Difference between revisions of "Existentialism" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
({{Contracted}})
 
(19 intermediate revisions by 9 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Contracted}}
+
{{Ebapproved}}{{Copyedited}}{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}
  
This article contains unverified information. Please clean up.
+
'''Existentialism''' is a [[philosophy|philosophical]] movement that arose in the twentieth century. It includes a number of thinkers who emphasize common themes, but whose ultimate [[metaphysics|metaphysical]] views often diverge radically because they believe the universe is unfathomable. Philosophically the term “existentialism” came to be associated primarily with the French philosopher [[Jean-Paul Sartre]]. Many other philosophers who are often tied to the existential movement, such as [[Martin Heidegger]], [[Gabriel Marcel]], and [[Karl Jaspers]], rejected the term “existentialism,” though they continued to deal with existential themes broadly construed. In [[German language|German]], the phrase ''Existenzphilosophie'' (philosophy of existence) is also used. Some of the common themes that unite these various existential thinkers are [[anxiety]], boredom, [[freedom]], [[will]], [[subjectivity]], awareness of [[death]], risk, [[responsibility]], and [[consciousness]] of existing. Perhaps the central issue that draws these thinkers together, however, is their emphasis upon the primacy of existence in philosophical questioning and the importance of responsible human action in the face of uncertainty.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
Although, as a movement, existentialism is considered a twentieth-century phenomenon, its roots go back to earlier existential thinkers, such as [[Blaise Pascal]] in the seventeenth century, and particularly [[Søren Kierkegaard]] and [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] in the nineteenth century. Both Kierkegaard and Nietzsche emphasized the subjective element in thinking and the primacy of the will over purely [[logic|logical]] or conceptual objectivity. In the twentieth century, Heidegger’s notion of “being-in-the-world” and Sartre’s idea of “existence preceding essence” became two of the most important themes in existential thought. Other more [[Christianity|Christian]] or theistic existential perspectives were also developed. Moreover, existential ideas became very influential in areas outside of philosophy, such as in [[psychology]] and the popular arts.  
  
'''Existentialism''' is a [[philosophical movement]] that views human [[existence]] as having a set of underlying themes and characteristics, such as anxiety, dread, freedom, awareness of death, and consciousness of existing. Existentialism is also an outlook, or a perspective, on life that pursues the question of the meaning of life or the meaning of existence. This question is seen as being of paramount importance, above all other scientific and philosophical pursuits.
+
== Main themes ==
 +
The emphasis on existence by existential thinkers is often summarized in [[Sartre]]’s famous assertion that “existence precedes essence.” Although the various philosophers differ in regard to the nature of this priority and the reasons for it, their thought can all be called existential in the broad sense because of the priority they give to existence or being. For this reason, these thinkers share the assumption that existence precedes essence in that existence or being exceeds all rational conceptions and objective or scientific knowledge of it. Or, to paraphrase the words of [[William Shakespeare|Shakespeare]]’s [[Hamlet]], there is more in heaven and earth than in all of philosophy. This leads some of the more radical existentialists to take what opponents consider to be an irrational or anti-philosophic position.
  
The Danish philosopher [[Søren Kierkegaard]] ([[1813]]-[[1855]]), the "father of existentialism", asserted that "truth is subjectivity": human beings can be understood only from the inside, in terms of their lived and experienced reality and dilemmas, not from the outside, in terms of a biological, psychological, or other scientific theory of human nature. Existentialism emphasises action, freedom and decision as fundamental to human existence and is fundamentally opposed to the [[rationalism|rationalist]] tradition and to [[positivism (philosophy)|positivism]].  That is, it argues against definitions of human beings either as primarily rational, knowing beings who relate to reality primarily as an object of [[knowledge]] or whose action can or ought to be regulated by rational principles, or as beings who can be defined in terms of their behavior as it looks to or is studied by others. More generally it rejects all of the Western rationalist definitions of Being in terms of a rational principle or essence or as the most general feature that all existing things share in common. Existentialism tends to view human beings as subjects in an indifferent, objective, often ambiguous, and "absurd" universe in which meaning is not provided by the natural order, but rather can be created, however provisionally and unstably, by human beings' actions and interpretations.
+
Another aspect of “existence preceding essence” is the idea that human beings are in [[Heidegger]]'s phrase "thrown" into existence. Existential thought, therefore, differs from the modern Western [[rationalism|rationalist]] tradition extending from [[Descartes]] to [[Husserl]] in that it rejects the idea that the most certain and primary reality is rational consciousness. Descartes argued that humans could think away everything that exists and so doubt its reality, but they could not think away or doubt the thinking consciousness itself. This reality of consciousness is more certain than any other reality. Existentialism decisively rejects this argument. Instead, it asserts that humans always already find themselves in a world. That is, they find themselves in a prior context and history that is given to and situated within their consciousness. The priority, or [[a priori and a posteriori]], therefore, is not thinking consciousness, but according to Heidegger, "being-in-the-world." Many existentialists consider this “being thrown into existence” as prior to, and the horizon or context of, all other thoughts or ideas about who human beings are. For Heidegger, this “facticity” of being thrown into existence means a supreme being determines who and what humans are, while for Sartre it means that the definitions of what it means to be human is something humans choose and create.
  
Human beings are exposed to or, to use the philosopher [[Martin Heidegger]]'s phrase, "thrown" into, existence - in that we have no choice to come into existence. Existentialists consider being thrown into existence as prior to, and the horizon or context of, any other thoughts or ideas that humans have or definitions of themselves that they create. This is one part of the meaning of the assertion of the philosopher [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], one of the founders of existentialism, "existence is prior to essence". Existentialism conceives of Being itself as something that can only be understood through and in relation to these basic characteristics of human existence.
+
The recognition of human [[freedom]] leads existential philosophers to emphasize [[will]] over [[reason]]. Many of them view [[action]] and decision, therefore, as fundamental to human existence. This position is opposed to [[rationalism]] and [[positivism]], where reason is the sufficient means of determining “what we should do.Existentialists argue against definitions of human beings as primarily rational, knowing subjects who relate to reality as an object of [[knowledge]]. Moreover, they deny human actions can or ought to be regulated strictly by rational principles or laws. They also reject the notion that human beings can be defined in terms of their behavior as in empirical science. They stress, then, the ambiguity and risk of life and the anxiety of having to choose in existential situations. This leads some of the [[atheism|atheistic]] existentialists to view human beings as subjects in an indifferent and absurd universe where meaning is not provided by the [[natural order]]. Meaning, then, must be created, however provisionally and unstably, by the actions and interpretations of individuals. They emphasize the [[authenticity]] that is needed in accepting responsibility for decisions. More theistic interpretations will likewise emphasize freedom, risk, and decision not by denying any ultimate or absolute [[Truth]], but by arguing that the individual must appropriate and so subjectively discover the Truth for oneself. In turn, only by living the truth can one be said to know the truth. Both atheistic and theistic versions of existentialism share the view that the individual must pursue the question of the meaning of existence, and that this question is above all other scientific and philosophic pursuits.
  
In terms of the existence and relevance of God, there are three schools of existentialist thought: [[atheistic]] existentialism (Sartre, Camus), [[Christian existentialism]] (Kierkegaard) and a third school, [[agnostic]] existentialism (Heidegger), which proposes that whether God exists or not is irrelevant to the issue of human existence.
+
== Origins ==
 +
An early forerunner of existentialism was [[Blaise Pascal]]. In 1670, his book ''Pensées'' was published; in the work he described many fundamental existential themes. Pascal argued that life without God is meaningless and miserable. When people are exposed to their own emptiness, they create obstacles in order to overcome them and in this way attempt to escape boredom. These token-victories are merely diversions people use to distract themselves from their [[spirituality|spiritual]] poverty and the recognition that one day they will [[death|die]]. According to Pascal this recognition of the reality of mortal existence is good reason for humans not to be atheistic. Thus, he presented his famous “wager” where the gambling believer has everything to gain and nothing to lose by putting his chips on the hope that there is a God, while the gambling unbeliever has nothing to gain and everything to lose by his unbelief. [[Sartre]] and other later atheistic existentialists will view this attempt at avoiding the inevitability of death as “bad faith” and as a refusal to accept the truth of human condition.  
  
Although there are certain common tendencies among existentialist thinkers, there are major differences and disagreements among them, and not all of them even affiliate themselves with or accept the validity of the term "existentialism". In German the phrase ''Existenzphilosophie'' (philosophy of existence) is also used.
+
The Danish philosopher [[Søren Kierkegaard]] (1813–1855) is often called the "father of existentialism." Kierkegaard is commonly considered more of a religious thinker (or “religious poet” as he sometimes called himself) than a philosopher, for he never practiced or espoused a systematic or methodical way of thinking. In fact, in large part, his works were a polemic against [[modern philosophy|modern philosophical]] [[rationalism]] with its emphasis on [[method]], which had begun with [[Descartes]] and culminated in [[Hegel]]. Given Kierkegaard’s suspicion regarding the absolute reliability of reason, he often wrote under pseudonymous names. The reason for this was not to conceal his true identity but to distance himself (as an existential person) from the concepts and ideas contained in his works (as a thinker). Moreover, much of his work is ironic, in imitation of his mentor [[Socrates]], and so these pseudonymous works should be read more like literature than straightforward philosophy (just as a reader of a novel should not mistake the ideas of a character with those of the author herself).  
  
== Overview ==
+
Nevertheless, Kierkegaard is often associated with the ideas of his pseudonyms and in particular the pseudonymous author Johannes Climacus who said that "truth is subjectivity" and that the person of [[faith]] must make a kind of “leap.” Although the conflation of Kierkegaard with Climacus is a mistake, it cannot be denied the philosophical tenets of Climacus did have a major influence on the twentieth-century existential movement. Furthermore, the term “leap of faith” is frequently employed by both defenders and critics of twentieth-century existentialism who view the idea as signifying the need for choice and risk by the individual in deciding life’s ultimate meaning.
Existentialism was inspired by the works of [[Søren Kierkegaard]], [[Fyodor Dostoevsky]] and the [[Germany|German]] philosophers [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], [[Edmund Husserl]], and [[Martin Heidegger]]. It became popular in the mid-[[20th century]] through the works of the French writer-philosophers [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] and [[Simone de Beauvoir]] whose versions of existentialism are set out in a popular form in Sartre's [[1946]] ''L'Existentialisme est un humanisme'', translated as ''[[Existentialism is a Humanism]]''.
 
  
[[Gabriel Marcel]] pursued theological versions of existentialism, most notably [[Christian existentialism]]. Other theological existentialists include [[Paul Tillich]], [[Miguel de Unamuno]], and [[Martin Buber]].  Moreover, one-time [[Marxism|Marxist]] [[Nikolai Berdyaev]] developed a philosophy of Christian existentialism in his native [[Russia]], and later in [[France]], in the decades preceding [[World War II]].
+
For Kierkegaard the idea of subjectivity signified the infinite depth dimension of human beings and so should not be understood as opposed to rational objectivity but rather as going beyond it. Understanding is always finite and so it can never fully grasp who or what people are as human beings. Or to put it another way, the apprehension of human’s existential selfhood extends beyond any philosophical definition of what a human being is. For this reason, the full extent of being human can only be apprehended from the inside, in terms of lived experience, and not from the outside, in terms of any scientific or objective definition, be it [[biology|biological]], [[psychology|psychological]], or any other scientific theory of [[human nature]].  
  
[[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]] and [[Arthur Schopenhauer]] are also important influences on the development of existentialism (although not direct precursors) because the philosophies of Søren Kierkegaard and Friedrich Nietzsche were written in response or opposition to Hegel and Schopenhauer, respectively.
+
[[Friedrich Nietzsche]] was also a forerunner of the existential movement in his critique of Western culture and philosophy, in particular [[Plato]] and [[Christianity]] (which he called “Platonism for the masses”). Nietzsche realized that human nature and human identity vary depending on what values and beliefs humans hold. Although Nietzsche’s work, like Kierkegaard’s, is often ironic and ambiguous (and so open to different interpretations), he did frequently write about the capacity of human beings to create or recreate themselves. In this sense, then, Nietzsche influenced later existential thinkers such as Sartre (in his emphasis on freedom and choice) and Heidegger (in his emphasis on [[creativity]] and history).  
  
==Major concepts in existentialism==
+
In literature, the most famous nineteenth-century existential writer was [[Fyodor Dostoevsky]]. The statement by one of his characters that “without God everything is permissible” was taken up by both theistic and atheistic twentieth-century existential thinkers.
Existentialism differentiates itself from the modern Western rationalist tradition extending from [[Descartes]] to [[Husserl]] by rejecting the idea that the most certain and primary reality is rational consciousness.  Descartes argued that humans could think away everything that exists and doubt its reality but that humans could not think away or doubt the thinking consciousness, whose reality is therefore more certain than any other reality. Existentialism decisively rejects this argument, asserting instead that as conscious beings humans always find themselves already in a world, a prior context and history that is given to consciousness and in which it is situated, and that humans cannot think away that world.  It is inherent and indubitably linked to consciousness.  In other words, the ultimate, certain, indubitable reality is not thinking consciousness but, according to Heidegger, "being in the world".  This is a radicalization of the notion of [[intentionality]] that comes from [[Brentano]] and [[Husserl]], which asserts that, even in its barest form, consciousness is always conscious ''of something''.
 
  
===Atheistic Existentialism===
+
==Twentieth-century existentialism==
[[Sartre]]'s dictum, "Existence precedes and rules essence", is generally taken to mean that ''there is no pre-defined essence to humanity, except that which people make for themselves''.  Since Sartrean existentialism does not acknowledge the existence of a [[God]], or of any other determining principle, [[human being]]s are free to act as they choose; his above mentioned essay is the most programmatic and straightforward statement of this principle.  Even if an individual believes that he has an essence—such as a soul or rationality or a psychological type—that essence is a choice that he is making rather than something pre-existing that is imposed on him.
+
The thought of the major existential philosophers of the twentieth century grew out of the [[phenomenology]] of [[Husserl]], which attempted to critique [[positivism]] and [[psychologism]] by grounding all [[perception]], [[experience]], and [[knowledge]] in structures of human [[consciousness]]. Husserl stressed that being is always being for a consciousness, or that consciousness is always consciousness of something. [[Heidegger]] transformed this into the core existential notion that being is always being, not for a pure consciousness, but rather for a concrete existence. This means that consciousness is a property of human existence ''(Dasein)'', which has "being-in-the-world" and so exists in a historical context. Heidegger, however, came to reject the idea that his philosophy was “existentialist.
  
===Christian Existentialism===
+
[[Jean-Paul Sartre]], on the other hand, embraced the term existentialism. His version of existentialism is set out in popular form in his 1946 essay ''L'Existentialisme est un humanisme,'' translated as “Existentialism is a Humanism.” In the essay he asserts his famous dictum, "Existence precedes essence," which is generally taken to mean that there is no predefined essence to humanity and so people must decide for themselves the meaning of existence. Sartrean existentialism takes it for granted that there is no God, and so for this reason essence or the nature of human beings cannot precede their existence. For how could there be an idea or definition of what human nature essentially is if there is no [[Creator]] or Divine Mind who created it? Sartre holds that human beings are not only free to act as they choose, but they have a responsibility to do so. They must accept the forlornness of their condition in that there is no God and so no preexisting [[morality|moral]] principles, nature, or laws that can tell them what to do. Instead, they are on their own and so must decide for themselves. But in choosing for themselves “[they] choose all humanity.” Moreover, for Sartre it is human actions that determine who humans are. They cannot blame their environment, circumstance, or chance for their successes and failures. Rather it is their actions that make them who they are and these are determined by their own choices.  
In contrast to Sartre's atheism stands [[Kierkegaard]]'s (5 May 1813 – 11 November 1855) Christian existentialism which, according to Kierkegaard, was inspired by [[Socrates]].  He never referred to himself as an existentialist, but rather as "the unique individual". Focused on the relationship between the self and God, Kierkegaard neither posited a proof for, nor thought it possible to prove the existence of God.  However, he argued that an individual could, despite one's doubt, have faith that God exists and that God is good. This leap of faith was for Kierkegaard a choice that an individual must make in defining his or her life.  The leap of faith signifies an individual's choice to embrace meaning in life, a meaning that is beyond individual (subjective) and external (objective) truth. He expressed the individual, external and finally the leap of faith as the Asthetic, Ethical and Religious lives. In which the Asthetic is represented by 'Johanes' the seducer who finds his meaning in the pleasure he derives from the seduction of women. The Ethical is represented is the moral hero who attempts to make the most moral choise in each circumstance but ends up sacrificing one principle for another. 'i.e Do you torture one man to save two'. It was the leap of faith to the unprovable ideal of Christianity and God that gave the individuals life meaning as in his opinion the faith required was the extra step that took the individual from being lost in absurdity as the moral hero to embracing absurdity and continuing to choose well, as Abraham having the faith to offer up Isaac in 'Fear and Trembling'.
 
  
As with atheistic existentialism, Kierkegaard's Christian existentialism does not impose a reality or meaning on the individual; rather, the individual makes the choice to take meaning in life and to define his or her life. The idea that the individual is a paradox of abstract and concrete: faith and its opposite, despair. Kierkegaard wrote that the individual person is infinite in depth, and ultimately, "subjectivity is truth" and "truth is subjectivity" (''Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments'').  Kierkegaard was also against the views espoused by [[Georg Hegel]]. ''[[Philosophical Fragments]]'' and ''[[Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments]]'' satirize [[Hegelianism]].
+
[[Albert Camus]] was another well-known writer and thinker associated with existentialism. Camus famously compared human condition to the myth of [[Sisyphus]]. Sisyphus is condemned each day to roll a rock up a hill only to have the rock, once it is almost to the top, roll back down. The next day Sisyphus must start all over despite knowing the result will be the same. Likewise, human beings must stoically roll the rock up the hill each day by creating their own meaning despite knowing the universe is essentially absurd and meaningless. Camus depicted many of his existential themes in fiction and drama, such as ''The Stranger,'' ''The Plague,'' ''The Fall,'' and ''The Possessed.''
  
===Agnostic Existentialism===
+
[[Gabriel Marcel]] developed a kind of Christian existentialism, though he, like Heidegger, rejected the term and instead preferred to call himself a “Christian Socratic.” Other theistic existentialists include [[Paul Tillich]], [[Miguel de Unamuno]], and [[Martin Buber]]. [[Nikolai Berdyaev]] developed a philosophy of Christian existentialism in his native [[Russia]], and later in [[France]], in the decades preceding [[World War II]]. Though these existential theists did not accept Sartre’s and Camus’ notion that the universe is absurd and meaning must be created by the individual, they nevertheless also distanced themselves from rationalist philosophies and insisted that the individual must participate in being or existence in order to come to a deeper appreciation and fuller understanding of it. [[Jacques Maritain]] and [[Etienne Gilson]] in a different way developed an existential [[Thomism]], which took many of the insights and approaches of the existential movement, but applied and attributed them to the metaphysics of [[St. Thomas Aquinas]].
The third class of existentialism is commonly misconstrued as the simplest and "safest" philosophy to adapt: ''embrace life for what it is'' (whatever that may be). The agnostic existentialist makes no claim to know, or not know, if there is a "greater picture" in play; rather, he simply recognizes that the greatest truth is that which he chooses to act upon. The agnosic existentialist feels that to know the "greater picture" whether there is one or not is impossible for human minds. Like Christian existentialists, the agnostic holds that existence is subjective. Every agnostic existentialist (like the other two) has unique views, however, the act of finding knowledge of the existence of God often has little value because he/she feels it to be impossible, and to pretend to know is useless. To work with what you think you know is more ideal to the agnostic existentialist.
 
  
===Common Threads===
+
==Criticisms of existentialism==
Since there is no predefined [[human nature]] (or even if there were, that human nature would be infinite), nor any ultimate evaluation of life beyond that which humans project onto the world, individuals may only be judged or defined by their actions and choices.
+
[[Herbert Marcuse]] criticized existentialism from a [[Marxism|Marxist]] perspective, especially [[Sartre]]'s ''Being and Nothingness,'' for projecting certain features, such as anxiety and meaninglessness, which really derive from the modern experience of living in an oppressive society, onto the nature of existence itself:
 
 
==Existentialism before 1970==
 
An early forerunner of existentialism was [[Blaise Pascal]].  In 1670, his book [[Pensées]] was published, in which he described many fundamental themes of existentialism.  Pascal argued that without a God, life would be meaningless and miserable. People would only be able to create obstacles and overcome them in an attempt to escape boredom.  These token-victories would ultimately become meaningless, since people would eventually die.  This was good enough reason not to choose to become an atheist according to Pascal. Sartre takes this idea of avoiding the inevitable death as bad faith.  Camus embraces the idea that without a God ultimately everything is meaningless, and tries to find meaning within it. 
 
 
 
The first philosophers considered existentialists are [[Søren Kierkegaard]] and [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], even though the term had not yet come into use. Like Pascal, they were interested in people's concealment of the meaninglessness of life and their use of diversion to escape from boredom.  However, what Pascal did not write about was that people can create and change their fundamental values and beliefs.  Kierkegaard and Nietzsche realized that human nature and human identity vary depending on what values and beliefs humans hold.  In contrast Pascal did not reason that human nature and identity are constituted by the free decisions and choices of people.  Sartre builds strongly on that idea with his ''existence precedes essence'' dictum.
 
 
 
The thought of the major existentialist philosophers of the 20th century, Heidegger and Sartre, grew out of the [[phenomenology]] of Husserl, which attempted to critique [[positivism]] and [[psychologism]] by grounding all perception, experience, and knowledge in structures of human [[consciousness]].  Husserl stressed that all Being is always being for a consciousness.  Heidegger transformed this into the core existentialist notion that Being is always being, not for a pure consciousness, but rather for a concrete existence, that is that consciousness is a property of a (human) existence (''Dasein'') that has "being-in-the-world", and exists in a concrete historical context.  Sartre developed his version of existentialist philosophy under the influence of Husserl and Heidegger.
 
 
 
In the [[1950s]] and [[1960s]], existentialism experienced a resurgence of interest in popular artforms. In fiction, [[Jack Kerouac]] and the [[Beat poets]] adopted existentialist themes. [[Hermann Hesse]]'s ''[[Steppenwolf (novel)|Steppenwolf]]'', based on an idea in Kierkegaard's ''Either/Or'' (1843), sold well in the West, and "arthouse" films began quoting and alluding to existentialist thought and thinkers. Simultaneously, in Sartre, [[Paris]] university students found a hero for the [[May 1968]] demonstrations, and others were appropriating the thematic pessimism found in [[Albert Camus]] and [[Søren Kierkegaard]]. The despair of choice and the despair of the unknowing self featured prominently (often in [[pidgin]] form) in cinema and novels.
 
 
 
==Existentialism since 1970==
 
Although [[Postmodernism|postmodernist]] thought became the focus of many intellectuals in the [[1970s]] and thereafter (whether the movement is strong today, and what, if anything, has replaced it, still is debated), much postmodern writing is existential —unsurprising, since postmodernism evolved from the thought of Nietzsche and Heidegger (two of the greatest proto-existential philosophers), despite Heidegger's rejecting the existentialist label.
 
 
 
One should, however, not confuse postmodernism with existentialism. Thematically postmodern films such as ''[[The Matrix]]'' posit the idea of [[simulacrum]], dealing with reality and appearance, and of how the latter renders the former indistinguishable, if the artificial can sufficiently mimic the real (see [[Jean Baudrillard]], the philosopher whose work was a primary influence on the film). Alternatively, existential cinema deals more with the themes of:
 
 
 
#Retaining authenticity in an apathetic, mechanical world, something [[post-modernism]] would staunchly reject—as authenticity is related to a non-existent "reality".
 
#The consciousness of death; e.g. Heidegger's 'being towards death'—exemplified in [[Ingmar Bergman]]'s film "[[The Seventh Seal]]" (1957).
 
#The feelings of alienation and loneliness consequent to being unique in a world of many, or, in Nietzsche's phrase, "herd-animals".
 
#The concept Alltägliche selbstsein (Everyday-ness) which Heidegger explicated in his book ''[[Sein und Zeit]]'' (1927), (English translation [[Being and Time]]).
 
  
Since [[1970]], much cultural activity in art, cinema, and literature contains postmodern and existential elements, which, ironically, would support the postmodern thesis of "borderlessness between concepts". Books such as ''[[Do Androids Dream of Electric Sheep]]'', by [[Philip K. Dick]], and ''[[Toilet: The Novel]]'', by [[Michael Szymczyk]] all distort the line between reality and appearance while simultaneously espousing strong existential themes.
+
<blockquote>In so far as Existentialism is a philosophical doctrine, it remains an idealistic doctrine: it hypothesizes specific historical conditions of human existence into ontological and metaphysical characteristics. Existentialism thus becomes part of the very ideology which it attacks, and its radicalism is illusory (Marcuse 1972, 161).</blockquote>
  
In cinema, postmodern editing techniques (showing the displacement, discontinuity, and temporal perspective of postmodernism) can go hand-in-hand with a purely existential story, thus synthesizing technique and function to give meaning. Moreover, this has created the neologism "[[Neo-Existentialism]]"—combining postmodernism's epistemology with the reflective [[ontological]] belief of existentialism.
+
[[Theodor Adorno]], in his ''Jargon of Authenticity,'' criticized [[Heidegger]]'s [[philosophy]], and in particular Heidegger’s use of language. Adorno viewed this as a mystifying ideology of advanced industrial society and its power structure.
  
==Criticisms of existentialism==
+
Roger Scruton claimed, in his book ''From Descartes to Wittgenstein,'' that both Heidegger's concept of inauthenticity and Sartre's concept of bad faith were incoherent. For both Heidegger and Sartre deny any universal moral creed, yet they speak of these concepts as if everyone were bound to abide by them. In chapter 18, he writes:  
[[Herbert Marcuse]] criticized existentialism, especially in Sartre's ''[[Being and Nothingness]]'', for projecting certain features, such as anxiety and meaninglessness, of the modern experience of living in an oppressive society, onto the nature of existence itself:  "In so far as Existentialism is a philosophical doctrine, it remains an idealistic doctrine: it hypothesizes specific historical conditions of human existence into ontological and metaphysical characteristics.  Existentialism thus becomes part of the very ideology which it attacks, and its radicalism is illusory" (Herbert Marcuse, "Sartre's Existentialism", p. 161).
 
  
[[Theodor Adorno]], in his ''Jargon of Authenticity'', criticized Heidegger's philosophy, with special attention to his use of language, as a mystifying ideology of advanced industrial society and its power structure.
+
<blockquote>In what sense Sartre is able to 'recommend' the authenticity which consists in the purely self-made morality is unclear. He does recommend it, but, by his own argument, his recommendation can have no objective force.</blockquote>
  
[[Roger Scruton]] claimed, in his book ''From Descartes to Wittgenstein'', that both Heidegger's concept of [[Authenticity (philosophy)|inauthenticity]] and Sartre's concept of [[Sartre and bad faith|bad faith]] were incoherent; both deny any universal moral creed, yet speak of these concepts as if everyone were bound to abide them. In chapter 18, he writes,''"In what sense Sartre is able to 'recommend' the authenticity which consists in the purely self-made morality is unclear.  He does recommend it, but, by his own argument, his recommendation can have no objective force."'' Familiar with this sort of argument, Sartre claimed that bad and good faith do not represent moral ideas, rather, they are ways of being.
+
Familiar with this sort of argument, Sartre claimed that bad and good faith do not represent moral ideas; rather, they are ways of being. Heidegger would also claim authenticity as an ontological rather than an ethical way of being.
  
Logical positivists, such as [[Carnap]] and [[Ayer]], claim that existentialists frequently become confused over the verb "to be" in their analyses of "being"The verb is prefixed to a [[predicate]] and to use the word without any predicate is meaningless. Borrowing from [[Kant]]'s argument against the [[ontological argument]] for the existence of God, they argue that existence is not a property.
+
[[Logical positivism|Logical positivists]], such as [[Carnap]] and [[Ayer]], claim that existentialists frequently become confused over the verb "to be" in their analyses of "being." The verb is prefixed to a predicate and to use the word without any predicate is meaningless. Borrowing from [[Kant]]'s argument against the [[ontological argument]] for the existence of God, they argue that existence is not a property.
  
 
==Existentialism in psychotherapy==
 
==Existentialism in psychotherapy==
With complete freedom to decide and being responsible for the outcome of said decisions comes [[anxiety]]—or angst—about the choices made. Anxiety's importance in existentialism makes it a popular topic in [[psychotherapy]]. Therapists often use existential philosophy to explain the patient's anxiety. Psychotherapists using an existential approach believe that the patient can harness his or her anxiety and use it constructively. Instead of suppressing anxiety, patients are advised to use it as grounds for change. By embracing anxiety as inevitable, a person can use it to achieve his or her full potential in life.
+
With complete freedom to decide and be responsible for the outcome of their decisions comes [[anxiety]] about the choices humans make. Anxiety's importance in existentialism makes it a popular topic in [[psychotherapy]]. Therapists often use existential philosophy to explain the patient's anxiety. Psychotherapists employ an existential approach by encouraging their patients to harness their anxiety and use it constructively. Instead of suppressing anxiety, patients are advised to use it as grounds for change. By embracing anxiety as inevitable, a person can use it to achieve his or her full potential in life.
 
 
[[Logotherapy]] asserts that all human beings have a will to find meaning, and that serious behavioral problems develop when they cannot find it.  The therapy helps patients handle the responsibility of choices and the pain of unavoidable suffering by helping them decide to give life meaning.
 
  
==Major thinkers and authors associated with the movement==
+
[[Logotherapy]] asserts that all human beings have a will to find meaning, and that serious behavioral problems develop when they cannot find it. The therapy helps patients handle the responsibility of choices and the pain of unavoidable suffering by helping them decide to give life meaning.
===Film directors===
 
* [[Woody Allen]]
 
* [[Paul Thomas Anderson]]
 
* [[Hideaki Anno]]
 
* [[Michelangelo Antonioni]]
 
* [[Ingmar Bergman]]
 
* [[Robert Bresson]]
 
* [[David Cronenberg]]
 
* [[Jean-Luc Godard]]
 
* [[Michel Gondry]]
 
* [[Werner Herzog]]
 
* [[Richard Linklater]]
 
* [[Mamoru Oshii]]
 
* [[Alain Robbe-Grillet]]
 
* [[Harold Ramis]]
 
* [[Éric Rohmer]]
 
* [[David O. Russell]]
 
* [[François Truffaut]]
 
* [[Luchino Visconti]]
 
* [[Jim Jarmusch]]
 
  
===Novelists, poets and playwrights===
+
==Popular Existentialism==
Existentialist novelists were generally seen as a mid-1950s phenomenon that continued until the mid- to late 1970s. Most of the major writers were either French or from French African colonies. Small circles of other Europeans were seen as literary existential precursors by the existentialists themselves, however, literary history increasingly has questioned the accuracy of this idealism for earlier models.
+
In the 1950s and 1960s, existentialism experienced a surge of interest in popular art forms. In fiction, [[Jack Kerouac]] and the Beat poets adopted existentialist themes. [[Hermann Hesse]]'s ''Steppenwolf'' was based on an idea in Kierkegaard's ''Either/Or'' (1843), and "arthouse" films began quoting and alluding to existentialist thought and thinkers. Simultaneously, in [[Sartre]], [[Paris]]ian university students found a hero for the May 1968 demonstrations, and others were appropriating the themes found in [[Camus]] and [[Kierkegaard]]. The despair of choice and the anxiety of the unknowing self featured prominently in cinema and novels.
  
There is overlapping between the American [[beat generation]] writers who lived in Paris, and felt it their spiritual home, and writers of [[road novels]]; as well as the delayed action of the French discovery of American [[film noir]], in the 1950s, after a decade of Nazi-Fascist censorship, which, as [[Truffaut]] and others in the ''[[Cahiers du Cinéma]]'' indicated, influenced novels and plays; to some extent, as well, the [[surrealist]] movement of [[Andre Breton]] and others, which questioned the established reality, made possible the isolation of non-academic novels protagonised by amoral anti-heroes.
+
Existentialist films deal with existential concepts that are familiar to the average person, such as [[free will]], [[personal identity]], individuality, [[responsibility]], mind versus reality, and what "really matters." The Coen Brothers’ ''The Man Who Wasn't There,'' Linklater's ''Waking Life,'' [[Ingmar Bergman|Bergman]]'s ''The Seventh Seal'' and ''Wild Strawberries,'' are good examples of existential films. Woody Allen films tend to touch the subject in a humorous manner, though his ''Match Point'' (2005) provides a more serious consideration of some existentialist themes. Existential cinema also explores themes such as retaining authenticity in an apathetic, mechanical world; the consciousness of death, e.g., Heidegger's “being towards death”—exemplified in Ingmar Bergman's film ''The Seventh Seal'' (1957); and the feelings of [[alienation]] and loneliness consequent to being unique in a world of [[mass media]] and [[consumerism]].
  
The ''Belmondo'' school of existentialism, inspired by [[Genet]], the criminal world, and French society's underclasses are seen now as a detective fiction sub-genre.
+
==Major philosophers associated with the movement==
 
 
This is a general list of existentialist writers:
 
 
 
*[[Kobo Abe]]
 
*[[Edward Albee]]
 
*[[Paul Auster]]
 
*[[Georges Bataille]]
 
*[[Samuel Beckett]]
 
*[[Simone de Beauvoir]]
 
*[[Michel Butor]]
 
*[[Albert Camus]] (Ultimately rejected being labeled an existentialist, but his thoughts and works are characterized as being existential.)
 
*[[Louis-Ferdinand Celine]]
 
*[[Noah Cicero]]
 
*[[Joseph Conrad]]
 
*[[Eugene Cullen]]
 
*[[Philip K. Dick]]
 
*[[Fyodor Dostoevsky]]
 
*[[Marguerite Duras]]
 
*[[Ralph Ellison]]
 
*[[John Fowles]]
 
*[[Jean Genet]]
 
*[[André Gide]]
 
*[[Knut Hamsun]]
 
*[[Joseph Heller]]
 
*[[Hermann Hesse]]
 
*[[Henrik Ibsen]]
 
*[[Eugène Ionesco]]
 
*[[Franz Kafka]]
 
*[[Jack Kerouac]]
 
*[[Imre Kertész]]
 
*[[Jerzy Kosinski]]
 
*[[André Malraux]] 
 
*[[Joe McGovern]]
 
*[[Yukio Mishima]]
 
*[[George Oppen]]
 
*[[Chuck Palahniuk]]
 
*[[Walker Percy]]
 
*[[Harold Pinter]]
 
*[[Rainer Maria Rilke]]
 
*[[Alain Robbe-Grillet]]
 
*[[Catherine Robbe-Grillet]]
 
*[[José Saramago]]
 
*[[Nathalie Sarraute]]
 
*[[Claude Simon]]
 
*[[Jean-Paul Sartre]] 
 
*[[Marquis de Sade]] (De Sade predated the existentialist movement, but his writings affected it)
 
*[[Ali Shariati]]
 
*[[Tom Stoppard]]
 
*[[Michael Szymczyk]]
 
*[[Alexander Trocchi]]
 
*[[Richard O. Russell]]
 
*[[Miguel de Unamuno]]
 
*[[Peter Weiss]]
 
*[[O V Vijayan]] (His most famous work Khasakkinte Itihaasam (The Legend of Khasak) deals with existentialism)
 
*[[Kurt Vonnegut]]
 
*[[Richard Wright (author)|Richard Wright]]
 
 
 
===Philosophers===
 
 
* [[Simone de Beauvoir]]
 
* [[Simone de Beauvoir]]
 
* [[Nikolai Berdyaev]]
 
* [[Nikolai Berdyaev]]
 
* [[Henri Bergson]]
 
* [[Henri Bergson]]
 +
* [[Albert Camus]]
 
* [[E. M. Cioran]]
 
* [[E. M. Cioran]]
* [[José Ortega y Gasset]]
+
* [[Martin Heidegger]]  
* [[Martin Heidegger]] (Like Camus, Heidegger rejected the label 'existentialist'.)
 
 
* [[Karl Jaspers]]
 
* [[Karl Jaspers]]
 
* [[Hans Jonas]]
 
* [[Hans Jonas]]
* [[Søren Kierkegaard]] (Kierkegaard died too soon to be a part of the existentialist movement, and it is probable he would have rejected many tenets of Sartre's existentialism. Yet, he was of the first philosophers dealing with the problems of human existence in ways recognizable as forerunners of Sartrean existentialism.)
 
 
* [[Walter Kaufmann]]
 
* [[Walter Kaufmann]]
 +
* [[Søren Kierkegaard]]
 
* [[Ladislav Klíma]]
 
* [[Ladislav Klíma]]
 
* [[Emmanuel Levinas]]
 
* [[Emmanuel Levinas]]
 
* [[Gabriel Marcel]]
 
* [[Gabriel Marcel]]
* [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] (Like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche died too soon to be part of the existentialist movement, and, in many ways differs from the existentialism we know. Yet, his work is precursor to many of the developments in later existentialist thought.)
+
* [[Friedrich Nietzsche]]  
 +
* [[José Ortega y Gasset]]
 +
* [[Ramond Quole]]
 
* [[Jean-Paul Sartre]]
 
* [[Jean-Paul Sartre]]
* [[Albert Camus]]
 
* [[Ramond Quole]]
 
 
* [[Lev Shestov]]
 
* [[Lev Shestov]]
 
* [[Max Stirner]]
 
* [[Max Stirner]]
 
* [[Miguel de Unamuno]]
 
* [[Miguel de Unamuno]]
 +
* [[Colin Henry Wilson|Colin Wilson]]
 
* [[Peter Wessel Zapffe]]
 
* [[Peter Wessel Zapffe]]
* [[Colin Henry Wilson|Colin Wilson]]
 
 
===Psychologists===
 
* [[Ernest Becker]]
 
* [[Ludwig Binswanger]]
 
* [[Medard Boss]]
 
* [[Frantz Fanon]]
 
* [[Viktor Frankl]]
 
* [[R. D. Laing]]
 
* [[Abraham H. Maslow]]
 
* [[Rollo May]]
 
* [[Theodore Shanks]]
 
* [[Fritz Perls]]
 
* [[Otto Rank]]
 
* [[Irvin D. Yalom]]
 
 
===Theologians===
 
*[[Martin Buber]]
 
*[[Rudolf Bultmann]]
 
*[[John Macquarrie]]
 
*[[Gabriel Marcel]]
 
*[[Paul Tillich]]
 
*[[David Layton]]
 
*[[Samuel Kuhn]]
 
 
==Existentialism in popular culture==
 
The [[burlesque]] existentialist is a [[stock character]] of the popular imagination, dressed in black and uttering [[gnomic]] assertions about life and the universe.
 
 
===Film===
 
Existentialist films deal with the concepts of existentialness that are familiar to the average person, such as [[free will]], [[personal identity]], individuality, [[responsibility]], mind versus reality, and what "really matters". The Coen Brothers' ''[[The Man Who Wasn't There]]'', Linklater's ''[[Waking Life]]'', Bergman's ''[[The Seventh Seal]]'' and ''[[Wild Strawberries]]'' are good examples of existential films. Woody Allen films tend to touch the subject, most in a humorous manner; whereas his ''[[Match Point]]'' (2005) provides a more serious consideration of some Existentialist themes.
 
 
===Humour===
 
Existentialism was [[parody|parodied]] in [[Paul Jennings (UK author)|Paul Jennings]]'s theory of [[resistentialism]].
 
It was also themed in the 2004 movie, [[I ♥ Huckabees]].
 
 
===Fiction===
 
In Simon R. Green's book Something From the Nightsde, and its sequels.  The word "existentalist" is used to describe a character by the name of Tommy Oblivion who can believe something and force it into reality.
 
  
 
==References==
 
==References==
*Herbert Marcuse, "Sartre's Existentialism", in ''Studies in Critical Philosophy'', translated by Joris De Bres (London: NLB, 1972)
+
*Buber, Martin. 1987. ''I and Thou.'' New York: Scribner.
*David E. Cooper, "Existentialism: A Reconstruction" (Blackwell, 1999)
+
*Camus, Albert. 1956. ''The Rebel.'' New York: Vintage.
 +
*Cooper, David E. 1999. ''Existentialism: A Reconstruction.'' Blackwell.
 +
*Beauvoir, Simone de. 1982. ''The Ethics of Ambiguity.'' Secaucus, NJ: Citadel Press.
 +
*Heidegger, Martin. 1962. ''Being and Time.'' New York: Harper & Row.
 +
*Heidegger, Martin. 1977. ''Basic Writings.'' San Francisco: Harper.
 +
*Kierkegaard, Søren. 1987. ''Either/Or.'' Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 +
*Kierkegaard, Søren. 1992. ''Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments.'' Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 +
*Marcel, Gabriel. 1964. ''The Mystery of Being.'' Chicago: Gateway.
 +
*Marcuse, Herbert. 1972. "Sartre's Existentialism, Studies in Critical Philosophy.'' London: NLB.
 +
*Maritain, Jacques. 1956. ''Existence and the Existent: An Essay on Christian Existentialism.'' New York: Image.
 +
*Murdoch, Iris. 1998. ''Existentialists and Mystics.'' New York: Penguin.
 +
*Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1972. ''Beyond Good and Evil.'' New York: Penguin.
 +
*Oaklander, L. Nathan. 1992. ''Existentialist Philosophy: An Introduction.'' Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
 +
*Pascal, Blaise. 1966. ''Pensées.'' New York: Penguin.
 +
*Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1956. ''Being and Nothingness.'' New York: Philosophical Library.
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
*[http://web.archive.org/web/20040205085207/http://www.columbia.edu/~ta63/exist.htm Essays on Existentialism]
+
All links retrieved March 23, 2024.
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existentialism/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Existentialism]
+
 
*[http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/sartre/works/exist/sartre.htm "Existentialism is a Humanism", a lecture given by Jean-Paul Sartre]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/existentialism/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Existentialism]  
*[http://counsellingresource.com/types/existential/index.html An Introduction to Existential Counselling]
+
*[http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/sartre/works/exist/sartre.htm "Existentialism is a Humanism," a lecture given by Jean-Paul Sartre]
*[http://www.tameri.com/csw/exist/ ''The Existential Primer'']
+
*[http://counsellingresource.com/types/existential/index.html An Introduction to Existential Counselling]  
*[http://www.stirrings-still.org Stirrings Still]: The International Journal of Existential Literature
+
*[http://www.tameri.com/csw/exist/ ''The Existential Primer'']  
*[http://philowiki.com/wiki/index.php/Existentialism_Debate_Guide: Existentialism Debate Guide]
 
{{Modernism}}
 
  
{{Philosophy navigation}}
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
  
 
[[Category:Ethics]]
 
[[Category:Ethics]]
[[Category:Existentialism]]
 
 
[[Category:Metaphysics]]
 
[[Category:Metaphysics]]
[[Category:Modernism]]
 
[[Category:Secularism]]
 
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
  
 
{{Credit|54987626}}
 
{{Credit|54987626}}

Latest revision as of 23:54, 24 March 2024


Existentialism is a philosophical movement that arose in the twentieth century. It includes a number of thinkers who emphasize common themes, but whose ultimate metaphysical views often diverge radically because they believe the universe is unfathomable. Philosophically the term “existentialism” came to be associated primarily with the French philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre. Many other philosophers who are often tied to the existential movement, such as Martin Heidegger, Gabriel Marcel, and Karl Jaspers, rejected the term “existentialism,” though they continued to deal with existential themes broadly construed. In German, the phrase Existenzphilosophie (philosophy of existence) is also used. Some of the common themes that unite these various existential thinkers are anxiety, boredom, freedom, will, subjectivity, awareness of death, risk, responsibility, and consciousness of existing. Perhaps the central issue that draws these thinkers together, however, is their emphasis upon the primacy of existence in philosophical questioning and the importance of responsible human action in the face of uncertainty.

Although, as a movement, existentialism is considered a twentieth-century phenomenon, its roots go back to earlier existential thinkers, such as Blaise Pascal in the seventeenth century, and particularly Søren Kierkegaard and Friedrich Nietzsche in the nineteenth century. Both Kierkegaard and Nietzsche emphasized the subjective element in thinking and the primacy of the will over purely logical or conceptual objectivity. In the twentieth century, Heidegger’s notion of “being-in-the-world” and Sartre’s idea of “existence preceding essence” became two of the most important themes in existential thought. Other more Christian or theistic existential perspectives were also developed. Moreover, existential ideas became very influential in areas outside of philosophy, such as in psychology and the popular arts.

Main themes

The emphasis on existence by existential thinkers is often summarized in Sartre’s famous assertion that “existence precedes essence.” Although the various philosophers differ in regard to the nature of this priority and the reasons for it, their thought can all be called existential in the broad sense because of the priority they give to existence or being. For this reason, these thinkers share the assumption that existence precedes essence in that existence or being exceeds all rational conceptions and objective or scientific knowledge of it. Or, to paraphrase the words of Shakespeare’s Hamlet, there is more in heaven and earth than in all of philosophy. This leads some of the more radical existentialists to take what opponents consider to be an irrational or anti-philosophic position.

Another aspect of “existence preceding essence” is the idea that human beings are in Heidegger's phrase "thrown" into existence. Existential thought, therefore, differs from the modern Western rationalist tradition extending from Descartes to Husserl in that it rejects the idea that the most certain and primary reality is rational consciousness. Descartes argued that humans could think away everything that exists and so doubt its reality, but they could not think away or doubt the thinking consciousness itself. This reality of consciousness is more certain than any other reality. Existentialism decisively rejects this argument. Instead, it asserts that humans always already find themselves in a world. That is, they find themselves in a prior context and history that is given to and situated within their consciousness. The priority, or a priori and a posteriori, therefore, is not thinking consciousness, but according to Heidegger, "being-in-the-world." Many existentialists consider this “being thrown into existence” as prior to, and the horizon or context of, all other thoughts or ideas about who human beings are. For Heidegger, this “facticity” of being thrown into existence means a supreme being determines who and what humans are, while for Sartre it means that the definitions of what it means to be human is something humans choose and create.

The recognition of human freedom leads existential philosophers to emphasize will over reason. Many of them view action and decision, therefore, as fundamental to human existence. This position is opposed to rationalism and positivism, where reason is the sufficient means of determining “what we should do.” Existentialists argue against definitions of human beings as primarily rational, knowing subjects who relate to reality as an object of knowledge. Moreover, they deny human actions can or ought to be regulated strictly by rational principles or laws. They also reject the notion that human beings can be defined in terms of their behavior as in empirical science. They stress, then, the ambiguity and risk of life and the anxiety of having to choose in existential situations. This leads some of the atheistic existentialists to view human beings as subjects in an indifferent and absurd universe where meaning is not provided by the natural order. Meaning, then, must be created, however provisionally and unstably, by the actions and interpretations of individuals. They emphasize the authenticity that is needed in accepting responsibility for decisions. More theistic interpretations will likewise emphasize freedom, risk, and decision not by denying any ultimate or absolute Truth, but by arguing that the individual must appropriate and so subjectively discover the Truth for oneself. In turn, only by living the truth can one be said to know the truth. Both atheistic and theistic versions of existentialism share the view that the individual must pursue the question of the meaning of existence, and that this question is above all other scientific and philosophic pursuits.

Origins

An early forerunner of existentialism was Blaise Pascal. In 1670, his book Pensées was published; in the work he described many fundamental existential themes. Pascal argued that life without God is meaningless and miserable. When people are exposed to their own emptiness, they create obstacles in order to overcome them and in this way attempt to escape boredom. These token-victories are merely diversions people use to distract themselves from their spiritual poverty and the recognition that one day they will die. According to Pascal this recognition of the reality of mortal existence is good reason for humans not to be atheistic. Thus, he presented his famous “wager” where the gambling believer has everything to gain and nothing to lose by putting his chips on the hope that there is a God, while the gambling unbeliever has nothing to gain and everything to lose by his unbelief. Sartre and other later atheistic existentialists will view this attempt at avoiding the inevitability of death as “bad faith” and as a refusal to accept the truth of human condition.

The Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard (1813–1855) is often called the "father of existentialism." Kierkegaard is commonly considered more of a religious thinker (or “religious poet” as he sometimes called himself) than a philosopher, for he never practiced or espoused a systematic or methodical way of thinking. In fact, in large part, his works were a polemic against modern philosophical rationalism with its emphasis on method, which had begun with Descartes and culminated in Hegel. Given Kierkegaard’s suspicion regarding the absolute reliability of reason, he often wrote under pseudonymous names. The reason for this was not to conceal his true identity but to distance himself (as an existential person) from the concepts and ideas contained in his works (as a thinker). Moreover, much of his work is ironic, in imitation of his mentor Socrates, and so these pseudonymous works should be read more like literature than straightforward philosophy (just as a reader of a novel should not mistake the ideas of a character with those of the author herself).

Nevertheless, Kierkegaard is often associated with the ideas of his pseudonyms and in particular the pseudonymous author Johannes Climacus who said that "truth is subjectivity" and that the person of faith must make a kind of “leap.” Although the conflation of Kierkegaard with Climacus is a mistake, it cannot be denied the philosophical tenets of Climacus did have a major influence on the twentieth-century existential movement. Furthermore, the term “leap of faith” is frequently employed by both defenders and critics of twentieth-century existentialism who view the idea as signifying the need for choice and risk by the individual in deciding life’s ultimate meaning.

For Kierkegaard the idea of subjectivity signified the infinite depth dimension of human beings and so should not be understood as opposed to rational objectivity but rather as going beyond it. Understanding is always finite and so it can never fully grasp who or what people are as human beings. Or to put it another way, the apprehension of human’s existential selfhood extends beyond any philosophical definition of what a human being is. For this reason, the full extent of being human can only be apprehended from the inside, in terms of lived experience, and not from the outside, in terms of any scientific or objective definition, be it biological, psychological, or any other scientific theory of human nature.

Friedrich Nietzsche was also a forerunner of the existential movement in his critique of Western culture and philosophy, in particular Plato and Christianity (which he called “Platonism for the masses”). Nietzsche realized that human nature and human identity vary depending on what values and beliefs humans hold. Although Nietzsche’s work, like Kierkegaard’s, is often ironic and ambiguous (and so open to different interpretations), he did frequently write about the capacity of human beings to create or recreate themselves. In this sense, then, Nietzsche influenced later existential thinkers such as Sartre (in his emphasis on freedom and choice) and Heidegger (in his emphasis on creativity and history).

In literature, the most famous nineteenth-century existential writer was Fyodor Dostoevsky. The statement by one of his characters that “without God everything is permissible” was taken up by both theistic and atheistic twentieth-century existential thinkers.

Twentieth-century existentialism

The thought of the major existential philosophers of the twentieth century grew out of the phenomenology of Husserl, which attempted to critique positivism and psychologism by grounding all perception, experience, and knowledge in structures of human consciousness. Husserl stressed that being is always being for a consciousness, or that consciousness is always consciousness of something. Heidegger transformed this into the core existential notion that being is always being, not for a pure consciousness, but rather for a concrete existence. This means that consciousness is a property of human existence (Dasein), which has "being-in-the-world" and so exists in a historical context. Heidegger, however, came to reject the idea that his philosophy was “existentialist.”

Jean-Paul Sartre, on the other hand, embraced the term existentialism. His version of existentialism is set out in popular form in his 1946 essay L'Existentialisme est un humanisme, translated as “Existentialism is a Humanism.” In the essay he asserts his famous dictum, "Existence precedes essence," which is generally taken to mean that there is no predefined essence to humanity and so people must decide for themselves the meaning of existence. Sartrean existentialism takes it for granted that there is no God, and so for this reason essence or the nature of human beings cannot precede their existence. For how could there be an idea or definition of what human nature essentially is if there is no Creator or Divine Mind who created it? Sartre holds that human beings are not only free to act as they choose, but they have a responsibility to do so. They must accept the forlornness of their condition in that there is no God and so no preexisting moral principles, nature, or laws that can tell them what to do. Instead, they are on their own and so must decide for themselves. But in choosing for themselves “[they] choose all humanity.” Moreover, for Sartre it is human actions that determine who humans are. They cannot blame their environment, circumstance, or chance for their successes and failures. Rather it is their actions that make them who they are and these are determined by their own choices.

Albert Camus was another well-known writer and thinker associated with existentialism. Camus famously compared human condition to the myth of Sisyphus. Sisyphus is condemned each day to roll a rock up a hill only to have the rock, once it is almost to the top, roll back down. The next day Sisyphus must start all over despite knowing the result will be the same. Likewise, human beings must stoically roll the rock up the hill each day by creating their own meaning despite knowing the universe is essentially absurd and meaningless. Camus depicted many of his existential themes in fiction and drama, such as The Stranger, The Plague, The Fall, and The Possessed.

Gabriel Marcel developed a kind of Christian existentialism, though he, like Heidegger, rejected the term and instead preferred to call himself a “Christian Socratic.” Other theistic existentialists include Paul Tillich, Miguel de Unamuno, and Martin Buber. Nikolai Berdyaev developed a philosophy of Christian existentialism in his native Russia, and later in France, in the decades preceding World War II. Though these existential theists did not accept Sartre’s and Camus’ notion that the universe is absurd and meaning must be created by the individual, they nevertheless also distanced themselves from rationalist philosophies and insisted that the individual must participate in being or existence in order to come to a deeper appreciation and fuller understanding of it. Jacques Maritain and Etienne Gilson in a different way developed an existential Thomism, which took many of the insights and approaches of the existential movement, but applied and attributed them to the metaphysics of St. Thomas Aquinas.

Criticisms of existentialism

Herbert Marcuse criticized existentialism from a Marxist perspective, especially Sartre's Being and Nothingness, for projecting certain features, such as anxiety and meaninglessness, which really derive from the modern experience of living in an oppressive society, onto the nature of existence itself:

In so far as Existentialism is a philosophical doctrine, it remains an idealistic doctrine: it hypothesizes specific historical conditions of human existence into ontological and metaphysical characteristics. Existentialism thus becomes part of the very ideology which it attacks, and its radicalism is illusory (Marcuse 1972, 161).

Theodor Adorno, in his Jargon of Authenticity, criticized Heidegger's philosophy, and in particular Heidegger’s use of language. Adorno viewed this as a mystifying ideology of advanced industrial society and its power structure.

Roger Scruton claimed, in his book From Descartes to Wittgenstein, that both Heidegger's concept of inauthenticity and Sartre's concept of bad faith were incoherent. For both Heidegger and Sartre deny any universal moral creed, yet they speak of these concepts as if everyone were bound to abide by them. In chapter 18, he writes:

In what sense Sartre is able to 'recommend' the authenticity which consists in the purely self-made morality is unclear. He does recommend it, but, by his own argument, his recommendation can have no objective force.

Familiar with this sort of argument, Sartre claimed that bad and good faith do not represent moral ideas; rather, they are ways of being. Heidegger would also claim authenticity as an ontological rather than an ethical way of being.

Logical positivists, such as Carnap and Ayer, claim that existentialists frequently become confused over the verb "to be" in their analyses of "being." The verb is prefixed to a predicate and to use the word without any predicate is meaningless. Borrowing from Kant's argument against the ontological argument for the existence of God, they argue that existence is not a property.

Existentialism in psychotherapy

With complete freedom to decide and be responsible for the outcome of their decisions comes anxiety about the choices humans make. Anxiety's importance in existentialism makes it a popular topic in psychotherapy. Therapists often use existential philosophy to explain the patient's anxiety. Psychotherapists employ an existential approach by encouraging their patients to harness their anxiety and use it constructively. Instead of suppressing anxiety, patients are advised to use it as grounds for change. By embracing anxiety as inevitable, a person can use it to achieve his or her full potential in life.

Logotherapy asserts that all human beings have a will to find meaning, and that serious behavioral problems develop when they cannot find it. The therapy helps patients handle the responsibility of choices and the pain of unavoidable suffering by helping them decide to give life meaning.

Popular Existentialism

In the 1950s and 1960s, existentialism experienced a surge of interest in popular art forms. In fiction, Jack Kerouac and the Beat poets adopted existentialist themes. Hermann Hesse's Steppenwolf was based on an idea in Kierkegaard's Either/Or (1843), and "arthouse" films began quoting and alluding to existentialist thought and thinkers. Simultaneously, in Sartre, Parisian university students found a hero for the May 1968 demonstrations, and others were appropriating the themes found in Camus and Kierkegaard. The despair of choice and the anxiety of the unknowing self featured prominently in cinema and novels.

Existentialist films deal with existential concepts that are familiar to the average person, such as free will, personal identity, individuality, responsibility, mind versus reality, and what "really matters." The Coen Brothers’ The Man Who Wasn't There, Linklater's Waking Life, Bergman's The Seventh Seal and Wild Strawberries, are good examples of existential films. Woody Allen films tend to touch the subject in a humorous manner, though his Match Point (2005) provides a more serious consideration of some existentialist themes. Existential cinema also explores themes such as retaining authenticity in an apathetic, mechanical world; the consciousness of death, e.g., Heidegger's “being towards death”—exemplified in Ingmar Bergman's film The Seventh Seal (1957); and the feelings of alienation and loneliness consequent to being unique in a world of mass media and consumerism.

Major philosophers associated with the movement

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Buber, Martin. 1987. I and Thou. New York: Scribner.
  • Camus, Albert. 1956. The Rebel. New York: Vintage.
  • Cooper, David E. 1999. Existentialism: A Reconstruction. Blackwell.
  • Beauvoir, Simone de. 1982. The Ethics of Ambiguity. Secaucus, NJ: Citadel Press.
  • Heidegger, Martin. 1962. Being and Time. New York: Harper & Row.
  • Heidegger, Martin. 1977. Basic Writings. San Francisco: Harper.
  • Kierkegaard, Søren. 1987. Either/Or. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Kierkegaard, Søren. 1992. Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Marcel, Gabriel. 1964. The Mystery of Being. Chicago: Gateway.
  • Marcuse, Herbert. 1972. "Sartre's Existentialism, Studies in Critical Philosophy. London: NLB.
  • Maritain, Jacques. 1956. Existence and the Existent: An Essay on Christian Existentialism. New York: Image.
  • Murdoch, Iris. 1998. Existentialists and Mystics. New York: Penguin.
  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1972. Beyond Good and Evil. New York: Penguin.
  • Oaklander, L. Nathan. 1992. Existentialist Philosophy: An Introduction. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
  • Pascal, Blaise. 1966. Pensées. New York: Penguin.
  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1956. Being and Nothingness. New York: Philosophical Library.

External links

All links retrieved March 23, 2024.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.