the culminating expression of Western metaphysics. It must be said though that Heidegger's published lectures during [[1936]] on ''Nietzsche’s Will to Power as Art'' are less scholarly commentaries than original philosophical works in their own right. Heidegger's concepts of angst and [[Dasein|Da-sein]] manifestly draw on Kierkegaard's notions of anxiety, furthermore Heidegger is indebted to the way in which Kierkegaard lays out the importance of our subjective relation to the truth, our existence in the face of death, the temporality of existence, and the importance of passionate affirmation of one's individual being-in-the-world. Nonetheless, it is important to notice the difference between a Danish philosopher operating inside the Christian framework and Heidegger, who largely gave his thought free play.
  
 
===''Being and Time''===
 
===''Being and Time''===
 +
''Main article: [[Being and Time]]''
  
Heidegger's most important work is the dense and challenging ''[[Being and Time]]'' ([[German (language)|German]] ''Sein und Zeit'', [[1927]]).  Although the book as published represents only a third of the total project outlined in its introduction, it marked a turning point in [[continental philosophy]].  It has been massively influential and remains one of the most discussed works of [[20th century]] [[philosophy]]; many subsequent philosophical views and approaches, such as [[existentialism]] and [[deconstruction]], have been strongly influenced by ''Being and Time''.
+
'''''Being and Time''''' ([[German language|German]] title: ''Sein und Zeit''), published in 1927, is [[Heidegger]]'s most influential work. This epochal book was his first significant academic work, and earned him a professorship at [[Freiburg University]]. He subsequently changed his views on several points made in the book. It is a touchstone of [[Continental philosophy]], a groundbreaking investigation of the concepts of [[Being]] & ''Da-sein'' (literally "existence" and, often translated by its components, "being-there"), as these relate to [[ontology]] and [[phenomenology]]. Although Heidegger distanced himself from [[existentialism]], ''Being and Time'' strongly influenced existentialist thinkers like [[Jean-Paul Sartre]].
 
 
In this work, Heidegger takes up the question of the meaning of being: what does it mean to say that an entity ''is''?  This is the fundamental question of [[ontology]], defined by [[Aristotle]] as the study of being ''qua'' (Latin, tr. roughly as 'as', or 'in the capacity of') being.  In his approach to this question, Heidegger departs from the tradition of [[Aristotle]] and of [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], both of whom, despite the vast difference between their respective philosophical positions, approach the question of the meaning of being from the perspective of the [[logic]] of propositional statements.  Implicit in this traditional approach is the thesis that theoretical knowledge represents the most fundamental relation between the human individual and the beings in his surrounding world (including himself).
 
 
 
Explicitly rejecting this thesis, Heidegger instead adopts a version of the [[phenomenology|phenomenological]] method, purged of what he regards as the residue of Aristotelian/Kantian cognitivism still present in [[Edmund Husserl|Husserl]]'s formulation of this method. Like [[Edmund Husserl|Husserl]], Heidegger takes as his starting point the phenomenon of [[intentionality]].  Human behavior is [[intentionality|intentional]] insofar as it is directed at some object or end (all building is building of something, all talking is talking about something, etc).  [[Intentionality]] was an activity termed by Heidegger as "''Sorge''" (care) and reflected a positive aspect of [[Angst]]. ''Sorge'', or caring, as the fundamental concept of the [[intentionality|intentional being]], presupposed an [[intentionality|ontological significance]] that distinguishes ontological being from mere ontic being (thinghood).  Theoretical knowledge represents only one kind of [[intentionality|intentional]] behavior, and Heidegger asserts that it is founded on more fundamental modes of behavior, modes of practical engagement with the surrounding world, rather than being their ultimate foundation.  An entity is what it is (i.e., it has being) insofar as it "shows up" within a context of practical engagement (Heidegger calls such a context a 'world'), not because it has certain inherent properties ascertainable by disinterested contemplation.  A hammer is a hammer not because it has certain hammer-like properties, but because it is used for hammering.
 
 
 
This also necessitated a rejection of the Cartesian, disembodied 'I': that is, an 'I' as a purely thinking object. Instead, Heidegger insisted that any analysis of human behaviour should begin with the fact that we are in the world (not viewing it in an 'abstract' fashion): therefore the fundamental fact about human existence is our 'being-in-the-world'. Human beings, Heidegger insisted, were embodied beings who acted in the world. He also said that the world was a characteristic of Being in the World, "Da-Sein.". He therefore rejected the 'subject-object' distinction assumed by most philosophers since Descartes. Things are meaningful to us in terms of their use in certain contexts, which are defined by social norms. However, all of these norms are radically contingent.  Their contingency is revealed in the fundamental phenomenon of [[Angst]], in which all norms fall away and beings show up as nothing in particular, in their essential meaninglessness.  (Contrary to some [[existentialism|existentialist]] interpretations of Heidegger, this does not mean that all existence is absurd; rather, it means that existence always has the ''potential'' for absurdity.)  The experience of [[Angst]] reveals the essential finitude of human being.
 
 
 
The fact that beings can show up, either as meaningful in a context or as meaningless in the experience of [[Angst]], depends on a prior phenomenon: that beings can show up at all.  Heidegger calls the showing up of beings' "truth", which he defines as unconcealment rather than correctness.  This "truth of beings", their self-revelation, involves a more fundamental kind of truth, the "disclosure of being in which the being of beings is unconcealed."  It is this unconcealment of being that defines human existence for Heidegger: the human being is that being for whom being is an issue, that is, for whom being shows up as such (Heidegger's word for such an entity, which could conceivably have non-human instantiations, is [[Dasein|Da-sein]]).  This is why Heidegger begins his inquiry into the meaning of being with an inquiry into the essence of ''human'' being; the [[ontology]] of ''Da-sein'' is fundamental [[ontology]].  The unconcealment of being is an essentially temporal and historical phenomenon (hence the "time" in ''Being and Time''); what we call past, present, and future correspond originarily to aspects of this unconcealment and not to three mutually exclusive regions of the homogeneous time that clocks measure (although clock-time is derivative from the originary time of unconcealment, as Heidegger attempts to show in the book's difficult final chapters).
 
 
 
The total understanding of being results from an explication of the implicit knowledge of being that inheres in all human behavior.  Philosophy thus becomes a form of interpretation; this is why Heidegger's technique in ''Being and Time'' is often referred to as [[hermeneutics|hermeneutical]] [[phenomenology]]. ''Being and Time'', being incomplete, contains Heidegger's statement of this project and his interpretation of human existence and its temporal horizon, but does not contain the working out of the meaning of being as such on the basis of this interpretation.  This ambitious task is taken up in a different way in his later works (see below).
 
 
 
As part of his [[ontology|ontological]] project, Heidegger undertakes a reinterpretation of previous Western philosophy.  He wants to explain why and how theoretical knowledge came to seem like the most fundamental relation to being.  This explanation takes the form of a destructuring (''Destruktion'') of the philosophical tradition, an interpretive strategy that reveals the fundamental experience of being at the base of previous philosophies.  In ''Being and Time'' he briefly destructures the philosophy of [[René Descartes|Descartes]]; in later works he uses this approach to interpret the philosophies of [[Aristotle]], [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]], and [[Plato]], among others.  This technique exerted a profound influence on [[Jacques Derrida|Derrida]]'s [[deconstruction|deconstructive]] approach, although there are very important differences between the two methods.
 
 
 
''Being and Time'' is the towering achievement of Heidegger's early career, but there are other important works from this period, including ''Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie'' (''The Basic Problems of Phenomenology'', 1927), ''Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik'' (''Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics'', 1929), and "Was ist Metaphysik?" ("What Is Metaphysics?", 1929).
 
  
 
===Later works===
 
===Later works===
 
 
Although Heidegger claimed that all of his writings concerned a single question, the question of being, in the years after the publication of ''[[Being and Time]]'' the focus of his work gradually changed.  This change is often referred to as Heidegger's ''Kehre'' (turn).  In his later works, Heidegger turns from "doing" to "dwelling."  He focuses less on the way in which the structures of being are revealed in everyday behavior and in the experience of [[Angst]], and more on the way in which behavior itself depends on a prior "openness to being."  The essence of being human is the maintenance of this openness.  (The difference between Heidegger's early and late works is more a difference of emphasis than a radical break like that between the early and late works of [[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Wittgenstein]], but it is important enough to justify a division of the Heideggerian corpus into "early" (roughly, pre-1930) and "late" writings.)
 
Although Heidegger claimed that all of his writings concerned a single question, the question of being, in the years after the publication of ''[[Being and Time]]'' the focus of his work gradually changed.  This change is often referred to as Heidegger's ''Kehre'' (turn).  In his later works, Heidegger turns from "doing" to "dwelling."  He focuses less on the way in which the structures of being are revealed in everyday behavior and in the experience of [[Angst]], and more on the way in which behavior itself depends on a prior "openness to being."  The essence of being human is the maintenance of this openness.  (The difference between Heidegger's early and late works is more a difference of emphasis than a radical break like that between the early and late works of [[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Wittgenstein]], but it is important enough to justify a division of the Heideggerian corpus into "early" (roughly, pre-1930) and "late" writings.)
  
Line 63: Line 54:
 
In the later writings, two recurring themes are poetry and technology.  Heidegger sees poetry as a preeminent way in which beings are revealed "in their being."  The play of poetic language (which is, for Heidegger, the essence of language itself) reveals the play of presence and absence that is being itself.  Heidegger focuses especially on the poetry of [[Friedrich Hölderlin|Hölderlin]].
 
In the later writings, two recurring themes are poetry and technology.  Heidegger sees poetry as a preeminent way in which beings are revealed "in their being."  The play of poetic language (which is, for Heidegger, the essence of language itself) reveals the play of presence and absence that is being itself.  Heidegger focuses especially on the poetry of [[Friedrich Hölderlin|Hölderlin]].
  
Against the revealing power of poetry, Heidegger sets the force of technology.  The essence of technology is the conversion of the whole universe of beings into an undifferentiated "standing reserve" (''Bestand'') of energy available for any use to which humans choose to put it.  The standing reserve represents the most extreme nihilism, since the being of beings is totally subordinated to the will of the human subject.  Heidegger does not unequivocally condemn technology; he believes that its increasing dominance might make it possible for humanity to return to its authentic task of the stewardship of being.  Nevertheless, many of Heidegger's later works are characterized by an unmistakable agrarian nostalgia.
+
Against the revealing power of poetry, Heidegger sets the force of technology.  The essence of technology is the conversion of the whole universe of beings into an undifferentiated "standing reserve" (''Bestand'') of energy available for any use to which humans choose to put it.  The standing reserve represents the most extreme nihilism, since the being of beings is totally subordinated to the will of the human subject. Indeed, Heidegger described the essence of technology as ''[[Gestell]]'', or enframing.  Heidegger does not unequivocally condemn technology; he believes that its increasing dominance might make it possible for humanity to return to its authentic task of the stewardship of being.  Nevertheless, an unmistakable agrarian nostalgia permeates much of his later work.
 +
 
 +
Heidegger's important later works include ''Vom Wesen der Wahrheit'' ("On the Essence of Truth," 1930), ''Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes'' ("The Origin of the Work of Art," 1935), ''Bauen Wohnen Denken'' ("Building Dwelling Thinking," 1951), and ''Die Frage nach der Technik'' ("The Question of Technology," 1953) and ''Was heisst Denken?'' ("What Is Called Thinking?" 1954).
  
Heidegger's important later works include ''Vom Wesen der Wahrheit'' ("On the Essence of Truth," 1930), ''Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes'' ("The Origin of the Work of Art," 1935), ''Bauen Wohnen Denken'' ("Building Dwelling Thinking," 1951), and ''Die Frage nach der Technik'' ("The Question Concerning Technology," 1953) and ''Was heisst Denken?'' ("What Is Called Thinking?" 1954).
 
  
===Influences and Difficulties of French Reception===
+
===Heidegger and Eastern thought===
 +
Heidegger's philosophy has been read as opening up the possibility for dialogue with traditions of thought outside of Western philosophy, paticularly East Asian thinking. This is an ambigous aspect of Heidegger's philosophy, insofar as his notions such as "language as the house of being" seem precisely to rule out such a possiblity. Eastern and Western thought literally and metaphorically don't speak the same language. However certain elements in Heidegger's latter work, particularly the dialogue between A Japanese and an Inquirer, do show an interest in such a dialogue occurring. Heidegger himself had contact with an number of leading Japanese intellectuals of his time in the [[Kyoto School]]. Further more it has also claimed that a number of elements within Heidegger's thought bear a close parallel to Eastern philosophical ideas, paticularly with [[Zen]] Buddhism and [[Daoism]]
  
Heidegger, like Husserl, is an explicitly acknowledged influence on existentialism, despite his explicit disavowal and objection, in texts such as the "Letter on Humanism," of the importation of key elements of his work into existentialist contexts. While Heidegger was banned from university teaching for a period shortly after the war on account of his activities as Rector of Freiburg, he developed a number of contacts in France who continued to teach his work and brought their students to visit him in Todtnauberg (see, for example, [[Jean-François Lyotard|Jean-François Lyotard's]] brief account in "Heidegger and 'the jews': A Conference in Vienna  and Freiburg," which discusses a Franco-German conference held in Freiburg in 1947, a first step in bringing together French and German students after the War). Heidegger subsequently made efforts to keep abreast of developments in French philosophy by way of recommendations from [[Jean Beaufret]], who was an early French translator, and [[Lucien Braun]].
+
===Influences and difficulties of French reception===
 +
 +
Heidegger, like Husserl, is an explicitly acknowledged influence on existentialism, despite his explicit disavowal and objection, in texts such as the "Letter on Humanism," of the importation of key elements of his work into existentialist contexts. While Heidegger was banned from university teaching for a period shortly after the war on account of his activities as Rector of Freiburg, he developed a number of contacts in France who continued to teach his work and brought their students to visit him in Todtnauberg (see, for example, [[Jean-François Lyotard|Jean-François Lyotard's]] brief account in "Heidegger and 'the Jews': A Conference in Vienna  and Freiburg," which discusses a Franco-German conference held in Freiburg in 1947, a first step in bringing together French and German students after the War). Heidegger subsequently made efforts to keep abreast of developments in French philosophy by way of recommendations from [[Jean Beaufret]], who was an early French translator, and [[Lucien Braun]].
  
[[Deconstruction]] as it is generally understood (i.e., as French and Anglo-American phenomena profoundly rooted in Heidegger's work, with limited general exposure in a German context until the 1980s) came to Heidegger's attention in 1967 by way of [[Lucien Braun|Lucien Braun's]] recommendation of [[Jacques Derrida|Jacques Derrida's]] work ([[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] was present at an initial discussion and indicated to Heidegger that Derrida's work came to his attention by way of an assistant). Heidegger expressed interest in meeting Derrida personally after the latter sent him some of his work. (There was discussion of a meeting in 1972, but this did not happen.) Heidegger's interest in Derrida is said by Braun to have been considerable (as is evident in two letters, of 29 September 1967 and 16 May 1972, from Heidegger to Braun). Braun also brought to Heidegger's attention the work of [[Michel Foucault]]. Foucault's relation to Heidegger is a matter of considerable difficulty; Foucault acknowledged Heidegger as the philosopher whom he read but never wrote about. (For more on this see ''Penser à Strasbourg,'' Jacques Derrida, et al, which includes reproductions of both letters and an account by Braun, "À mi-chemin entre Heidegger et Derrida").
+
[[Deconstruction]] as it is generally understood (i.e., as French and Anglo-American phenomena profoundly rooted in Heidegger's work, with limited general exposure in a German context until the 1980s) came to Heidegger's attention in 1967 by way of [[Lucien Braun|Lucien Braun's]] recommendation of [[Jacques Derrida|Jacques Derrida's]] work ([[Hans-Georg Gadamer]] was present at an initial discussion and indicated to Heidegger that Derrida's work came to his attention by way of an assistant). Heidegger expressed interest in meeting Derrida personally after the latter sent him some of his work. (There was discussion of a meeting in 1972, but this did not happen.) Heidegger's interest in Derrida is said by Braun to have been considerable (as is evident in two letters, of 29 September 1967 and 16 May 1972, from Heidegger to Braun). Braun also brought to Heidegger's attention the work of [[Michel Foucault]]. Foucault's relation to Heidegger is a matter of considerable difficulty; Foucault acknowledged Heidegger as a philosopher whom he read but never wrote about. (For more on this see ''Penser à Strasbourg,'' Jacques Derrida, et al, which includes reproductions of both letters and an account by Braun, "À mi-chemin entre Heidegger et Derrida").
  
One feature that garnered initial interest in a French context (which propagated rather quickly to scholars of French literature and philosophy working in American universities) was Derrida's efforts to displace the understanding of Heidegger's work prevalent in France from the period of the ban against Heidegger teaching in German universities, which amounts in part to rejecting almost wholesale the influence of [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] and existentialist terms. In Derrida's view, deconstruction is a tradition inherited via Heidegger (the French term translate language from Heidegger), and Sartre's interpretation of Dasein and other key Heideggerian terms is overly psychologistic and ironically anthropocentric, consisting of a radical misconception of the limited number of Heidegger's texts commonly studied in France up to that point (namely ''Being and Time,'' ''What is Metaphysics?,'' and ''Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics''). Derrida, on the other hand, is at times presented as an ultra-orthodox "French Heidegger," so much so that he, his colleagues, and his former students are made to go proxy for Heidegger's worst mistakes, despite ample evidence that the reception of Heidegger's work by later practitioners of deconstruction is anything but doctrinaire "Heideggerianism" (the work of [[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]] may be taken as exemplary in this regard and was often commended as such by Derrida, who further contrasted Lacoue-Labarthe's extended work on Heidegger with Foucault's silence).
+
One feature that garnered initial interest in a French context (which propagated rather quickly to scholars of French literature and philosophy working in American universities) was Derrida's efforts to displace the understanding of Heidegger's work that had been prevalent in France from the period of the ban against Heidegger teaching in German universities, which amounts in part to an almost wholesale rejection of the influence of [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] and existentialist terms. In Derrida's view, deconstruction is a tradition inherited via Heidegger (the French term "déconstruction" is a term coined to translate Heidegger's use of the words "Destruktion" - literally "destruction" - and "Abbau" - more literally "de-building"), whereas Sartre's interpretation of Dasein and other key Heideggerian terms is overly psychologistic and (ironically) anthropocentric, consisting of a radical misconception of the limited number of Heidegger's texts commonly studied in France up to that point (namely ''Being and Time,'' ''What is Metaphysics?,'' and ''Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics''). Derrida, on the other hand, is at times presented as an ultra-orthodox "French Heidegger," to the extent that he, his colleagues, and his former students are made to go proxy for Heidegger's worst (political) mistakes, despite ample evidence that the reception of Heidegger's work by later practitioners of deconstruction is anything but doctrinaire. The work of [[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]] may be taken as exemplary in this regard and was often commended as such by Derrida, who further contrasted Lacoue-Labarthe's extended work on Heidegger with Foucault's silence.
 +
 
 +
Having earlier mentioned the contributions of Derrida, Lacoue-Labarthe, and Lyotard to scholarship on Heidegger and National Socialism, it is worth noting that Heidegger's relation to the Holocaust and Nazism was the subject of great and occasionally fractious debate across various [[Deconstruction|"deconstructions"]]. These included the extent to which specific practitioners of deconstruction could entirely do without Heideggerian deconstruction (as Lyotard in particular may have wished) or were - rather - obliged to further (and in the cases of many mis- and uninformed criticisms, recall) already extensive criticisms of Heidegger which considerably predated (in the case of Derrida, by decades) the broad recognition of Heidegger's activities as a National Socialist.  The latter were precipitated by press attention to the Víctor Farías book "Heidegger et le nazisme" (Farias was an ex-student of Heidegger) and extensive treatments of the Holocaust and its implications. These included for example, the proceedings of the first conference dedicated to Derrida's work, published as "Les Fins de l'Homme" (the essay from which that title was taken), Derrida's "Feu la cendre/cio' che resta del fuoco", or the studies on Celan by Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida which shortly preceded the detailed studies of Heidegger's politics published in and after 1987.
  
Having earlier mentioned the contributions of Derrida, Lacoue-Labarthe, and Lyotard to scholarship on Heidegger and National Socialism, it is worth noting that Heidegger's relation to the Holocaust and Nazism was the subject of great and occasionally fractious debate across various [[Deconstruction|deconstructions]], whose stakes included the extent to which specific practitioners of deconstruction could entirely do without Heideggerian deconstruction (as Lyotard in particular may have wished) or were therefore obliged to further (and in the cases of many mis- and uninformed criticisms, recall) already extensive criticisms of Heidegger which considerably predated (in the case of Derrida, by decades) the broad recognition of Heidegger's activities as a National Socialist precipitated by press attention to the Farias book and extensive treatments of the Holocaust and its implications (for example, the proceedings of the first conference dedicated to Derrida's work, published as Les Fins de l'Homme, the essay from which that title was taken, Derrida's Cinders and "Restitutions of the Truth in Pointing," or the studies on Celan by Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida which shortly preceded the detailed studies of Heidegger's politics published in and after 1987). On so many of these matters, please see Avital Ronell's "The Differends of Man" in Finitude's Score. Particularly given that the ways in which various deconstructions have more or less self-consciously inherited from Heidegger is often used to find them complicit in his most reprehensible politics by implication, one ought to review at least the above readings before indulging such a line of argument or when otherwise wishing to understand what filiation has been taken to mean in a philosophical context.
 
  
 
=== Criticism ===
 
=== Criticism ===
 +
Heidegger's importance to the world of continental philosophy (a subject he is even said by some to have created, although there was some distinction between continental and [[analytic philosophy]] before him, the origins of continental philosophy being traceable to [[romanticism]] and analytic philosophy to utiliterianism),  is probably unsurpassed. His reception among analytic philosophers, however, is quite another story. Saving a moderately favorable review in ''Mind'' by a young [[Gilbert Ryle]] of ''Being and Time'' shortly after its publication, Heidegger's analytic contemporaries (a field still young, but already quite sharply delineated from other branches of philosophy) generally regarded both the content, if any, and the style in which he delivered it, as examples of the worst possible way of doing philosophy.
  
Heidegger's importance to the world of continental philosophy (which he largely created, there being no distinction between analytical and continental philosophy prior to him) is probably unsurpassed. His reception amongst philosophers of the analytic school, however, is quite another story. Saving a somewhat favorable review by Gilbert Ryle in the journal ''Mind'' of ''Being and Time'' at the time of its publication, Heidegger's contemporaries from the analytic tradition (which was still young, but already quite sharply delineated from other branches of philosophy) generally regarded both the content, insofar as they believed there to be any at all, and the style by which he delivered it, as evidence of the worst possible way of doing philosophy.
+
The analytic tradition values clarity of expression, whereas Heidegger thought that "making itself intelligible was suicide for philosophy." Apart from the charge of obscurantism, analytic philosophers generally considered the actual content that could be gleaned from Heidegger's work to be either faulty and frivolous, unpalatably subjective or uninteresting. This view has largely survived, and Heidegger is still derided by most analytical philosophers, who deem his work to have been disastrous for philosophy, in that a clear line can be traced from it to most varieties of postmodern thinking. Others have accused Heidegger of having an 'illusory' ontology and have decried his influence on subsequent philosophy{{fact}}. 
 
 
The analytic tradition values clarity of expression, whereas Heidegger thought that "making itself intelligible was suicide for philosophy." Apart from the charge of obscurantism, analytic philosophers generally considered the actual content that could be gleaned from Heidegger's work to be either trivially false, non-verifiable or uninteresting. This view has largely survived, and Heidegger is still spoken of with derision in most quarters of analytical philosophy, and his influence is considered to have been disastrous for philosophy, in that a clear line can be traced from it to most varieties of postmodern philosophical thinking.
 
  
 +
His reputation has improved slightly through the impact of [[Richard Rorty]]'s philosophy on the English-speaking world; Rorty even claims that Heidegger's approach to philosophy in the second half of his career has much in common with that of the latter-day [[Wittgenstein]] - one of the giants of analytical philosophy.
  
 
== Heidegger and Nazi Germany ==
 
== Heidegger and Nazi Germany ==
 +
Heidegger joined the [[Nazi Party]] on [[May 1]], [[1933]], before being appointed Rector of the [[University of Freiburg]]. He resigned the Rectorship in April [[1934]]. However, he remained a member of the Nazi party until the end of the war. During his time as Rector, Freiburg denied Heidegger's former teacher [[Edmund Husserl|Husserl]], born a [[Jew]] and an adult Lutheran convert, access of the university library, invoking the Nazi [[racial policy of Nazi Germany|racial cleansing laws]]. Heidegger also removed the dedication to Husserl from ''[[Being and Time]]'' when it was reissued in [[1941]], later claiming he did so because of pressure from his publisher, [[Max Niemeyer]]. Additionally, when Heidegger's ''Introduction to Metaphysics'' (based on lectures given in [[1935]]) was published in [[1953]], he declined to remove a reference to the "inner truth and greatness of this movement [''die innere Wahrheit und Größe dieser Bewegung'']," i.e. [[Nazism|National Socialism]]. Instead of deleting or altering the text, he added the parenthetical gloss, "(namely, the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity) ''(nämlich [die] Begegnung der planetarisch bestimmten Technik und des neuzeitlichen Menschen)''." Many readers, notably [[Jürgen Habermas]], came to interpret this ambiguous remark as evidence of his continued commitment to National Socialism.
  
Heidegger joined the [[Nazi Party]] on [[May 1]], [[1933]], before being appointed the rector of the university in [[Freiburg]]. He resigned from the rectorship in April [[1934]]. During this time Heidegger's former teacher [[Edmund Husserl|Husserl]], who was [[Jew]]ish, was denied the use of the university library at Freiburg because of the [[racial policy of Nazi Germany|racial cleansing laws]] issued by the Nazi Party. Heidegger also removed the dedication to Husserl from ''[[Being and Time]]'' when it was reissued in [[1941]]. Heidegger later claimed that this was due to pressure from his publisher, [[Max Niemeyer]]. Additionally, when Heidegger's ''Introduction to Metaphysics'' (lectures originally given in [[1935]]) was published in 1953, he declined to remove a reference to the "inner truth and greatness of this movement [''die innere Wahrheit und Größe dieser Bewegnung'']," i.e. [[Nazism|National Socialism]]. Instead of deleting or altering the text, he merely added the parenthetical gloss, "(namely, the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity) ''(nämlich [die] Begegnung der planetarisch bestimmten Technik und des neuzeitlichen Menschen)''." Many readers, notably [[Jürgen Habermas]], came to interpret this ambiguous remark as evidence of his continued commitment to National Socialism.
+
Critics further cite Heidegger's affair with [[Hannah Arendt]], who was Jewish, while she was his doctoral student at the [[University of Marburg]]. This affair took place in the [[1920s]], some time before Heidegger's involvement in Nazism, but it did not end when she moved to [[Heidelberg]] to continue with [[Karl Jaspers]]. She later spoke on his behalf at his [[denazification]] hearings. Jaspers spoke against him at these same hearings, suggesting he would have a detrimental influence on German students because of his powerful teaching presence. Arendt very cautiously resumed their friendship after the war, despite or even because of the widespread contempt for Heidegger and his political sympathies, and despite his being forbidden to teach for some years.
  
Critics further cite Heidegger's affair with [[Hannah Arendt]], when she was a doctoral student of his at the [[University of Marburg]]. This affair mostly went along in the 20s, some time before Heidegger's involvement in Nazism, but it did not end when she "fled" from him and moved to [[Heidelberg]] to continue with [[Karl Jaspers]], and she later spoke on his behalf at his [[denazification]] hearings. Jaspers spoke against him at these same hearings, suggesting he would have a detrimental influence on young German students because of his powerful teaching presence. Arendt, who was Jewish, resumed their friendship, if extremely cautiously, after the war, despite or even because of the widespread contempt that Heidegger was held in for his political sympathies, and despite his being forbidden from teaching for a number of years.
+
===''Der Spiegel'' interview===
 +
Some years later, hoping to quiet controversy, Heidegger gave an interview to ''[[Der Spiegel]]'' magazine, in which he agreed to discuss his political past provided that the interview be published posthumously. It should be noted that Heidegger extensively edited, at his insistance, the published version of the interview. In that interview, Heidegger's defense of his Nazi involvement runs in two tracks: first, he argued that there was no alternative, saying that he was trying to save the university (and science in general) from being politicized and thus had to compromise with the Nazi administration. Second, he saw an "awakening" ("Aufbruch") which might help to find a "new national and social approach". After 1934, he said, he would (should?) have been more critical of the Nazi government. Heidegger's answers to some questions are evasive. For example, when he talks about a "national and social approach" of national socialism, he links this to [[Friedrich Naumann]]. But Naumann's "national-sozialer Verein" was not at all national socialist, but liberal. Heidegger seems to have deliberately created this confusion. Also, he alternates quickly between his two lines of arguments, overlooking any contradictions. And his statements often tend to take the form "others were much more Nazi than me" and "the Nazis did bad things to me, too" which, while true, miss the point.  
  
===''Der Spiegel'' Interview===
+
The ''Der Spiegel'' interviewers also did not bring up Heidegger's 1949 quotation where he compares engineered food production to [[the Holocaust]] ("essentially the same.") While Heidegger's defenders have attempted to account for this "similarity of essence" by reference to his essay "On the Essence of Truth," this account of the technological frame that now infects human nourishment and human mortality is not a conventional reaction to genocide. Moreover, many of those who align themselves with Heidegger philosophically have pointed out that in his own work on being-towards-death, we can recognize a much more salient criticism of what was wrong with the mass-produced murder of a people. Thinkers as diverse as Giorgio Agamben and Judith Butler have made this point sympathetically. Commentators differ on whether this philosophical shorthand is evidence of a profound disregard for the Jews or simply the astygmatism of an old man concerned more with his own legacy than with that of the Holocaust.
  
Some years later, hoping to quiet controversy, Heidegger gave an interview to ''[[Der Spiegel]]'' magazine, in which he promised to discuss the issue provided it was published posthumously. It should also be mentioned that the published version was not a real interview, but the protocol had been largely "corrected" on Heidegger's demand. In this interview, Heidegger's defense of his Nazi involvement runs in two tracks: first, he argues that there would have been no alternative; he says he had tried to save the university (and science in general) from being politicized and had to make compromises with the Nazi administration. Second, he saw an "awakening" ("Aufbruch"), something which might help to find a "new national and social approach". From 1934 on, he says, he would have been more critical towards the government. Heidegger is evasive on some questions in this interview. For example, when he talks about a "national and social approach" in national socialism he links this to [[Friedrich Naumann]]. But Naumann's "national-sozialer Verein" was not at all national socialist, but liberal. This confusion seems to be put up deliberately by Heidegger. Also, he changes between his two arguments quickly, not regarding they are in a way contradictory. And his statements often tend to take the form "others were much more Nazis than me" and "the Nazis did bad things to me, too" which is true, but misses the point in question. Also, the ''Spiegel'' interviewers did not bring to question Heidegger's quote from 1949 where he compares engineered food production to [[the Holocaust]] ("essentially the same"); in fact, they were not in possession of much of the evidence for Heidegger's sympathies towards Nazism which is known today. To further evaluate this issue, read "Only a God Can Save Us," ''Der Spiegel'' interview with Heidegger (1966) and [[Jürgen Habermas]], "Work and Weltanschauung: The Heidegger Controversy from a German Perspective." translated by John McCumber, ''Critical Inquiry'' 15 (Winter 1989): pp. 431-456.
+
In fact, the ''Der Spiegel'' interviewers were not in possession of most of the evidence now known for Heidegger's Nazi sympathies. For more on this notorious interview and its aftermath, see "Only a God Can Save Us," ''Der Spiegel'' interview with Heidegger (1966) and [[Jürgen Habermas]], "Work and Weltanschauung: The Heidegger Controversy from a German Perspective." translated by John McCumber, ''Critical Inquiry 15'' (Winter 1989): 431-56.
  
===Obligations & Unsplendid Silence: Celan at "Todtnauberg"===
+
===Obligations and unsplendid silence: Celan at "Todtnauberg"===
 +
Shortly after giving the ''Spiegel'' interview and following Celan's lecture at Freiburg, Heidegger hosted [[Paul Celan]] at his chalet at Todtnauberg. The two walked in the woods. Celan impressed Heidegger with his knowledge of [[botany]] (also evident in his poetry), and Heidegger is thought to have spoken about elements of his press interview. Celan signed Heidegger's guest book.
  
Shortly after giving the ''Spiegel'' interview and following Celan's lecture at Freiburg, Heidegger hosted [[Paul Celan]] at his chalet at Todtnauberg. The two walked in the woods. Celan impressed Heidegger with his knowledge of [[botany]] (also evident in his poetry), and Heidegger is thought to have spoken about elements of his press interview. Celan signed Heidegger's guest book.
+
In his ''Poetry as Experience,'' Lacoue-Labarthe advanced the argument that, although Celan's poetry was deeply informed by Heidegger's philosophy, Celan was long aware of Heidegger's association with the Nazi party and therefore fundamentally circumspect toward the man and transformative in his reception of his work. Celan was nonetheless willing to meet Heidegger (although he may not have been willing to be photographed with him or to contribute to ''[[Festschrift]]en'' honoring Heidegger's work). Heidegger was a professed admirer of Celan's writing, although he did not attend to it as [[Friedrich Hölderlin|Hölderlin]] or [[Georg Trakl|Trakl]] (neither did he attend to Celan as a Jewish poet working within that German tradition). "Todtnauberg", however, seems to hold out the unrealized possibility of a profound rapprochement between their work, albeit on the condition that Heidegger break a silence that virtually blanketed his work to the end (Lacoue-Labarthe has commented on the insufficiency of Heidegger's one known remark about the gas chambers, made in 1949). In this respect Heidegger's work was perhaps redeemable for Celan, even if that redemption or what need was had for it was never transacted between the two men. Lest one implicitly take this as Celan simply demanding an apology of Heidegger (such a scenario seems simplistic, the more so given that neither was given to simplism), there are reasonable grounds to argue that it was (and still is) at least as important to specify how the Nazi period is ''das Unheil'' (disaster, calamity) (which is to say: specificity as to a great deal more than counting the dead). What compelled Heidegger to write about poetry, technology, and truth ought to have compelled him to write about the German disaster, all the more so because, on the basis of his thought, Heidegger attributed an "inner greatness" to the movement that brought about that disaster.
  
In his ''Poetry as Experience,'' Lacoue-Labarthe advanced the argument that, although Celan's poetry was deeply informed by Heidegger's philosophy, Celan was long aware of Heidegger's association with the Nazi party and therefore fundamentally circumspect toward the man and transformative in his reception of his work. Celan was nonetheless willing to meet Heidegger (although he may not have been willing to be photographed with him or to contribute to ''Festschriften'' honoring Heidegger's work). Heidegger was a professed admirer of Celan's writing, although he did not attend to it as [[Friedrich Hölderlin|Hölderlin]] or [[Georg Trakl|Trakl]]. "Todtnauberg", however, seems to hold out the unrealized possibility of a profound rapprochement between their work, albeit on the condition that Heidegger break a silence that virtually blanketed his work to the end (Lacoue-Labarthe has commented on the insufficiency of Heidegger's one known remark about the gas chambers, made in 1949). In this respect Heidegger's work was perhaps redeemable for Celan, even if that redemption or what need was had for it was never transacted between the two men. Lest one implicitly take this as Celan simply demanding an apology of Heidegger (such a scenario seems simplistic, the more so given that neither was given to simplism), there are reasonable grounds to argue that it was (and still is) at least as important to specify how the Nazi period is ''das Unheil'' (disaster, calamity) (which is to say: specificity as to a great deal more than counting the dead). What compelled Heidegger to write about poetry, technology, and truth ought to have compelled him to write about the German disaster, all the more so because, on the basis of his thought, Heidegger attributed an "inner greatness" to the movement that brought about that disaster.
+
Lacoue-Labarthe and [[Jacques Derrida]] have both commented extensively on Heidegger's corpus, and both have identified an idiomatically Heideggerian National Socialism that persisted until the end. It is perhaps of greater importance that Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida, following Celan to a degree, also believed Heidegger capable of a profound criticism of Nazism and the horrors it brought forth. They consider Heidegger's greatest failure not to be his involvement in the National Socialist movement but his "silence on the extermination" (Lacoue-Labarthe) and his refusal to engage in a thorough deconstruction of Nazism beyond laying out certain of his considerable objections to party orthodoxies and (particularly in the case of Lacoue-Labarthe) their passage through [[Nietzsche]], [[Hölderlin]], and [[Richard Wagner]], all taken to be susceptible to Nazi appropriation. It would be reasonable to say that both Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida regarded Heidegger as capable of confronting Nazism in this more radical fashion and have themselves undertaken such work on the basis of this. (One ought to note in due course the questions Derrida raised in "Desistance," calling attention to Lacoue-Labarthe's parenthetical comment: "(in any case, Heidegger never avoids anything)").
  
Lacoue-Labarthe and [[Jacques Derrida]] have both commented extensively on Heidegger's corpus, and both have identified an idiomatically Heideggerian National Socialism that persisted until the end. It is perhaps of greater importance that Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida, following Celan to a degree, believed Heidegger capable of profound criticism of Nazism and the horrors it brought forth. They hold that Heidegger's greatest failure not to be his involvement in the National Socialist movement but his "silence on the extermination" (Lacoue-Labarthe) and refusal to elaborate a thorough deconstruction of Nazism beyond laying out certain of his considerable objections to party orthodoxies and (particularly in the case of Lacoue-Labarthe) their passage through [[Nietzsche]], [[Hölderlin]], and [[Richard Wagner]], taken to be susceptible to Nazi appropriation. It would be reasonable to say that both Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida regarded Heidegger as capable of engaging Nazism in this other fashion and have undertaken such work on the basis of this (one ought to note in due course the questions raised by Derrida in "Desistance" in calling attention to Lacoue-Labarthe's parenthetical comment: "(in any case, Heidegger never avoids anything)").
 
  
 
===Conclusion===
 
===Conclusion===
 
+
Heidegger's involvement with the Nazi movement, and his failure to regret or apologize for having done so, complicated many of his friendships and continues to complicate the reception of his work. It is debatable whether Heidegger was [[antisemitism|antisemitic]] or whether he was taken in by charismatic Nazi propaganda; nevertheless, he clearly sympathized with certain elements of Nazism. Whether this in any way resulted from his philosophy is still contested.
Heidegger's involvements with the Nazis and the lack of a clear apology for them complicated many of his friendships, and continues to complicate the reception of his work. It is disputable whether Heidegger was [[antisemitism|antisemitic]] or if he was taken in by the charismatic projections of Nazi propaganda, but he had clear sympathies for certain elements of Nazism. Whether this is in any way a result of his philosophy is still contested. It has also been noted that many parts of "Sein und Zeit" can be read as anti-democratic, anti-modernist and anti-liberal, e.g. the condemnations against the "lordship of the ''they''" (Herrschaft des Man), the "chatter" (Gerede) and the Dasein's ''Verfallenheit'' (roughly, being-fallen-to) the world.
+
Still, the mere possibility that Heidegger's affiliation with the Nazi party might have been an unfortunate consequence of his philosophical thinking appears sufficient for some people to discredit him as a philosopher. As [[Jean-François Lyotard]] remarked, the formula becomes "if a Nazi, then not a great thinker" or, on the other hand, "if a great thinker, then not a Nazi".
 
+
This may well be a great over simpilification and deep misjudgement though. It is certainly used by many who don't like his philosophy as an excuse to easily disregard or discredit him.
The possibility that Heidegger's affiliation with the Nazi party was the result of his philosophy would lead many to discredit Heidegger as a philosopher solely on this basis, as [[Jean-François Lyotard]] remarked, the formula becomes "if a Nazi, then not a great thinker" or, conversely, "if a great thinker, then not a Nazi").
 
 
 
 
== Further reading ==
 
== Further reading ==
 +
There is a large secondary literature on Heidegger's philosophy, much of it not in English.  Accessible commentaries on ''Being and Time'' include
 +
*[[Hubert Dreyfus]], ''Being-in-the-World''
 +
*[[Theodore Kisiel]], ''The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time''
 +
*Mulhall, Stephen, ''Heidegger and Being and Time''
 +
*[[Reiner Schürmann]], ''Heidegger on Being and Acting: From Principles to Anarchy''.
  
There is a large secondary literature on Heidegger's philosophy.  Accessible commentaries on ''Being and Time'' include
+
By far the best and most even-handed biography of Heidegger, and also perhaps the best introduction to his thought, is  
 +
*[[Rüdiger Safranski]]'s ''Heidegger. Between Good and Evil'' ,
  
*''Being-in-the-World'' by [[Hubert Dreyfus]],
+
the English translation of his ''Ein Meister aus Deutschland'' (the title alludes to [[Paul Celan]]'s "Todesfuge").
*''The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time'' by [[Theodore Kisiel]], and
 
*''Heidegger and Being and Time'' by Stephen Mulhall.
 
*''Heidegger on Being and Acting: From Principles to Anarchy'' by [[Reiner Schürmann]].
 
 
 
By far the best and most even-handed biography of Heidegger, which also is perhaps the best introduction to his thought, is
 
 
 
*[[Rüdiger Safranski]]'s ''Heidegger. Between Good and Evil''
 
 
 
which is the English translation of his ''Ein Meister aus Deutschland'' (the title is an allusion to [[Paul Celan]]'s "Todesfugue").
 
 
 
More information on the subject of Heidegger's political history can be found in
 
  
 +
More about Heidegger's political history can be found in
 
*[[Victor Farías]]'s 1987 book, ''[[Heidegger and Nazism]]''.  
 
*[[Victor Farías]]'s 1987 book, ''[[Heidegger and Nazism]]''.  
  
It should be noted that in many philosophical circles, Farias' arguments are controversial, and many of his conclusions are contested.
+
Farias' arguments are controversial in many philosophical circles, which also contest most of his conclusions. Less controversial examinations of the relation between Heidegger's politics and philosophy are:
 
+
*[[Dominique Janicaud]], ''The Shadow of That Thought''.  
*[[Dominique Janicaud]]'s ''The Shadow of That Thought''.  
+
*Ott, Hugo, 1993. ''Martin Heidegger: A political life''.  Translated by Allan Blunden. Basic Books.
 
+
*[[Hans Sluga]], ''Heidegger's Crisis: Philosophy & Politics in Nazi Germany''.
*[[Hans Sluga]]'s book ''Heidegger's Crisis: Philosophy & Politics in Nazi Germany''  
+
*[[Faye, Emmanuel]], 2005, ''[[Heidegger, l'introduction du nazisme dans la philosophie. Autour des seminaires inedits de 1933-35]]''.
 
 
gives a fair examination of the relations between philosophy and politics. Similar questions have been taken up from a philosophical perspective by (among others)
 
  
 +
Related questions have been taken up from a philosophical perspective by (among others)
 +
*[[Bourdieu]] in ''The Political Ontology of Martin Heidegger'', and
 
*[[Jacques Derrida|Derrida]] in ''Of Spirit'',  
 
*[[Jacques Derrida|Derrida]] in ''Of Spirit'',  
*[[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]] in ''Typography''  
+
*[[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]] in ''Typography''
*''Heidegger, Art, and Politics: The Fiction of the Political'' trans. Chris Turner (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990) and
+
*[[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]], ''Heidegger, Art, and Politics: The Fiction of the Political'' trans. Chris Turner (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990) and
*''Poetry as Experience'',
+
*[[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]], ''Poetry as Experience'',
*[[Bourdieu]] in ''The Political Ontology of Martin Heidegger'', and
 
 
*[[Lyotard]] in ''Heidegger and "the Jews"''.
 
*[[Lyotard]] in ''Heidegger and "the Jews"''.
 +
 +
The role of Heidegger's influence in France has been repeatedly documented. See
 +
*[[Dominique Janicaud]], ''Heidegger en France'', 2 vols. [Paris: Albin Michel, 2001]
 +
*[[Bernhard Waldenfels]], ''Phänomenologie in Frankreich'', [Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Vlg, 1983].
  
 
Also cited above:
 
Also cited above:
 
 
*[[Jacques Derrida|Derrida]], et al in ''Penser à Strasbourg''
 
*[[Jacques Derrida|Derrida]], et al in ''Penser à Strasbourg''
 
*[[Jean-François Lyotard|Lyotard]] in ''Political Writings''
 
*[[Jean-François Lyotard|Lyotard]] in ''Political Writings''
  
==Selected Bibliography==
+
==Bibliography==
 +
===''Gesamtausgabe''===
 +
Heidegger's collected works are published by Vittorio Klostermann, Heidegger's house press, in Frankfurt am Main. It was started already by Heidegger himself and is not completed yet.  There are four series, (I) Publications, (II) Lectures, and (III) Unpublished  material, lectures, and notes, and (IV), ''Hinweise und Aufzeichnungen''.
  
*''Gelassenheit'' (1959).  Translated as ''Discourse On Thinking''.
+
===Selected works===
*''Identität und Differenz'' (1955-57). Translated as ''Identity and Difference''.
+
*''Sein und Zeit'' (1927). Translated as ''[[Being and Time]]''.
 
*''Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik'' (1929). Translated as ''Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics''.
 
*''Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik'' (1929). Translated as ''Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics''.
 +
*''Einführung in die Metaphysik'' (1935, published 1953). Translated as ''Introduction to Metaphysics''.
 +
*''Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis)'' (1936-1938, published 1989). Translated as ''Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning)''.
 +
*''Holzwege'' (1950). Translated as ''Off the Beaten Track''.
 
*''Der Satz vom Grund'' (1955-56). Translated as ''The Principle of Reason''.
 
*''Der Satz vom Grund'' (1955-56). Translated as ''The Principle of Reason''.
*''Sein und Zeit'' (1927). Translated as ''Being and Time''.
+
*''Identität und Differenz'' (1955-57). Translated as ''Identity and Difference''.
 +
*''Gelassenheit'' (1959).  Translated as ''Discourse On Thinking''.
 
*''Unterwegs zur Sprache'' (1959). Translated as ''On the Way To Language'' with the omission of the essay ''Die Sprache'' (''Language'') by arrangement with Herr Heidegger.
 
*''Unterwegs zur Sprache'' (1959). Translated as ''On the Way To Language'' with the omission of the essay ''Die Sprache'' (''Language'') by arrangement with Herr Heidegger.
 +
*''[[Question Concerning Technology]]'' [http://www.culturaleconomics.atfreeweb.com/Anno/Heidegger%20The%20Question%201954.htm]
  
 
==Cinema==
 
==Cinema==
 
*A [[2004]] film, ''[[The Ister]],'' is based on Heidegger's 1942 lectures on Friedrich [[Friedrich Hölderlin|Hölderlin]], and features [[Jean-Luc Nancy]], [[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]], [[Bernard Stiegler]], and [[Hans-Juergen Syberberg]]. * [http://www.theister.com/ Official site]
 
*A [[2004]] film, ''[[The Ister]],'' is based on Heidegger's 1942 lectures on Friedrich [[Friedrich Hölderlin|Hölderlin]], and features [[Jean-Luc Nancy]], [[Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe]], [[Bernard Stiegler]], and [[Hans-Juergen Syberberg]]. * [http://www.theister.com/ Official site]
 +
*A [[1979]] film, ''[[Being There]]'', is based upon a political, [[satirical]] 1971 novel by [[Jerzy Kosiński]], and is a comedic spoof of Heidegger's notions of ''Dasein'' (Being There) and getting back to one's roots (our forgetfulness of Being).  The film stars [[Peter Sellers]], [[Shirley MacLaine]], [[Melvyn Douglas]], [[Jack Warden]], [[Richard A. Dysart]] and [[Richard Basehart]].
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
 
{{wikiquote}}
 
{{wikiquote}}
 +
*[http://www.transordinator.de/erzaehler/1.html Be there...] Act out Heidegger's concept of time.
 +
*[http://www.phenomenology.ro/?page=studia_all_issues&id=160 Translating Heidegger's Sein und Zeit. Twenty-Two Translators of "Being and Time" in: Studia Phaenomenologica V (2005)]
 
*[http://www.phainomena.de phainomena.de] ''Heidegger-Blog (German)'' – Literature, activities and news about Hermeneutical Phenomenology
 
*[http://www.phainomena.de phainomena.de] ''Heidegger-Blog (German)'' – Literature, activities and news about Hermeneutical Phenomenology
 
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/h/heidegge.htm "Martin Heidegger" <nowiki>[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]</nowiki>] - Informative article, summarizing Heidegger's philosophy, including his theories on ''Angst'', and criticisms from other philosophers such as Husserl.
 
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/h/heidegge.htm "Martin Heidegger" <nowiki>[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]</nowiki>] - Informative article, summarizing Heidegger's philosophy, including his theories on ''Angst'', and criticisms from other philosophers such as Husserl.
 
* [http://www.denisdutton.com/heidegger.htm "Kaufmann, Heidegger, and Nazism"] by Denis Dutton, ''Philosophy and Literature'' 12 (1988): 325-36. A positive review of [[Walter Kaufmann]]'s and [[George Steiner]]'s negative treatments of Heidegger
 
* [http://www.denisdutton.com/heidegger.htm "Kaufmann, Heidegger, and Nazism"] by Denis Dutton, ''Philosophy and Literature'' 12 (1988): 325-36. A positive review of [[Walter Kaufmann]]'s and [[George Steiner]]'s negative treatments of Heidegger
 
*[http://www.egwald.com/ubcstudent/theory/heidegger.php Hearing Heidegger and Saussure] by Elmer G. Wiens.
 
*[http://www.egwald.com/ubcstudent/theory/heidegger.php Hearing Heidegger and Saussure] by Elmer G. Wiens.
 +
*[http://www.phenomenology.ro/?page=studia_all_issues&id=27 The Early Heidegger in Studia Phaenomenologica I 3-4/2001]
 +
* [http://www.waste.org/~roadrunner/writing/thesis.htm "Viewing Power in Heidegger and Levinas"] by Mitchell Cowen Verter
 +
* [http://parolesdesjours.free.fr/scandale.htm "Heideggerians response to Emmanuel Faye on Heidegger and nazism"] In French.
 +
*[http://www.appep.net/heidegger.html "Nazi fundations of Heidegger's Work"] by Emmanuel Faye, with a discussion. In French.
 +
*[http://aps.sulb.uni-saarland.de/theologie.geschichte/inhalt/2006/07.html "For the opening of Heidegger's Archives"] by Emmanuel Faye. In French.
 +
  
[[Category:1889 births|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:1976 deaths|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
 
[[Category:20th century philosophers|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:20th century philosophers|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:Continental philosophers|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:Continental philosophers|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:Deconstruction|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:Deconstruction|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:German philosophers|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:German philosophers|Heidegger, Martin]]
 +
[[Category:Nazis|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:Nazism|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:Nazism|Heidegger, Martin]]
[[Category:Nazis|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
 
[[Category:Phenomenology|Heidegger, Martin]]
 
[[Category:Phenomenology|Heidegger, Martin]]
 +
[[Category:Philosophers of Technology|Heidegger, Martin]]
 +
[[Category:Philosophers|Heidegger, Martin]]
 +
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
  
[[bn:মার্টিন হাইডেগার]]
 
[[cs:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[de:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[et:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[es:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[fr:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[hr:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[it:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[he:מרטין היידגר]]
 
[[ka:ჰაიდეგერი, მარტინ]]
 
[[lt:Martinas Haidegeris]]
 
[[hu:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[nl:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[ja:マルティン・ハイデッガー]]
 
[[no:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[pl:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[pt:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[ro:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[ru:Хайдеггер, Мартин]]
 
[[sk:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[fi:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[sv:Martin Heidegger]]
 
[[tr:Martin Heidegger]]
 
  
{{credit|24702717}}
+
{{Credit|46374882}}

Revision as of 22:30, 31 March 2006

Western Philosophers
20th-century philosophy
200px
Name: Martin Heidegger
Birth: September 26, 1889 (Meßkirch, Germany)
Death: May 26, 1976 (Meßkirch, Germany)
School/tradition: Phenomenology, Existentialism
Main interests
Metaphysics, Epistemology, Greek philosophy, technology, Ontology
Notable ideas
Dasein, Gestell
Influences Influenced
Pre-Socratics, Plato, Aristotle, Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Husserl Jean-Paul Sartre, Jacques Derrida, Maurice Merleau-Ponty Michel Foucault

Martin Heidegger (September 26, 1889 – May 26, 1976) was a German philosopher. An influence on many other major philosophers, his own students at various times included Hans-Georg Gadamer, Hans Jonas, Emmanuel Levinas, Hannah Arendt, Xavier Zubiri and Karl Löwith. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Jean-Paul Sartre, Jacques Derrida, Michel Foucault, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe also studied his work more or less closely. Beyond his relation to phenomenology, Heidegger is regarded as a major or indispensable influence on existentialism, deconstruction, hermeneutics and postmodernism. He attempted to reorient Western philosophy away from metaphysical and epistemological and toward ontological questions, that is, questions concerning the meaning of being, or what it means "to-be". Much controversy has surrounded his status as a prominent academic member of the Nazi Party.

Biography

Heidegger was born in a rural Roman Catholic family in Messkirch, Germany. His father was the sexton of the village church. His family could not afford to send him to university and he entered a Jesuit seminary instead. After studying Theology at the University of Freiburg from 1909 to 1911, he switched to Philosophy, receiving his PhD in 1914 with a thesis on Psychologism, and the venia legendi in Philosophy with a Habilitation thesis on Duns Scotus in 1916. 1916-17, he was an unsalaried Privatdozent, then served as a soldier during the last year of World War I, working behind a desk and never leaving Germany. After the war, he served as a salaried senior assistant to Edmund Husserl at the University of Freiburg until 1923. During this time, he built his mountain cabin, the Hütte, in Todtnauberg in the nearby Schwarzwald. In 1923, he was elected to an extraordinary Professorship (full professor but without a Chair) in Philosophy at the equally reputable but very Protestant University of Marburg. At Marburg his colleagues included Rudolf Bultmann, Ernst Friedländer, Nicolai Hartmann, and Paul Natorp, and his notable students, Hans-Georg Gadamer, Karl Löwith, Gerhard Krüger, Leo Strauss, and Hannah Arendt. When Husserl retired in 1928, Heidegger, having published Sein und Zeit the previous year, accepted Freiburg's election to be his successor, in spite of a counter-offer by Marburg. Heidegger remained at Freiburg for the rest of his life, declining a number of later offers including one from Berlin, the most prestigious German university of the day. In 1933, he became a member of the NSDAP (Nazi party), to which he had been close since 1931, and was appointed Rector of the University. His inaugural address, his "Rektoratsrede," became notorious. He resigned the Rectorship in 1934, but never resigned from the Nazi party. In 1945/47, the French Occupation Authority forbade him to teach because of his Nazi past, a decision rescinded in 1951 when he became Professor emeritus with all privileges. He then taught on regularly from 1951 and 1958, and until 1967 by invitation. He died in 1976, was given a Roman Catholic funeral, and is buried in the Meßkirch cemetery.

Personal and Family Life

In 1917, Heidegger married Elfriede Petri, in a Protestant wedding. She has been blamed for being a negative influence on him, by virtue of her strong anti-Semitic and Nazi sympathies. Heidegger had several extramarital affairs, including two very important ones with Jewish women who were his students, Hannah Arendt and Elisabeth Blochmann, with whom he remained in contact for the rest of his life (except during World War II). Only with the recent publication of the letters between Martin and Elfriede Heidegger in 2005 did it become known that the Heidegger marriage was an "open" one, in that Elfriede likewise had affairs, including one with the family doctor who fathered her first son, Hermann Heidegger.

Philosophy

Heidegger is one of the most significant philosophers of the 20th century, and his ideas have penetrated into many areas. His discussion of ontology has led to his being often cited as one of the founders of existentialism and his ideas inspired major philosophical work, e.g., Sartre, who adopts many of Heidegger's ideas (although Heidegger insisted that Sartre misunderstood him). His philosophical work was taken up throughout Germany, France, and Japan and has gained, since the 1970s at least, a fair following in North America as well. Heidegger's work was scorned and dismissed, however, by many of his contemporaries, such as the Vienna Circle, Theodor Adorno, and Anglo-American philosophers such as Bertrand Russell and Alfred Ayer.

Heidegger's refusal to recognize concepts such as the fact-value distinction, his criticisms of logic, modern science, and technology, and his refusal to include an "ethical" dimension to his theory, and claiming that doing so amounted to a fundamental misunderstanding of his thought, often puzzled and confused philosophers. Thus he has been attacked on these philosophical points and in regards to his political and personal behavior.

His philosophy also has been read as opening up the possibility for dialogue with traditions of thought outside the western philosophy, particularly East Asian thinking. This is an ambigous aspect of Heidegger's philosophy, because his notions such "language as the house of being" precisely seem to rule out such a possiblity. Eastern and western thought literally and metaphorically don't speak the same language. However certain elements in Heidegger's latter work, paticularly the dialogue between A Japanese and an Inquirer, do show an interest in such a dialogue occurring. Heidegger himself had contact with a number of leading Japanese intellectuals of his time in the Kyoto School. Further more it has also been claimed that a number of elements within Heidegger's thought bear a close parallel to eastern philosophical ideas, particularly with Zen Buddhism and Daoism.

Influences

Heidegger was influenced as a teenager by Aristotle mediated through Christian theology. The concept of being, which in the traditional sense can be dated back to Plato, made up his first exposure to an idea that he would later plant at the core of his most famous work Being and Time (1927). Originally, he would have to be called a phenomenologist. The phenomenological approach to philosophy can be briefly sketched as an attempt to perceive experience unmediated by any prior knowledge and thus as a way of trying to reach the thing itself, bypassing every abstract theoretical assumption of it. Edmund Husserl was a founder and major exponent of this philosophical branch, and also Heidegger's teacher and mentor. In spite of some disagreements over method phenomenology no doubt held a special place for Heidegger throughout the evolution of his thinking, even though he became more and more interested in the specific question of being (or what it means to be). He himself characterizes his famous work Being and Time as phenomenological ontology. The idea of being can at the very least be tracked back to Parmenides and has traditionally served as one of the key thoughts of Western philosophy. The question of being was so to speak revived by Heidegger after being eclipsed by the metaphysical tradition from Plato to Descartes, and even more recently during the Enlightenment. Heidegger sought to explain being in terms of time, and thus to discover its real essence or meaning, that is, its intelligibility for us.

In this manner Heidegger began where being began — in ancient Greek thought, resurrecting a lost and under-appreciated issue in contemporary philosophy. Heidegger's great opening was to take Plato seriously again, and at the same time undermine the entire Platonic world by challenging the core of Platonism — treating being not as timeless and transcendent, but instead as embedded in time and history. This is partially why Platonists tend to regard Heidegger as a great thinker, even if they disagree with his analysis of Being and his conception of Platonic thought. Although Heidegger was a supremely creative and original thinker, he at the same time borrowed heavily from Friedrich Nietzsche and Søren Kierkegaard, the latter of whom is mostly referred to in footnotes. Heidegger can be compared to Aristotle, who took Plato's dialogues and systematically presented them as treatises and conceptual structures. Similarly, Heidegger extracted Nietzsche's unpublished fragments and interpreted them as the culminating expression of Western metaphysics. It must be said though that Heidegger's published lectures during 1936 on Nietzsche’s Will to Power as Art are less scholarly commentaries than original philosophical works in their own right. Heidegger's concepts of angst and Da-sein manifestly draw on Kierkegaard's notions of anxiety, furthermore Heidegger is indebted to the way in which Kierkegaard lays out the importance of our subjective relation to the truth, our existence in the face of death, the temporality of existence, and the importance of passionate affirmation of one's individual being-in-the-world. Nonetheless, it is important to notice the difference between a Danish philosopher operating inside the Christian framework and Heidegger, who largely gave his thought free play.

Being and Time

Main article: Being and Time

Being and Time (German title: Sein und Zeit), published in 1927, is Heidegger's most influential work. This epochal book was his first significant academic work, and earned him a professorship at Freiburg University. He subsequently changed his views on several points made in the book. It is a touchstone of Continental philosophy, a groundbreaking investigation of the concepts of Being & Da-sein (literally "existence" and, often translated by its components, "being-there"), as these relate to ontology and phenomenology. Although Heidegger distanced himself from existentialism, Being and Time strongly influenced existentialist thinkers like Jean-Paul Sartre.

Later works

Although Heidegger claimed that all of his writings concerned a single question, the question of being, in the years after the publication of Being and Time the focus of his work gradually changed. This change is often referred to as Heidegger's Kehre (turn). In his later works, Heidegger turns from "doing" to "dwelling." He focuses less on the way in which the structures of being are revealed in everyday behavior and in the experience of Angst, and more on the way in which behavior itself depends on a prior "openness to being." The essence of being human is the maintenance of this openness. (The difference between Heidegger's early and late works is more a difference of emphasis than a radical break like that between the early and late works of Wittgenstein, but it is important enough to justify a division of the Heideggerian corpus into "early" (roughly, pre-1930) and "late" writings.)

Heidegger opposes this openness to the "will to power" of the modern human subject, who subordinates beings to his own ends rather than letting them "be what they are." Heidegger interprets the history of western philosophy as a brief period of authentic openness to being in the time of the pre-Socratics, especially Parmenides, Heraclitus, and Anaximander, followed by a long period increasingly dominated by nihilistic subjectivity, initiated by Plato and culminating in Nietzsche.

In the later writings, two recurring themes are poetry and technology. Heidegger sees poetry as a preeminent way in which beings are revealed "in their being." The play of poetic language (which is, for Heidegger, the essence of language itself) reveals the play of presence and absence that is being itself. Heidegger focuses especially on the poetry of Hölderlin.

Against the revealing power of poetry, Heidegger sets the force of technology. The essence of technology is the conversion of the whole universe of beings into an undifferentiated "standing reserve" (Bestand) of energy available for any use to which humans choose to put it. The standing reserve represents the most extreme nihilism, since the being of beings is totally subordinated to the will of the human subject. Indeed, Heidegger described the essence of technology as Gestell, or enframing. Heidegger does not unequivocally condemn technology; he believes that its increasing dominance might make it possible for humanity to return to its authentic task of the stewardship of being. Nevertheless, an unmistakable agrarian nostalgia permeates much of his later work.

Heidegger's important later works include Vom Wesen der Wahrheit ("On the Essence of Truth," 1930), Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes ("The Origin of the Work of Art," 1935), Bauen Wohnen Denken ("Building Dwelling Thinking," 1951), and Die Frage nach der Technik ("The Question of Technology," 1953) and Was heisst Denken? ("What Is Called Thinking?" 1954).


Heidegger and Eastern thought

Heidegger's philosophy has been read as opening up the possibility for dialogue with traditions of thought outside of Western philosophy, paticularly East Asian thinking. This is an ambigous aspect of Heidegger's philosophy, insofar as his notions such as "language as the house of being" seem precisely to rule out such a possiblity. Eastern and Western thought literally and metaphorically don't speak the same language. However certain elements in Heidegger's latter work, particularly the dialogue between A Japanese and an Inquirer, do show an interest in such a dialogue occurring. Heidegger himself had contact with an number of leading Japanese intellectuals of his time in the Kyoto School. Further more it has also claimed that a number of elements within Heidegger's thought bear a close parallel to Eastern philosophical ideas, paticularly with Zen Buddhism and Daoism

Influences and difficulties of French reception

Heidegger, like Husserl, is an explicitly acknowledged influence on existentialism, despite his explicit disavowal and objection, in texts such as the "Letter on Humanism," of the importation of key elements of his work into existentialist contexts. While Heidegger was banned from university teaching for a period shortly after the war on account of his activities as Rector of Freiburg, he developed a number of contacts in France who continued to teach his work and brought their students to visit him in Todtnauberg (see, for example, Jean-François Lyotard's brief account in "Heidegger and 'the Jews': A Conference in Vienna and Freiburg," which discusses a Franco-German conference held in Freiburg in 1947, a first step in bringing together French and German students after the War). Heidegger subsequently made efforts to keep abreast of developments in French philosophy by way of recommendations from Jean Beaufret, who was an early French translator, and Lucien Braun.

Deconstruction as it is generally understood (i.e., as French and Anglo-American phenomena profoundly rooted in Heidegger's work, with limited general exposure in a German context until the 1980s) came to Heidegger's attention in 1967 by way of Lucien Braun's recommendation of Jacques Derrida's work (Hans-Georg Gadamer was present at an initial discussion and indicated to Heidegger that Derrida's work came to his attention by way of an assistant). Heidegger expressed interest in meeting Derrida personally after the latter sent him some of his work. (There was discussion of a meeting in 1972, but this did not happen.) Heidegger's interest in Derrida is said by Braun to have been considerable (as is evident in two letters, of 29 September 1967 and 16 May 1972, from Heidegger to Braun). Braun also brought to Heidegger's attention the work of Michel Foucault. Foucault's relation to Heidegger is a matter of considerable difficulty; Foucault acknowledged Heidegger as a philosopher whom he read but never wrote about. (For more on this see Penser à Strasbourg, Jacques Derrida, et al, which includes reproductions of both letters and an account by Braun, "À mi-chemin entre Heidegger et Derrida").

One feature that garnered initial interest in a French context (which propagated rather quickly to scholars of French literature and philosophy working in American universities) was Derrida's efforts to displace the understanding of Heidegger's work that had been prevalent in France from the period of the ban against Heidegger teaching in German universities, which amounts in part to an almost wholesale rejection of the influence of Jean-Paul Sartre and existentialist terms. In Derrida's view, deconstruction is a tradition inherited via Heidegger (the French term "déconstruction" is a term coined to translate Heidegger's use of the words "Destruktion" - literally "destruction" - and "Abbau" - more literally "de-building"), whereas Sartre's interpretation of Dasein and other key Heideggerian terms is overly psychologistic and (ironically) anthropocentric, consisting of a radical misconception of the limited number of Heidegger's texts commonly studied in France up to that point (namely Being and Time, What is Metaphysics?, and Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics). Derrida, on the other hand, is at times presented as an ultra-orthodox "French Heidegger," to the extent that he, his colleagues, and his former students are made to go proxy for Heidegger's worst (political) mistakes, despite ample evidence that the reception of Heidegger's work by later practitioners of deconstruction is anything but doctrinaire. The work of Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe may be taken as exemplary in this regard and was often commended as such by Derrida, who further contrasted Lacoue-Labarthe's extended work on Heidegger with Foucault's silence.

Having earlier mentioned the contributions of Derrida, Lacoue-Labarthe, and Lyotard to scholarship on Heidegger and National Socialism, it is worth noting that Heidegger's relation to the Holocaust and Nazism was the subject of great and occasionally fractious debate across various "deconstructions". These included the extent to which specific practitioners of deconstruction could entirely do without Heideggerian deconstruction (as Lyotard in particular may have wished) or were - rather - obliged to further (and in the cases of many mis- and uninformed criticisms, recall) already extensive criticisms of Heidegger which considerably predated (in the case of Derrida, by decades) the broad recognition of Heidegger's activities as a National Socialist. The latter were precipitated by press attention to the Víctor Farías book "Heidegger et le nazisme" (Farias was an ex-student of Heidegger) and extensive treatments of the Holocaust and its implications. These included for example, the proceedings of the first conference dedicated to Derrida's work, published as "Les Fins de l'Homme" (the essay from which that title was taken), Derrida's "Feu la cendre/cio' che resta del fuoco", or the studies on Celan by Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida which shortly preceded the detailed studies of Heidegger's politics published in and after 1987.


Criticism

Heidegger's importance to the world of continental philosophy (a subject he is even said by some to have created, although there was some distinction between continental and analytic philosophy before him, the origins of continental philosophy being traceable to romanticism and analytic philosophy to utiliterianism), is probably unsurpassed. His reception among analytic philosophers, however, is quite another story. Saving a moderately favorable review in Mind by a young Gilbert Ryle of Being and Time shortly after its publication, Heidegger's analytic contemporaries (a field still young, but already quite sharply delineated from other branches of philosophy) generally regarded both the content, if any, and the style in which he delivered it, as examples of the worst possible way of doing philosophy.

The analytic tradition values clarity of expression, whereas Heidegger thought that "making itself intelligible was suicide for philosophy." Apart from the charge of obscurantism, analytic philosophers generally considered the actual content that could be gleaned from Heidegger's work to be either faulty and frivolous, unpalatably subjective or uninteresting. This view has largely survived, and Heidegger is still derided by most analytical philosophers, who deem his work to have been disastrous for philosophy, in that a clear line can be traced from it to most varieties of postmodern thinking. Others have accused Heidegger of having an 'illusory' ontology and have decried his influence on subsequent philosophy[citation needed].

His reputation has improved slightly through the impact of Richard Rorty's philosophy on the English-speaking world; Rorty even claims that Heidegger's approach to philosophy in the second half of his career has much in common with that of the latter-day Wittgenstein - one of the giants of analytical philosophy.

Heidegger and Nazi Germany

Heidegger joined the Nazi Party on May 1, 1933, before being appointed Rector of the University of Freiburg. He resigned the Rectorship in April 1934. However, he remained a member of the Nazi party until the end of the war. During his time as Rector, Freiburg denied Heidegger's former teacher Husserl, born a Jew and an adult Lutheran convert, access of the university library, invoking the Nazi racial cleansing laws. Heidegger also removed the dedication to Husserl from Being and Time when it was reissued in 1941, later claiming he did so because of pressure from his publisher, Max Niemeyer. Additionally, when Heidegger's Introduction to Metaphysics (based on lectures given in 1935) was published in 1953, he declined to remove a reference to the "inner truth and greatness of this movement [die innere Wahrheit und Größe dieser Bewegung]," i.e. National Socialism. Instead of deleting or altering the text, he added the parenthetical gloss, "(namely, the confrontation of planetary technology and modern humanity) (nämlich [die] Begegnung der planetarisch bestimmten Technik und des neuzeitlichen Menschen)." Many readers, notably Jürgen Habermas, came to interpret this ambiguous remark as evidence of his continued commitment to National Socialism.

Critics further cite Heidegger's affair with Hannah Arendt, who was Jewish, while she was his doctoral student at the University of Marburg. This affair took place in the 1920s, some time before Heidegger's involvement in Nazism, but it did not end when she moved to Heidelberg to continue with Karl Jaspers. She later spoke on his behalf at his denazification hearings. Jaspers spoke against him at these same hearings, suggesting he would have a detrimental influence on German students because of his powerful teaching presence. Arendt very cautiously resumed their friendship after the war, despite or even because of the widespread contempt for Heidegger and his political sympathies, and despite his being forbidden to teach for some years.

Der Spiegel interview

Some years later, hoping to quiet controversy, Heidegger gave an interview to Der Spiegel magazine, in which he agreed to discuss his political past provided that the interview be published posthumously. It should be noted that Heidegger extensively edited, at his insistance, the published version of the interview. In that interview, Heidegger's defense of his Nazi involvement runs in two tracks: first, he argued that there was no alternative, saying that he was trying to save the university (and science in general) from being politicized and thus had to compromise with the Nazi administration. Second, he saw an "awakening" ("Aufbruch") which might help to find a "new national and social approach". After 1934, he said, he would (should?) have been more critical of the Nazi government. Heidegger's answers to some questions are evasive. For example, when he talks about a "national and social approach" of national socialism, he links this to Friedrich Naumann. But Naumann's "national-sozialer Verein" was not at all national socialist, but liberal. Heidegger seems to have deliberately created this confusion. Also, he alternates quickly between his two lines of arguments, overlooking any contradictions. And his statements often tend to take the form "others were much more Nazi than me" and "the Nazis did bad things to me, too" which, while true, miss the point.

The Der Spiegel interviewers also did not bring up Heidegger's 1949 quotation where he compares engineered food production to the Holocaust ("essentially the same.") While Heidegger's defenders have attempted to account for this "similarity of essence" by reference to his essay "On the Essence of Truth," this account of the technological frame that now infects human nourishment and human mortality is not a conventional reaction to genocide. Moreover, many of those who align themselves with Heidegger philosophically have pointed out that in his own work on being-towards-death, we can recognize a much more salient criticism of what was wrong with the mass-produced murder of a people. Thinkers as diverse as Giorgio Agamben and Judith Butler have made this point sympathetically. Commentators differ on whether this philosophical shorthand is evidence of a profound disregard for the Jews or simply the astygmatism of an old man concerned more with his own legacy than with that of the Holocaust.

In fact, the Der Spiegel interviewers were not in possession of most of the evidence now known for Heidegger's Nazi sympathies. For more on this notorious interview and its aftermath, see "Only a God Can Save Us," Der Spiegel interview with Heidegger (1966) and Jürgen Habermas, "Work and Weltanschauung: The Heidegger Controversy from a German Perspective." translated by John McCumber, Critical Inquiry 15 (Winter 1989): 431-56.

Obligations and unsplendid silence: Celan at "Todtnauberg"

Shortly after giving the Spiegel interview and following Celan's lecture at Freiburg, Heidegger hosted Paul Celan at his chalet at Todtnauberg. The two walked in the woods. Celan impressed Heidegger with his knowledge of botany (also evident in his poetry), and Heidegger is thought to have spoken about elements of his press interview. Celan signed Heidegger's guest book.

In his Poetry as Experience, Lacoue-Labarthe advanced the argument that, although Celan's poetry was deeply informed by Heidegger's philosophy, Celan was long aware of Heidegger's association with the Nazi party and therefore fundamentally circumspect toward the man and transformative in his reception of his work. Celan was nonetheless willing to meet Heidegger (although he may not have been willing to be photographed with him or to contribute to Festschriften honoring Heidegger's work). Heidegger was a professed admirer of Celan's writing, although he did not attend to it as Hölderlin or Trakl (neither did he attend to Celan as a Jewish poet working within that German tradition). "Todtnauberg", however, seems to hold out the unrealized possibility of a profound rapprochement between their work, albeit on the condition that Heidegger break a silence that virtually blanketed his work to the end (Lacoue-Labarthe has commented on the insufficiency of Heidegger's one known remark about the gas chambers, made in 1949). In this respect Heidegger's work was perhaps redeemable for Celan, even if that redemption or what need was had for it was never transacted between the two men. Lest one implicitly take this as Celan simply demanding an apology of Heidegger (such a scenario seems simplistic, the more so given that neither was given to simplism), there are reasonable grounds to argue that it was (and still is) at least as important to specify how the Nazi period is das Unheil (disaster, calamity) (which is to say: specificity as to a great deal more than counting the dead). What compelled Heidegger to write about poetry, technology, and truth ought to have compelled him to write about the German disaster, all the more so because, on the basis of his thought, Heidegger attributed an "inner greatness" to the movement that brought about that disaster.

Lacoue-Labarthe and Jacques Derrida have both commented extensively on Heidegger's corpus, and both have identified an idiomatically Heideggerian National Socialism that persisted until the end. It is perhaps of greater importance that Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida, following Celan to a degree, also believed Heidegger capable of a profound criticism of Nazism and the horrors it brought forth. They consider Heidegger's greatest failure not to be his involvement in the National Socialist movement but his "silence on the extermination" (Lacoue-Labarthe) and his refusal to engage in a thorough deconstruction of Nazism beyond laying out certain of his considerable objections to party orthodoxies and (particularly in the case of Lacoue-Labarthe) their passage through Nietzsche, Hölderlin, and Richard Wagner, all taken to be susceptible to Nazi appropriation. It would be reasonable to say that both Lacoue-Labarthe and Derrida regarded Heidegger as capable of confronting Nazism in this more radical fashion and have themselves undertaken such work on the basis of this. (One ought to note in due course the questions Derrida raised in "Desistance," calling attention to Lacoue-Labarthe's parenthetical comment: "(in any case, Heidegger never avoids anything)").


Conclusion

Heidegger's involvement with the Nazi movement, and his failure to regret or apologize for having done so, complicated many of his friendships and continues to complicate the reception of his work. It is debatable whether Heidegger was antisemitic or whether he was taken in by charismatic Nazi propaganda; nevertheless, he clearly sympathized with certain elements of Nazism. Whether this in any way resulted from his philosophy is still contested. Still, the mere possibility that Heidegger's affiliation with the Nazi party might have been an unfortunate consequence of his philosophical thinking appears sufficient for some people to discredit him as a philosopher. As Jean-François Lyotard remarked, the formula becomes "if a Nazi, then not a great thinker" or, on the other hand, "if a great thinker, then not a Nazi". This may well be a great over simpilification and deep misjudgement though. It is certainly used by many who don't like his philosophy as an excuse to easily disregard or discredit him.

Further reading

There is a large secondary literature on Heidegger's philosophy, much of it not in English. Accessible commentaries on Being and Time include

  • Hubert Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World
  • Theodore Kisiel, The Genesis of Heidegger's Being and Time
  • Mulhall, Stephen, Heidegger and Being and Time
  • Reiner Schürmann, Heidegger on Being and Acting: From Principles to Anarchy.

By far the best and most even-handed biography of Heidegger, and also perhaps the best introduction to his thought, is

  • Rüdiger Safranski's Heidegger. Between Good and Evil ,

the English translation of his Ein Meister aus Deutschland (the title alludes to Paul Celan's "Todesfuge").

More about Heidegger's political history can be found in

  • Victor Farías's 1987 book, Heidegger and Nazism.

Farias' arguments are controversial in many philosophical circles, which also contest most of his conclusions. Less controversial examinations of the relation between Heidegger's politics and philosophy are:

  • Dominique Janicaud, The Shadow of That Thought.
  • Ott, Hugo, 1993. Martin Heidegger: A political life. Translated by Allan Blunden. Basic Books.
  • Hans Sluga, Heidegger's Crisis: Philosophy & Politics in Nazi Germany.
  • Faye, Emmanuel, 2005, Heidegger, l'introduction du nazisme dans la philosophie. Autour des seminaires inedits de 1933-35.

Related questions have been taken up from a philosophical perspective by (among others)

  • Bourdieu in The Political Ontology of Martin Heidegger, and
  • Derrida in Of Spirit,
  • Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe in Typography
  • Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Heidegger, Art, and Politics: The Fiction of the Political trans. Chris Turner (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1990) and
  • Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Poetry as Experience,
  • Lyotard in Heidegger and "the Jews".

The role of Heidegger's influence in France has been repeatedly documented. See

  • Dominique Janicaud, Heidegger en France, 2 vols. [Paris: Albin Michel, 2001]
  • Bernhard Waldenfels, Phänomenologie in Frankreich, [Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Vlg, 1983].

Also cited above:

  • Derrida, et al in Penser à Strasbourg
  • Lyotard in Political Writings

Bibliography

Gesamtausgabe

Heidegger's collected works are published by Vittorio Klostermann, Heidegger's house press, in Frankfurt am Main. It was started already by Heidegger himself and is not completed yet. There are four series, (I) Publications, (II) Lectures, and (III) Unpublished material, lectures, and notes, and (IV), Hinweise und Aufzeichnungen.

Selected works

  • Sein und Zeit (1927). Translated as Being and Time.
  • Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929). Translated as Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics.
  • Einführung in die Metaphysik (1935, published 1953). Translated as Introduction to Metaphysics.
  • Beiträge zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis) (1936-1938, published 1989). Translated as Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning).
  • Holzwege (1950). Translated as Off the Beaten Track.
  • Der Satz vom Grund (1955-56). Translated as The Principle of Reason.
  • Identität und Differenz (1955-57). Translated as Identity and Difference.
  • Gelassenheit (1959). Translated as Discourse On Thinking.
  • Unterwegs zur Sprache (1959). Translated as On the Way To Language with the omission of the essay Die Sprache (Language) by arrangement with Herr Heidegger.
  • Question Concerning Technology [1]

Cinema

  • A 2004 film, The Ister, is based on Heidegger's 1942 lectures on Friedrich Hölderlin, and features Jean-Luc Nancy, Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, Bernard Stiegler, and Hans-Juergen Syberberg. * Official site
  • A 1979 film, Being There, is based upon a political, satirical 1971 novel by Jerzy Kosiński, and is a comedic spoof of Heidegger's notions of Dasein (Being There) and getting back to one's roots (our forgetfulness of Being). The film stars Peter Sellers, Shirley MacLaine, Melvyn Douglas, Jack Warden, Richard A. Dysart and Richard Basehart.

External links

Wikiquote-logo-en.png
Wikiquote has a collection of quotations related to:


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.