Lyotard, Jean-François

From New World Encyclopedia
m (Robot: Remove date links)
 
(15 intermediate revisions by 7 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Contracted}}
+
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{Copyedited}}
{{epname}}
+
{{epname|Lyotard, Jean-François}}
 +
{{Infobox Philosopher
 +
<!-- Philosopher category —>
 +
|region = [[Western Philosophy]]
 +
|era    = [[20th-century philosophy]]
 +
|color  = #B0C4DE
 +
<!-- Image —>
 +
|image_name = Jean-Francois Lyotard.jpg
 +
<!-- Information —>
 +
|name            = Jean-François Lyotard
 +
|birth            = August 10, 1924<br/>{{flagicon|FRA|size=16px}} [[Versailles]], [[France]]
 +
|death            = April 21, 1998<br/>{{flagicon|FRA|size=16px}} [[Paris]], [[France]]
 +
|school_tradition = [[Postmodernism]]
 +
|main_interests  = [[Metanarrative]]
 +
|notable_ideas    = The "[[Postmodernity|postmodern condition]]"<br/>Collapse of the "[[Metanarrative|grand narrative]]"
 +
|influences      = [[Michel de Montaigne|Montaigne]]{{·}} [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]]{{·}} [[Karl Marx|Marx]]{{·}} [[Sigmund Freud|Freud]]<br/>[[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Wittgenstein]]{{·}} [[Talcott Parsons|Parsons]]{{·}} [[Émile Durkheim|Durkheim]]<br/>[[J. L. Austin|J.L. Austin]]
 +
|influenced      = [[Richard Rorty|Rorty]]{{·}} [[Roland Barthes|Barthes]]{{·}} [[Michel Foucault|Foucault]]{{·}} [[Jacques Derrida|Derrida]]<br/>[[Jean Baudrillard|Baudrillard]]
 +
}}
 +
'''Jean-François Lyotard''' ([[International Phonetic Alphabet|pronounced]] {{IPA|[ʒɑ̃ frɑ̃swa ljɔtaʀ]}}; August 10, 1924{{ndash}} April 21, 1998) was a [[France|French]] [[Philosophy|philosopher]] and [[Literary theory|literary theorist]]. He is well-known for his articulation of [[postmodernism]] after the late 1970s and the analysis of the impact of [[postmodernity]] on the [[human condition]]. He was a [[Marxism|Marxist]] but he was deeply disappointed with it and rejected any form of "grand narrative," a totalistic, universal theory which promises to explain and solve all problems by one set of ideas. Lyotard adopted [[Wittgenstein]]'s concept of "language games" and [[Kant]]'s theory of [[aesthetics]] for his analysis. Critics argue that postmodernism is a [[skepticism]] that presents no positive alternative. Lyotard, however, captured the [[pluralism|pluralistic]] tendencies of the late twentieth century.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
==Life==
  
'''Jean-François Lyotard''' (August 10 1924-April 21 1998) was a [[France|French]] [[philosopher]] and [[Literary theory|literary theorist]]. Among other things, he is well-known for his articulation of [[postmodernism]] after the late 1970s.  
+
He was born in [[Versailles]], France to Jean-Pierre Lyotard, a sale representative, and Madeleine. He went to primary school at the Paris [[Lycées Buffon]] and [[Louis-le-Grand]] and later began studying philosophy at the [[Sorbonne]]. He married [[Andrée May]] in 1948 and became a father. After graduation he took up a position teaching philosophy in [[Constantine, Algeria|Constantine ]] in French-occupied East Algeria in 1950.
  
==Political life==
+
===Political life===
Lyotard was a member of [[Socialisme ou Barbarie]], a political organisation formed in France in 1948 around a view of the inadequacy of the [[Trotskyist]] analysis of the new forms of domination in the Soviet Union. ''Socialisme ou Barbarie'' became increasingly anti-[[Marxist]] and Lyotard was prominent in the [[Pouvoir Ouvrier]] group who rejected that position and split in 1963. Later he became a founding member of the [[European Graduate School]].
 
==Overview==
 
== The collapse of the "Grand Narrative"==
 
Lyotard's work is characterised by a persistent opposition to universals, meta-narratives, and generality. He is fiercely critical of many of the 'universalist' claims of [[the Enlightenment]], and several of his works serve to undermine the fundamental principles that generate these broad claims. Most famously, in ''La Condition postmoderne: Rapport sur le savoir (The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge)'' (1979), he argued that our age (the postmodern condition of the book's title) is marked by an 'incredulity towards metanarratives'. These metanarratives - sometimes 'grand narratives' - are grand large scale theories and philosophies of the world: history as progress, the knowability of everything by science, the possibility of absolute freedom, etc. Lyotard argues that we have ceased to believe that these kinds of beliefs are adequate to represent and contain us all. We are much more alert to difference, diversity, the incompatibility of our aspirations, beliefs and desires, and for that reason postmodernity is characterised by an abundance of micronarratives. For this concept he is drawing on the notion of the '[[language game]]' to be found in the work of [[Wittgenstein]], though strongly reinterpreted.
 
  
In Lyotard's work the term, sometimes also called 'phrase regimens', denotes the multiplicity of communities of meaning, the innumerable and incommensurable separate systems in which meanings are produced and rules for their circulation are created.
+
In 1954, Lyotard became a member of [[Socialisme ou Barbarie]], a French political organisation formed in 1948 around the inadequacy of the [[Trotskyist]] analysis to explain the new forms of domination in the Soviet Union. ''Socialisme ou Barbarie'' became increasingly anti-[[Marxism|Marxist]] and Lyotard was prominent in the [[Pouvoir Ouvrier]], a group that rejected the position and split in 1963. His writings in this period are mostly concerned with ultra-left politics, with focus on the [[Algeria]]n situation, which he witnessed first hand while teaching philosophy in [[Constantine, Algeria|Constantine]].
  
This becomes more crucial in ''Au juste: Conversations (Just Gaming)'' (1979) and ''Le Différend (The Differend)'' (1983) which develop a postmodern theory of justice. It might appear that the atomisation of human beings implied by the notion of the micronarrative and the language game suggests a collapse of ethics. It has often been thought that universality is a condition for something to be a properly ethical statement: 'thou shall not steal' is an ethical statement in a way that 'thou shall not steal from Margaret' is not. The latter is too particular to be an ethical statement (what's so special about Margaret?); it is only ethical if it rests on a universal statement (such as the former: 'thou shall not steal'). But universals are impermissible in a world that has lost faith in metanarratives and so it would seem that ethics is impossible. Justice and injustice can only be terms within language games, and the universality of ethics is out of the window. Lyotard argues that notions of justice and injustice do in fact remain in postmodernism. The new definition of injustice is indeed to use the language rules from one 'phrase regimen' and apply it to another. Ethical behaviour is about remaining alert precisely to the threat of this injustice, of paying attention to things in their particularity and not to enclose them within abstract conceptuality. One must bear witness to the 'differend'.
+
===Academic career===
  
This may seem rather abstract though it can be (and has been) applied to thinking through colonial and imperial powers and the ways they impose a new system and definition of justice on another. One might say the same within particular cultures, in which, as Lyotard might put it, the cultural diversity that we often celebrate, is evidence of proliferating micronarratives that rule the metanarrative of justice out of court (pardon the pun). Such issues seem particularly pertinent in the aftermath of the terrorist atrocities (among others) of [[11 September 2001]] in New York, [[11 March 2004]] in Madrid, and [[7 July 2005]] in London. Is it just to impose one definition of freedom and justice on all our citizens?
+
In the early 1970s, Lyotard began teaching at the [[University of Paris VIII]], Vincennes until 1987 when he became Professor Emeritus. During the next two decades he lectured outside of France notably as a Professor of Critical Theory at the [[University of California, Irvine]] and as visiting professor at universities around the world including John Hopkins, Berkeley, [[Yale]], and San Diego in the States, the [[Université de Montréal]] in Canada and the [[University of São Paulo]] in Brazil. He was also a founding director and councile member of the [[Collège International de Philosophie]], [[Paris]]. Before his death, he split his time between Paris and Atlanta, where he taught at [[Emory University]] as a Woodruff Professor of Philosophy and French.
==Anti-foundationalism==
 
  
==The sublime==
+
===Later life and death===
Lyotard was a frequent writer on aesthetic matters. He was, despite his reputation as a postmodernist, a great promoter of [[modernist art]]. (It is worth commenting that Lyotard saw 'postmodernism' as a latent tendency within thought throughout time and not a narrowly-limited historical period.) He favoured the startling and perplexing works of the high modernist avant-garde. In them he found a demonstration of the limits of our conceptuality, a valuable lesson for anyone too imbued with Enlightenment confidence.  
+
Lyotard repeatedly returned to the notion of the Postmodern in essays gathered in [[England|English]] as ''[[The Postmodern Explained to Children]]'', ''[[Toward the Postmodern]]'', and ''[[Postmodern Fables]]''. In 1998, while preparing for a conference on [[Postmodernism]] and Media Theory, he died unexpectedly from a case of leukemia that had advanced rapidly. He is buried in [[Le Père Lachaise Cemetery]] in [[Paris]].
  
He developed these themes in particular by discussing the '[[sublime]]'. The sublime is a term in aesthetics whose fortunes revived under postmodernism after a century or more of neglect. It refers to the experience of pleasurable anxiety that we experience when confronting wild and threatening sights like, for example, a massive craggy mountain, black against the sky, looming terrifyingly in our vision.
+
== Thought ==
  
Lyotard found particularly interesting the explanation of the sublime offered by [[Immanuel Kant]] in his ''[[Critique of Judgment]]'' (sometimes ''Critique of the Power of Judgment''). In this book Kant explains this mixture of anxiety and pleasure in the following terms: there are two kinds of 'sublime' experience. In the 'mathematical' sublime, an object strikes the mind in such a way that we find ourselves unable to take it in as a whole. It is simply incalculably large. It outstrips our usual means of seeing it. In the 'dynamical' sublime, the mind recoils at an object so immeasurably more powerful than us, whose weight, force, scale could crush us without the remotest hope of our being able to resist it. (Kant stresses that if we are in ''actual'' danger, our feeling of anxiety is very different from that of a sublime feeling. The sublime is an aesthetic experience, not a practical feeling of personal danger.) This explains the feeling of anxiety.
+
=== The collapse of the "Grand Narrative"===
  
The feeling of pleasure comes when human reason asserts itself. What is deeply unsettling about the mathematical sublime is that the mental faculties that present visual perceptions to the mind are inadequate to the concept corresponding to it; in other words, what we are able to make ourselves see cannot fully match up to what we know is there. We know it's a mountain but we cannot take the whole thing into our perception. What this does, ironically, is to compel our awareness of the supremacy of the human reason. Our sensibility is incapable of coping with such sights, but our reason can take in the infinite. With the dynamical sublime, our sense of physical danger should prompt an awareness that we are not just physical material beings, but moral and (in Kant's terms) [[noumenal]] beings as well. The body may be crushed but our reason need not be. This explains, in both cases, why the sublime is an experience of pleasure as well as pain.
+
Lyotard's work is characterised by a persistent opposition to universals, [[meta-narrative]]s, and generality. He is fiercely critical of many of the 'universalist' claims of [[the Enlightenment]], and several of his works serve to undermine the fundamental principles that generate these broad claims. Most famously, in ''[[The Postmodern Condition|La Condition postmoderne: Rapport sur le savoir (The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge)]]'' (1979), he argued that our age (with its postmodern condition) is marked by an 'incredulity towards meta-narratives'. These meta-narratives—sometimes 'grand narratives'—are grand, large-scale theories and philosophies of the world, such as the progress of history, the knowability of everything by science, and the possibility of absolute [[freedom]]. Lyotard argues that we have ceased to believe that narratives of this kind are adequate to represent and contain us all. We have become alert to difference, diversity, the incompatibility of our aspirations, beliefs and desires, and for that reason postmodernity is characterised by an abundance of micronarratives. For this concept Lyotard draws on and strongly reinterprets the notion of '[[language-games]]' found in the work of [[Wittgenstein]].
  
Lyotard is fascinated by this admission, from one of the philosophical architects of the Enlightenment, that the mind cannot always organise the world rationally. Some objects are simply incapable of being brought neatly under concepts. For Lyotard, in ''Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime'', but drawing on his argument in ''The Differend'', this is a good thing. Such generalities as 'concepts' fail to pay proper attention to the particularity of things. What happens in the sublime is a crisis where we realise the inadequacy of the imagination and reason to each other. What we are witnessing, says Lyotard, is actually the differend; the straining of the mind at the edges of itself and at the edges of its conceptuality.  
+
In Lyotard's works, the term 'language games', sometimes also called 'phrase regimens', denotes the multiplicity of communities of meaning, the innumerable and incommensurable separate systems in which meanings are produced and rules for their circulation are created.
 +
 
 +
This becomes more crucial in ''Au juste: Conversations ([[Just Gaming]])'' (1979) and ''Le Différend ([[The Differend]])'' (1983), which develop a postmodern theory of [[justice]]. It might appear that the atomisation of human beings implied by the notion of the micronarrative and the language game suggests a collapse of [[ethics]]. It has often been thought that universality is a condition for something to be a properly ethical statement: 'thou shalt not steal' is an ethical statement in a way that 'thou shalt not steal from Margaret' is not. The latter is too particular to be an ethical statement (what's so special about Margaret?); it is only ethical if it rests on a universal statement ('thou shalt not steal from anyone'). But universals are impermissible in a world that has lost faith in metanarratives, and so it would seem that ethics is impossible. Justice and injustice can only be terms within language games, and the universality of ethics is out of the window. Lyotard argues that notions of justice and injustice do in fact remain in postmodernism. The new definition of injustice is indeed to use the language rules from one 'phrase regimen' and apply them to another. Ethical behaviour is about remaining alert precisely to the threat of this injustice, of paying attention to things in their particularity and not enclosing them within abstract conceptuality. One must bear witness to the 'differend'.
 +
 
 +
===The [[sublime (philosophy)|sublime]]===
 +
 
 +
Lyotard was a frequent writer on [[Aesthetics|aesthetic]] matters. He was, despite his reputation as a postmodernist, a great promoter of [[modernist art]]. (It is worth commenting that Lyotard saw 'postmodernism' as a latent tendency within thought throughout time and not a narrowly-limited historical period.) He favored the startling and perplexing works of the high modernist avant-garde. In them he found a demonstration of the limits of our conceptuality, a valuable lesson for anyone too imbued with Enlightenment confidence.
 +
 
 +
He developed these themes in particular by discussing the [[Sublime (philosophy)|sublime]]. The "sublime" is a term in aesthetics whose fortunes revived under postmodernism after a century or more of neglect. It refers to the experience of pleasurable anxiety that we experience when confronting wild and threatening sights like, for example, a massive craggy mountain, black against the sky, looming terrifyingly in our vision.
 +
 
 +
Lyotard found particularly interesting the explanation of the sublime offered by [[Immanuel Kant]] in his ''[[Critique of Judgment]]'' (sometimes ''Critique of the Power of Judgment''). In this book Kant explains this mixture of anxiety and pleasure in the following terms: there are two kinds of 'sublime' experience. In the 'mathematical' sublime, an object strikes the mind in such a way that we find ourselves unable to take it in as a whole. More precisely, we experience a clash between our reason (which tells us that all objects are finite) and the imagination (the aspect of the mind that organizes what we see, and which sees an object incalculably larger than ourselves, and feels infinite). In the 'dynamical' sublime, the mind recoils at an object so immeasurably more powerful than we, whose weight, force, scale could crush us without the remotest hope of our being able to resist it. (Kant stresses that if we are in ''actual'' danger, our feeling of anxiety is very different from that of a sublime feeling. The sublime is an [[aesthetics|aesthetic]] experience, not a practical feeling of personal danger.) This explains the feeling of anxiety.
 +
 
 +
The feeling of pleasure comes when human reason asserts itself. What is deeply unsettling about the mathematical sublime is that the mental faculties that present visual perceptions to the mind are inadequate to the concept corresponding to it; in other words, what we are able to make ourselves see cannot fully match up to what we know is there. We know it's a mountain but we cannot take the whole thing into our perception. What this does, ironically, is to compel our awareness of the supremacy of the human reason. Our sensibility is incapable of coping with such sights, but our reason can assert the finitude of the presentation. With the dynamical sublime, our sense of physical danger should prompt an awareness that we are not just physical material beings, but moral and (in Kant's terms) [[noumenal]] beings as well. The body may be dwarfed by its power but our reason need not be. This explains, in both cases, why the sublime is an experience of pleasure as well as pain.
 +
 
 +
Lyotard is fascinated by this admission, from one of the philosophical architects of the Enlightenment, that the mind cannot always organise the world rationally. Some objects are simply incapable of being brought neatly under concepts. For Lyotard, in ''[[Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime]]'', and drawing on his argument in ''[[The Differend]]'', this is a good thing. Such generalities as 'concepts' fail to pay proper attention to the particularity of things. What happens in the sublime is a crisis where we realize the inadequacy of the imagination and reason individually. What we are witnessing, says Lyotard, is actually the differend; the straining of the mind at the edges of itself and at the edges of its conceptuality.
  
 
==Criticism==
 
==Criticism==
Lyotard's ideas have often been criticized. His theories can seem self-contradictory. ''The Postmodern Condition'' seems to offer a pretty grand narrative in its story of the decline of the metanarrative. Similarly, one is entitled to ask, in respect of ''The Differend'', from which 'phrase regimen' does the term 'phrase regimen' come from, and why is it being used to describe them all? On what principle does the injustice of the 'differend' rest, given that it seems to be prior to and to describe relations between all phrase regimes. Such a position would seem to be that of a metanarrative which the book has surely ruled out? In his analysis of the ''sublime'' he appropriates Kant very loosely, ignoring the crucial second half of the experience of the sublime, the pleasurable recognition of reason's universality, which, of course, Lyotard will not accept.
+
Some argue that Lyotard's theories may seem self-contradictory because ''The Postmodern Condition'' seems to offer its own grand narrative in the story of the decline of the metanarrative. Against this it can be argued that Lyotard's narrative in ''The Postmodern Condition'' declares the decline of only a few defunct "narratives of legitimation" and not of narrative knowledge itself. It is not logically contradictory to say that a statement about narratives is itself a narrative, just as when Lyotard states that "every utterance [in a language game] should be thought of as a 'move' in a game"<ref>Jean-François Lyotard, 1979, [http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/fr/lyotard.htm The Postmodern Condition, A Report on Knowledge], Manchester University Press, 1984. The First 5 Chapters of main body of work are reproduced here. his statement is itself a 'move' in a language game. Retrieved November 11, 2007.</ref>
 
 
==Later life and death==
 
Lyotard returned repeatedly to the notion of the Postmodern, in essays gathered in English as ''The Postmodern Explained to Children'', ''Toward the Postmodern'', and ''Postmodern Fables''. He was preparing for a conference on Postmodernism and Media Theory when he died, suddenly, from leukemia, in 1998. On his passing, Lyotard was interred in [[Le Père Lachaise Cemetery]] in Paris.
 
  
 
==See also==
 
==See also==
 +
*[[Continental philosophy]]
 
*[[Postmodernism]]
 
*[[Postmodernism]]
*[[Postmodernity]]
+
 
 +
==Notes==
 +
<references/>
 +
 
 +
==References==
 +
*Baynes, Kenneth, James Bohman, and Thomas A. McCarthy. ''After Philosophy End or Transformation?'' Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1987. ISBN 0262022540 ISBN 9780262022545 ISBN 026252113X ISBN 9780262521130
 +
*Lyotard, Jean François, and Andrew E. Benjamin. ''The Lyotard Reader.'' Blackwell readers. Oxford, UK: Blackwell, 1989. ISBN 0631163387 ISBN 9780631163381 ISBN 0631163395 ISBN 9780631163398
 +
*Lyotard, Jean François. ''The Postmodern Condition A Report on Knowledge.'' Theory and history of literature, v. 10. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984. ISBN 0816611661 ISBN 9780816611669 ISBN 0816611734 ISBN 9780816611737
 +
*Malpas, Simon. ''Jean-Francois Lyotard.'' Routledge critical thinkers. London: Routledge, 2003. ISBN 0415256143 ISBN 9780415256148 ISBN 0415256151 ISBN 9780415256155
 +
*Rojek, Chris, Bryan S. Turner, and Jean François Lyotard. ''The Politics of Jean-François Lyotard.'' London: Routledge, 2002. ISBN 0203294688 ISBN 9780203294680
 +
*Rorty, Richard. ''Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth.'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991. ISBN 0521409152 ISBN 9780521409155
 +
*Silverman, Hugh J. ''Lyotard Philosophy, Politics, and the Sublime.'' Continental philosophy, 8. New York: Routledge, 2002. ISBN 0415919584 ISBN 9780415919586 ISBN 0415919592 ISBN 9780415919593
 +
*Smith, James K. A. ''Who's Afraid of Postmodernism? Taking Derrida, Lyotard, and Foucault to Church.'' The church and postmodern culture. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Academic, 2006. ISBN 080102918X ISBN 9780801029189
 +
*Williams, James. ''Lyotard and the Political. Thinking the political.'' London: Routledge, 2000. ISBN 0415183480 ISBN 9780415183482 ISBN 0415183499 ISBN 9780415183499
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved April 15, 2018.
 +
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/lyotard/ Jean-François Lyotard] – The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/postmodernism/ Postmodernism] – Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
* [http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/fr/lyotard.htm The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge (The first 5 chapters)]
 +
* [http://lyotard.free.fr International symposium : January 2007, 25-27th] – (French).
 +
===General Philosophy Sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
  
* [http://www.egs.edu/faculty/jeanfrancoislyotard.html Jean-Francois Lyotard European Graduate School]
 
* [http://www.marxists.org/reference/subject/philosophy/works/fr/lyotard.htm The Post Modern Condition (The first 5 chapters)]
 
* [http://www.che-lives.com/home/modules.php?name=News&file=article&sid=198 Post-modern Philosophical Martyrdom]
 
  
 +
{{Contemporary Western philosophers}}
 
{{Philosophy navigation}}
 
{{Philosophy navigation}}
[[Category:20th century philosophers|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
+
 
[[Category:Continental philosophers|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
+
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
[[Category:Deconstruction|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
+
[[Category:philosophy]]
 
[[Category:French philosophers|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
 
[[Category:French philosophers|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
 
[[Category:Social philosophy|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
 
[[Category:Social philosophy|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
[[Category:Postmodernism|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
 
[[Category:Rhetoricians|Lyotard, Jean-Francois]]
 
[[Category:philosophy and religion]]
 
  
{{credit|42757601}}
+
 
 +
{{credit|169912710}}

Latest revision as of 14:38, 16 April 2018

Western Philosophy
20th-century philosophy
Jean-Francois Lyotard.jpg
Name: Jean-François Lyotard
Birth: August 10, 1924
Flag of France Versailles, France
Death: April 21, 1998
Flag of France Paris, France
School/tradition: Postmodernism
Main interests
Metanarrative
Notable ideas
The "postmodern condition"
Collapse of the "grand narrative"
Influences Influenced
Montaigne · Kant · Marx · Freud
Wittgenstein · Parsons · Durkheim
J.L. Austin
Rorty · Barthes · Foucault · Derrida
Baudrillard

Jean-François Lyotard (pronounced [ʒɑ̃ frɑ̃swa ljɔtaʀ]; August 10, 1924 – April 21, 1998) was a French philosopher and literary theorist. He is well-known for his articulation of postmodernism after the late 1970s and the analysis of the impact of postmodernity on the human condition. He was a Marxist but he was deeply disappointed with it and rejected any form of "grand narrative," a totalistic, universal theory which promises to explain and solve all problems by one set of ideas. Lyotard adopted Wittgenstein's concept of "language games" and Kant's theory of aesthetics for his analysis. Critics argue that postmodernism is a skepticism that presents no positive alternative. Lyotard, however, captured the pluralistic tendencies of the late twentieth century.

Life

He was born in Versailles, France to Jean-Pierre Lyotard, a sale representative, and Madeleine. He went to primary school at the Paris Lycées Buffon and Louis-le-Grand and later began studying philosophy at the Sorbonne. He married Andrée May in 1948 and became a father. After graduation he took up a position teaching philosophy in Constantine in French-occupied East Algeria in 1950.

Political life

In 1954, Lyotard became a member of Socialisme ou Barbarie, a French political organisation formed in 1948 around the inadequacy of the Trotskyist analysis to explain the new forms of domination in the Soviet Union. Socialisme ou Barbarie became increasingly anti-Marxist and Lyotard was prominent in the Pouvoir Ouvrier, a group that rejected the position and split in 1963. His writings in this period are mostly concerned with ultra-left politics, with focus on the Algerian situation, which he witnessed first hand while teaching philosophy in Constantine.

Academic career

In the early 1970s, Lyotard began teaching at the University of Paris VIII, Vincennes until 1987 when he became Professor Emeritus. During the next two decades he lectured outside of France notably as a Professor of Critical Theory at the University of California, Irvine and as visiting professor at universities around the world including John Hopkins, Berkeley, Yale, and San Diego in the States, the Université de Montréal in Canada and the University of São Paulo in Brazil. He was also a founding director and councile member of the Collège International de Philosophie, Paris. Before his death, he split his time between Paris and Atlanta, where he taught at Emory University as a Woodruff Professor of Philosophy and French.

Later life and death

Lyotard repeatedly returned to the notion of the Postmodern in essays gathered in English as The Postmodern Explained to Children, Toward the Postmodern, and Postmodern Fables. In 1998, while preparing for a conference on Postmodernism and Media Theory, he died unexpectedly from a case of leukemia that had advanced rapidly. He is buried in Le Père Lachaise Cemetery in Paris.

Thought

The collapse of the "Grand Narrative"

Lyotard's work is characterised by a persistent opposition to universals, meta-narratives, and generality. He is fiercely critical of many of the 'universalist' claims of the Enlightenment, and several of his works serve to undermine the fundamental principles that generate these broad claims. Most famously, in La Condition postmoderne: Rapport sur le savoir (The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge) (1979), he argued that our age (with its postmodern condition) is marked by an 'incredulity towards meta-narratives'. These meta-narratives—sometimes 'grand narratives'—are grand, large-scale theories and philosophies of the world, such as the progress of history, the knowability of everything by science, and the possibility of absolute freedom. Lyotard argues that we have ceased to believe that narratives of this kind are adequate to represent and contain us all. We have become alert to difference, diversity, the incompatibility of our aspirations, beliefs and desires, and for that reason postmodernity is characterised by an abundance of micronarratives. For this concept Lyotard draws on and strongly reinterprets the notion of 'language-games' found in the work of Wittgenstein.

In Lyotard's works, the term 'language games', sometimes also called 'phrase regimens', denotes the multiplicity of communities of meaning, the innumerable and incommensurable separate systems in which meanings are produced and rules for their circulation are created.

This becomes more crucial in Au juste: Conversations (Just Gaming) (1979) and Le Différend (The Differend) (1983), which develop a postmodern theory of justice. It might appear that the atomisation of human beings implied by the notion of the micronarrative and the language game suggests a collapse of ethics. It has often been thought that universality is a condition for something to be a properly ethical statement: 'thou shalt not steal' is an ethical statement in a way that 'thou shalt not steal from Margaret' is not. The latter is too particular to be an ethical statement (what's so special about Margaret?); it is only ethical if it rests on a universal statement ('thou shalt not steal from anyone'). But universals are impermissible in a world that has lost faith in metanarratives, and so it would seem that ethics is impossible. Justice and injustice can only be terms within language games, and the universality of ethics is out of the window. Lyotard argues that notions of justice and injustice do in fact remain in postmodernism. The new definition of injustice is indeed to use the language rules from one 'phrase regimen' and apply them to another. Ethical behaviour is about remaining alert precisely to the threat of this injustice, of paying attention to things in their particularity and not enclosing them within abstract conceptuality. One must bear witness to the 'differend'.

The sublime

Lyotard was a frequent writer on aesthetic matters. He was, despite his reputation as a postmodernist, a great promoter of modernist art. (It is worth commenting that Lyotard saw 'postmodernism' as a latent tendency within thought throughout time and not a narrowly-limited historical period.) He favored the startling and perplexing works of the high modernist avant-garde. In them he found a demonstration of the limits of our conceptuality, a valuable lesson for anyone too imbued with Enlightenment confidence.

He developed these themes in particular by discussing the sublime. The "sublime" is a term in aesthetics whose fortunes revived under postmodernism after a century or more of neglect. It refers to the experience of pleasurable anxiety that we experience when confronting wild and threatening sights like, for example, a massive craggy mountain, black against the sky, looming terrifyingly in our vision.

Lyotard found particularly interesting the explanation of the sublime offered by Immanuel Kant in his Critique of Judgment (sometimes Critique of the Power of Judgment). In this book Kant explains this mixture of anxiety and pleasure in the following terms: there are two kinds of 'sublime' experience. In the 'mathematical' sublime, an object strikes the mind in such a way that we find ourselves unable to take it in as a whole. More precisely, we experience a clash between our reason (which tells us that all objects are finite) and the imagination (the aspect of the mind that organizes what we see, and which sees an object incalculably larger than ourselves, and feels infinite). In the 'dynamical' sublime, the mind recoils at an object so immeasurably more powerful than we, whose weight, force, scale could crush us without the remotest hope of our being able to resist it. (Kant stresses that if we are in actual danger, our feeling of anxiety is very different from that of a sublime feeling. The sublime is an aesthetic experience, not a practical feeling of personal danger.) This explains the feeling of anxiety.

The feeling of pleasure comes when human reason asserts itself. What is deeply unsettling about the mathematical sublime is that the mental faculties that present visual perceptions to the mind are inadequate to the concept corresponding to it; in other words, what we are able to make ourselves see cannot fully match up to what we know is there. We know it's a mountain but we cannot take the whole thing into our perception. What this does, ironically, is to compel our awareness of the supremacy of the human reason. Our sensibility is incapable of coping with such sights, but our reason can assert the finitude of the presentation. With the dynamical sublime, our sense of physical danger should prompt an awareness that we are not just physical material beings, but moral and (in Kant's terms) noumenal beings as well. The body may be dwarfed by its power but our reason need not be. This explains, in both cases, why the sublime is an experience of pleasure as well as pain.

Lyotard is fascinated by this admission, from one of the philosophical architects of the Enlightenment, that the mind cannot always organise the world rationally. Some objects are simply incapable of being brought neatly under concepts. For Lyotard, in Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime, and drawing on his argument in The Differend, this is a good thing. Such generalities as 'concepts' fail to pay proper attention to the particularity of things. What happens in the sublime is a crisis where we realize the inadequacy of the imagination and reason individually. What we are witnessing, says Lyotard, is actually the differend; the straining of the mind at the edges of itself and at the edges of its conceptuality.

Criticism

Some argue that Lyotard's theories may seem self-contradictory because The Postmodern Condition seems to offer its own grand narrative in the story of the decline of the metanarrative. Against this it can be argued that Lyotard's narrative in The Postmodern Condition declares the decline of only a few defunct "narratives of legitimation" and not of narrative knowledge itself. It is not logically contradictory to say that a statement about narratives is itself a narrative, just as when Lyotard states that "every utterance [in a language game] should be thought of as a 'move' in a game"[1]

See also

Notes

  1. Jean-François Lyotard, 1979, The Postmodern Condition, A Report on Knowledge, Manchester University Press, 1984. The First 5 Chapters of main body of work are reproduced here. his statement is itself a 'move' in a language game. Retrieved November 11, 2007.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

External links

All links retrieved April 15, 2018.

General Philosophy Sources



Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.