Difference between revisions of "Absolute Idealism" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Mergefrom|Neo-Hegelianism|date=July 2006}}
+
{{claimed}}
 
+
'''Absolute idealism''' is an [[ontology|ontologically]] [[monistic]] philosophy attributed to [[G.W.F. Hegel]]. It is Hegel's account of how [[being]] is ultimately comprehensible as an all-inclusive whole. Hegel asserted that in order for the thinking [[self (psychology)|subject]] (human reason or consciousness) to be able to know its [[object (philosophy)|object]] (the world) at all, there must be in some sense an [[Identity (philosophy)|identity]] of thought and being. Otherwise, the subject would never have access to the object and we would have no certainty about any of our knowledge of the world. To account for the differences between thought and being, however, as well as the richness and diversity of each, the unity of thought and being cannot be expressed as the abstract identity "A=A." Absolute idealism is the attempt to demonstrate this unity using a new "speculative" philosophical method, which requires new concepts and rules of logic. According to Hegel, the absolute ground of being is essentially a dynamic, historical process of necessity that unfolds by itself in the form of increasingly complex forms of being and of consciousness, ultimately giving rise to all the diversity in the world and in the [[concept]]s with which we think and make sense of the world.  
'''Absolute idealism''' is a [[monistic]] [[ontology]] attributed to [[G.W.F. Hegel]]. That is, it is Hegel's account of how [[being]] is ultimately comprehensible as an all-inclusive whole. It posits that in order for the [[self (psychology)|subject]] to relate to the world, or [[object (philosophy)|object]], some necessary point of [[Identity (philosophy)|identity]] between the two must exist. Otherwise, the subject would never have access to the object and we wouldn't be able to know anything about the world. That point of identity must itself give rise to different [[ideas]], including the notion of subject and object, and must be the basis of all the [[concept]]s with which we think and make sense of the world.
 
  
 
==Teachings==
 
==Teachings==
If we try to rationally conceive that [[The Absolute|absolute]] point, we will always fall short. We can describe it using different concepts, but no concept will adequately describe what that absolute is and give rise to a consideration of its opposite. For instance if we hold that the absolute is in fact [[infinity]], then that would mean that the finite would not be part of it, but finity is just as much a part of that underlying absolute as infinity is. The absolute is in fact the unity and ground of these concepts. We learn that every concept has a necessary relation to its opposite. Thoroughly thinking through this relation, one realises that it is present in every way we relate to an object, from an 'immediate' relation to what presents itself in front of my eyes this very moment, to considering the idea of God, or art for example.
 
  
This absolute relation we have to the world creates in this [[dialectic]]al fashion all concepts we use in order to understand the world. This works in the individual mind, but also through history. Our historical development – which Hegel called "[[spirit]]" – can be seen as a journey through stages of explanations of the world. Each successive explanation created problems and oppositions within itself, leading to tensions which could only be overcome by adopting a view that could accommodate these oppositions in a higher unity. At the base of spirit lies a rational development. This means that the absolute itself is exactly that rational development. The [[assertion]] that "All reality is spirit" means that all of reality rationally orders itself and while doing so creates the oppositions we find in it. Even [[nature]] is not different from the spirit since it itself is ordered by the determinations given to us by spirit. Nature, as that which is not spirit is so determined by spirit, therefore it follows that nature is not absolutely other, but understood as other and therefore not essentially alien.  
+
For Hegel, the interaction of opposites generates in [[dialectic]]al fashion all concepts we use in order to understand the world. Moreover, this development occurs not only in the individual mind, but also through history. In the ''Phenomenology of Spirit'', for example, Hegel presents a history of human consciousness as a journey through stages of explanations of the world. Each successive explanation created problems and oppositions within itself, leading to tensions which could only be overcome by adopting a view that could accommodate these oppositions in a higher unity. At the base of spirit lies a rational development. This means that the absolute itself is exactly that rational development. The [[assertion]] that "All reality is spirit" means that all of reality rationally orders itself and while doing so creates the oppositions we find in it. Even [[nature]] is not different from the spirit since it itself is ordered by the determinations given to us by spirit. Nature, as that which is not spirit is so determined by spirit, therefore it follows that nature is not absolutely other, but understood as other and therefore not essentially alien.  
  
 
The aim of Hegel was to show that we do not relate to the world as if it is other from us, but that we continue to find ourselves back into that world. With the realisation that both my mind and the world are ordered according to the same rational principles, our access to the world has been made secure, a security which was lost after Kant proclaimed the 'Ding an sich' to be ultimately inaccessible.  
 
The aim of Hegel was to show that we do not relate to the world as if it is other from us, but that we continue to find ourselves back into that world. With the realisation that both my mind and the world are ordered according to the same rational principles, our access to the world has been made secure, a security which was lost after Kant proclaimed the 'Ding an sich' to be ultimately inaccessible.  
  
The Absolute Idealist position should be distinguished from [[Berkeleyan Idealism]] ([[George Berkeley|Berkeley]]), [[Transcendental Idealism]] ([[Kant]]), [[subjective idealism]] ([[Fichte]]), and [[Objective Idealism]] ([[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling|Schelling]]).
+
The Absolute Idealist position should be distinguished from [[Berkeleyan Idealism]] ([[George Berkeley|Berkeley]]), [[Transcendental Idealism]] ([[Kant]]), [[subjective idealism]] ([[Fichte]]), and [[Objective idealism]] ([[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling|Schelling]]).
  
 
==German Idealism==
 
==German Idealism==
Line 23: Line 21:
 
==British idealism==
 
==British idealism==
  
'''British idealism''' does not refer to all idealist philosophers who happened to be British (e.g. Berekley), rather british idealism was a philosophical movement that was influential in Britain during the mid to late [[nineteenth century]] and the early [[twentieth century]]. The leading figures in the movement were [[Thomas Hill Green|T.H. Green]] (1836-1882), [[F.H. Bradley]] (1846-1924), and [[Bernard Bosanquet (philosopher)|Bernard Bosanquet]] (1848-1923). They were succeeded by the second generation of [[J. M. E. McTaggart]], [[H. H. Joachim]], [[J. H. Muirhead]], and [[G. R. G. Mure]]. The doctrines of British idealism so provoked the young Cambridge philosophers [[G. E. Moore]] and [[Bertrand Russell]] that they gave birth to [[analytic philosophy]].
+
'''British idealism''' does not refer to all idealist philosophers who happened to be British (e.g. Berkeley), but rather to a philosophical movement that was influential in Britain from the mid-[[nineteenth century]] to the early [[twentieth century]]. The leading figures in the movement were [[Thomas Hill Green|T.H. Green]] (1836-1882), [[F.H. Bradley]] (1846-1924), and [[Bernard Bosanquet (philosopher)|Bernard Bosanquet]] (1848-1923). They were succeeded by the second generation of [[J. M. E. McTaggart]], [[H. H. Joachim]], [[J. H. Muirhead]], and [[G. R. G. Mure]]. The doctrines of British idealism so provoked the young Cambridge philosophers [[G. E. Moore]] and [[Bertrand Russell]] that they gave birth to [[analytic philosophy]].
  
 
Though much more variegated than some commentaries would seem to suggest, British idealism was generally marked by several broad tendencies: a belief in an [[The Absolute|Absolute]] (a single all-encompassing reality that in some sense formed a coherent and all-inclusive system); the assignment of a high place to [[reason]] as both the faculty by which the Absolute's structure is grasped and as that structure itself; and a fundamental unwillingness to accept a dichotomy between thought and object, reality consisting of thought-and-object together in a strongly coherent unity.
 
Though much more variegated than some commentaries would seem to suggest, British idealism was generally marked by several broad tendencies: a belief in an [[The Absolute|Absolute]] (a single all-encompassing reality that in some sense formed a coherent and all-inclusive system); the assignment of a high place to [[reason]] as both the faculty by which the Absolute's structure is grasped and as that structure itself; and a fundamental unwillingness to accept a dichotomy between thought and object, reality consisting of thought-and-object together in a strongly coherent unity.
  
In some sense this movement was a development of the [[German idealism|German Idealist]] movement — particularly such philosophers as [[Immanuel Kant]] and [[G.W.F. Hegel]], who were characterised by Green, among others, as the salvation of British philosophy after the alleged demise of [[empiricism]]. The movement was certainly a reaction against the thinking of [[John Locke]], [[David Hume]], [[John Stuart Mill]], [[Henry Sidgwick]], and other [[utilitarianism|utilitarian]]s. Some of those involved would have denied any specific influence, particularly in respect of Hegel. Nevertheless, [[James Hutchison Stirling]]'s book ''[[The Secret of Hegel]]'' is believed to have won significant converts in [[Britain]].  
+
British idealism largely developed from the [[German idealism|German Idealist]] movement—particularly such philosophers as [[Immanuel Kant]] and [[G.W.F. Hegel]], who were characterised by Green, among others, as the salvation of British philosophy after the alleged demise of [[empiricism]]. The movement was certainly a reaction against the thinking of [[John Locke]], [[David Hume]], [[John Stuart Mill]], [[Henry Sidgwick]], and other empiricists and [[utilitarianism|utilitarian]]s. Some of those involved would have denied any specific influence, particularly in respect of Hegel. Nevertheless, [[James Hutchison Stirling]]'s book ''[[The Secret of Hegel]]'' is believed to have won significant converts in [[United Kingdom|Britain]].  
  
Certainly British idealism was influenced by Hegel at least in broad outline, and undeniably adopted some of his terminology and doctrines. Examples include not only the aforementioned Absolute, but also a [[doctrine of internal relations]], a [[coherentism|coherence theory of truth]], and a concept of a concrete [[Universal (metaphysics)|universal]]. Some commentators have also pointed to a sort of dialectical structure in e.g. some of the writings of Bradley. But none of the British idealists adopted Hegel's philosophy wholesale, and his most significant writings on [[logic]] seem to have found no purchase whatsoever in their thought (nor in British thought generally).
+
British idealism was influenced by Hegel at least in broad outline, and undeniably adopted some of Hegel's terminology and doctrines. Examples include not only the aforementioned Absolute, but also a [[doctrine of internal relations]], a [[coherentism|coherence theory of truth]], and a concept of a concrete [[Universal (metaphysics)|universal]]. Some commentators have also pointed to a sort of dialectical structure in e.g. some of the writings of Bradley. But none of the British idealists adopted Hegel's philosophy wholesale, and his most significant writings on [[logic]] seem to have found no purchase whatsoever in their thought (nor in British thought generally).
  
On its political side, the British idealists were largely concerned to refute what they regarded as a brittle and "atomistic" form of [[individualism]], as espoused by e.g. [[Herbert Spencer]]. In their view, humans are fundamentally social beings in a manner and to a degree not adequately recognized by Spencer and his followers. The British idealists did not, however, reify the State in the manner that Hegel apparently did; Green in particular spoke of the individual as the sole locus of value and contended that the State's existence was justified only insofar as it contributed to the realization of value in the lives of individual persons.
+
On its political side, the British idealists were largely concerned to refute what they regarded as a brittle and "atomistic" form of [[individualism]], as espoused by e.g. [[Herbert Spencer]]. In their view, humans are fundamentally social beings in a manner and to a degree not adequately recognized by Spencer and his followers. The British Idealists did not, however, reify the State in the manner that Hegel apparently did; Green in particular spoke of the individual as the sole locus of value and contended that the State's existence was justified only insofar as it contributed to the realization of value in the lives of individual persons.
  
The hold of British idealism in the [[United Kingdom|UK]] weakened when [[Bertrand Russell]] and [[G.E. Moore]] turned against it, and their education in the tradition. Moore in particular delivered what quickly came to be accepted as conclusive arguments against Idealism. At that point British philosophy in general revolted once more against [[metaphysics]] in general. The later work of [[R.G. Collingwood]] was a turning back, if relatively isolated. Among present-day UK philosophers the best-known exponent of absolute idealism is probably [[Timothy L.S. Sprigge]].
+
The hold of British idealism in the [[United Kingdom|UK]] weakened when [[Bertrand Russell]] and [[G.E. Moore]], who were educated in the British idealist tradition, turned against it. Moore in particular delivered what quickly came to be accepted as conclusive arguments against Idealism. At that point British philosophy in general revolted once more against [[metaphysics]] in general. The later work of [[R.G. Collingwood]] was a relatively isolated exception. Among present-day UK philosophers the best-known exponent of absolute idealism is probably [[Timothy L.S. Sprigge]].
  
British idealism's influence in the [[United States]] was somewhat limited. The early thought of [[Josiah Royce]] had something of a neo-Hegelian cast, as did that of a handful of his less famous contemporaries. American rationalist [[Brand Blanshard]] was so strongly influenced by Bradley, Bosanquet, and Green (and other British philosophers) that he could almost be classified as a British philosopher himself. Even this limited influence, though, did not last out the [[twentieth century]].
+
British idealism's influence in the [[United States]] was somewhat limited. The early thought of [[Josiah Royce]] had something of a neo-Hegelian cast, as did that of a handful of his less famous contemporaries. The American rationalist [[Brand Blanshard]] was so strongly influenced by Bradley, Bosanquet, and Green (and other British philosophers) that he could almost be classified as a British philosopher himself. Even this limited influence, though, did not last out the [[twentieth century]].
  
 
===References===
 
===References===
 
*[[William Ritchie Sorley]], ''A History of British Philosophy to 1900'', is an idiosyncratic account of the British tradition centred in British Idealism, first published 1920 as ''A History of English Philosophy''
 
*[[William Ritchie Sorley]], ''A History of British Philosophy to 1900'', is an idiosyncratic account of the British tradition centred in British Idealism, first published 1920 as ''A History of English Philosophy''
 +
 +
==Neo-Hegelianism==
 +
Neo-Hegelianism is a school (or schools) of thought associated and inspired by the works of [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]], a [[German idealist]] [[philosopher]] active around the year 1800.  During the late 19th and early 20th century, many European and American philosophers revived interest in Hegel's works, especially those pertaining to the importance of spirit, and the belief that ideas and moral ideals are fundamental.
 +
 +
===Hegelianism after Hegel===
 +
 +
Although Hegel died in 1831, his philosophy lived on. In politics, there was a developing schism, even before his death,  between [[right Hegelians]] and [[left Hegelians]]. [[Marxism]] developed out of the latter group.
 +
 +
In [[philosophy of religion]], Hegel's influence soon became very powerful in the English-speaking world. The British school, called [[British idealism]] and partly Hegelian in inspiration, included [[Thomas Hill Green]], [[William Wallace (Scottish philosopher)|William Wallace]], [[F.H. Bradley]] and [[Edward Caird]]. It was primarily directed towards [[political philosophy]].
 +
 +
America saw the development of a school of Hegelian thought in [[St. Louis, Missouri|St. Louis]], [[Missouri]] even when that city was barely past its own [[frontier]] stage.
 +
 +
===German twentieth-century neo-Hegelians===
 +
 +
In Germany there was a neo-Hegelianism ''(neohegelianismus)'' of the early [[twentieth century]], partly developing out of the [[Neo-Kantian]]s. [[Richard Kroner]] wrote one of its leading works, a history of [[German idealism]] from a Hegelian point of view.
 +
 +
=== Other notable neo-Hegelians ===
 +
 +
*[[Francis Herbert Bradley]] (1846 - 1924), a British [[absolute idealist]] who adapted Hegel's Metaphysics.
 +
 +
*[[Josiah Royce]] (1855 - 1916), an American defender of [[absolute idealism]].
 +
 +
*[[Benedetto Croce]] (1866 - 1952), an Italian philosopher who defended Hegel's account on how we understand history.  Croce wrote primarily on topics of [[Aesthetics]], such as artistic inspiration/intuition and personal expression.
 +
 +
*[[Bertrand Russell]] (1872 - 1970), an influential British [[mathematician]], [[philosopher]], and [[logician]], working mostly in the [[20th century]]. Russell, however, shed his neo-Hegelianism in his early years.
 +
 +
*[[Giovanni Gentile]] (1875-1944), important philosopher within the [[fascist]] movement. Ghost-wrote "The Doctrine of Fascism"
  
 
== Criticisms ==
 
== Criticisms ==
Generally speaking, criticisms of absolute idealism come specifically from the standpoint of analytic philosophy, which criticised Hegel's work as hopelessly obscure, and existentialist philosophy, proponents of which criticise Hegel for ultimately choosing an essentialistic whole over the particularity of existence. Epistemologically, one of the main problems plaguing Hegel's system is how these thought determinations have bearing on reality as such. A perennial problem of his metaphysics seems to be the question of how spirit externalises itself and how the concepts it generates can say anything true about nature. At the same time, they will have to, because otherwise Hegel's system concepts would say nothing about something that is not itself a concept and the system would come down to being only an intricate game involving vacuous concepts.
+
Exponents of [[analytic philosophy]], which has been the dominant form of Anglo-American philosophy for most of the last century, have criticised Hegel's work as hopelessly obscure. [[Existentialism|Existentialists]] also criticise Hegel for ultimately choosing an essentialistic whole over the particularity of existence. Epistemologically, one of the main problems plaguing Hegel's system is how these thought determinations have bearing on reality as such. A perennial problem of his metaphysics seems to be the question of how spirit externalises itself and how the concepts it generates can say anything true about nature. At the same time, they will have to, because otherwise Hegel's system concepts would say nothing about something that is not itself a concept and the system would come down to being only an intricate game involving vacuous concepts.
  
 
=== Schopenhauer ===
 
=== Schopenhauer ===
[[Schopenhauer]] noted that [[Hegel]] created his absolute idealism after [[Kant]] had discredited all proofs of [[God]]'s existence. The Absolute is a non-personal substitute for the concept of God. It is the one subject that perceives the [[universe]] as one object. Individuals share in parts of this [[perception]]. Since the [[universe]] exists as an [[idea]] in the [[mind]] of the Absolute, it copies [[Spinoza]]'s [[pantheism]] in which everything is in God or [[Nature]].
+
[[Schopenhauer]] noted that [[Hegel]] created his absolute idealism after [[Kant]] had discredited all proofs of [[God]]'s existence. The Absolute is a non-personal substitute for the concept of God. It is the one subject that perceives the [[universe]] as one object. Individuals share in parts of this [[perception]]. Since the universe exists as an [[idea]] in the [[mind]] of the Absolute, it copies [[Spinoza]]'s [[panentheism]] in which everything is in God or [[Nature]].
  
 
=== Moore and Russell ===
 
=== Moore and Russell ===
  
Famously, G.E. Moore’s rebellion against absolutism found expression in his defense of common sense against the radically counterintuitive conclusions of absolutism (e.g. time is unreal, change is unreal, separateness is unreal, imperfection is unreal, etc.). G.E. Moore also pioneered the use of logical analysis against the absolutists, which Bertrand Russell promulgated and began the entire tradition of analytic philosophy with its use against the philosophies of his direct predecessors. In recounting his own mental development Russell reports, "For some years after throwing over [absolutism] I had an optimistic riot of opposite beliefs. I thought that whatever Hegel had denied must be true." (Russell in Barrett and Adkins 1962, p.477) Also:
+
Famously, G.E. Moore’s rebellion against absolutism found expression in his defense of common sense against the radically counter-intuitive conclusions of absolutism (e.g. time is unreal, change is unreal, separateness is unreal, imperfection is unreal, etc.). G.E. Moore also pioneered the use of logical analysis against the absolutists, which Bertrand Russell promulgated and began the entire tradition of analytic philosophy with its use against the philosophies of his direct predecessors. In recounting his own mental development Russell reports, "For some years after throwing over [absolutism] I had an optimistic riot of opposite beliefs. I thought that whatever Hegel had denied must be true." (Russell in Barrett and Adkins 1962, p.477) Also:
 
{{Quotation|G.E. Moore took the lead in the rebellion, and I followed, with a sense of emancipation. [Absolutism] argued that everything common sense believes in is mere appearance. We reverted to the opposite extreme, and thought that everything is real that common sense, uninfluenced by philosophy or theology, supposes real.|[[Bertrand Russell]]; as quoted in Klemke 2000, p.28}}
 
{{Quotation|G.E. Moore took the lead in the rebellion, and I followed, with a sense of emancipation. [Absolutism] argued that everything common sense believes in is mere appearance. We reverted to the opposite extreme, and thought that everything is real that common sense, uninfluenced by philosophy or theology, supposes real.|[[Bertrand Russell]]; as quoted in Klemke 2000, p.28}}
 
{{sectstub}}
 
{{sectstub}}
Line 62: Line 87:
  
 
==Relation to science==  
 
==Relation to science==  
Absolute idealism or Hegelianism has influenced the Humanities to a great extent. In German they are called "Geisteswissenschaften" and in Dutch "Geesteswetenschappen", a direct influence of the Hegelian notion of spirit (Geist). In sociology for instance the position of important sociologist Ralph Dahrendorf is inspired by Hegel.  
+
Absolute idealism or Hegelianism has influenced the Humanities to a great extent. In German they are called "Geisteswissenschaften" and in Dutch "Geesteswetenschappen," a direct influence of the Hegelian notion of spirit (Geist). In sociology for instance the position of important sociologist Ralph Dahrendorf is inspired by Hegel.  
  
 
Lately American historian Francis Fukuyama was inspired by an alleged thesis of Hegel, namely the End of History, to write an immensely popular book. That Hegel proclaimed the end of history though is a myth popularised by the French Hegel interpreter Aleksandr Kojeve.  
 
Lately American historian Francis Fukuyama was inspired by an alleged thesis of Hegel, namely the End of History, to write an immensely popular book. That Hegel proclaimed the end of history though is a myth popularised by the French Hegel interpreter Aleksandr Kojeve.  
Line 69: Line 94:
  
 
==Influence==  
 
==Influence==  
Absolute idealism has greatly altered the philosophical landscape. Paradoxically, (though, from a Hegelian point of view, maybe not paradoxically at all) this influence is mostly felt in the strong opposition it engendered. Both [[Logical positivism]] and [[Analytic philosophy]] grew out of a rebellion against Hegelianism prevalent in England during the 19th century. Continental [[phenomenology]], [[existentialism]] and [[post-modernism]] also seek to 'free themselves from Hegel's thought'. [[Martin Heidegger]], one of the leading figures of [[Continental philosophy]] in the 20th century, sought to distance himself from Hegel's work. One of Heidegger's philosophical themes was "overcoming metaphysics".
+
Absolute idealism has greatly altered the philosophical landscape. Paradoxically, (though, from a Hegelian point of view, maybe not paradoxically at all) this influence is mostly felt in the strong opposition it engendered. Both [[logical positivism]] and [[analytic philosophy]] grew out of a rebellion against Hegelianism prevalent in England during the 19th century. Continental [[phenomenology]], [[existentialism]] and [[post-modernism]] also seek to 'free themselves from Hegel's thought'. [[Martin Heidegger]], one of the leading figures of [[Continental philosophy]] in the 20th century, sought to distance himself from Hegel's work. One of Heidegger's philosophical themes was "overcoming metaphysics."
  
 
==See also==
 
==See also==
Line 84: Line 109:
 
*''A History of Christian Thought'' (Tillich)
 
*''A History of Christian Thought'' (Tillich)
 
*''From Socrates to Sartre'' (Lavine)
 
*''From Socrates to Sartre'' (Lavine)
*''Hegel: Een inleidng'' (Ed. Ad Verbrugge et al) (in Dutch)
+
*''Hegel: Een inleiding'' (Ed. Ad Verbrugge et al) (in Dutch)
 
*''Hegels Idealism, The Satisfactions of Self Consciousness'' (Pippin)  
 
*''Hegels Idealism, The Satisfactions of Self Consciousness'' (Pippin)  
 
*''Endings, Questions of Memory in Hegel and Heidegger'' (Ed. Mc Cumber, Comay)
 
*''Endings, Questions of Memory in Hegel and Heidegger'' (Ed. Mc Cumber, Comay)
  
 +
[[Category:Idealism]]
 +
[[Category:Georg Hegel]]
 
[[Category:Philosophical theories]]
 
[[Category:Philosophical theories]]
 
[[Category:British philosophy]]
 
[[Category:British philosophy]]
 
[[Category:History of the United Kingdom]]
 
[[Category:History of the United Kingdom]]
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
  
{{credit|103743733}}
+
{{credit|165803920}}

Revision as of 22:04, 14 November 2007

Absolute idealism is an ontologically monistic philosophy attributed to G.W.F. Hegel. It is Hegel's account of how being is ultimately comprehensible as an all-inclusive whole. Hegel asserted that in order for the thinking subject (human reason or consciousness) to be able to know its object (the world) at all, there must be in some sense an identity of thought and being. Otherwise, the subject would never have access to the object and we would have no certainty about any of our knowledge of the world. To account for the differences between thought and being, however, as well as the richness and diversity of each, the unity of thought and being cannot be expressed as the abstract identity "A=A." Absolute idealism is the attempt to demonstrate this unity using a new "speculative" philosophical method, which requires new concepts and rules of logic. According to Hegel, the absolute ground of being is essentially a dynamic, historical process of necessity that unfolds by itself in the form of increasingly complex forms of being and of consciousness, ultimately giving rise to all the diversity in the world and in the concepts with which we think and make sense of the world.

Teachings

For Hegel, the interaction of opposites generates in dialectical fashion all concepts we use in order to understand the world. Moreover, this development occurs not only in the individual mind, but also through history. In the Phenomenology of Spirit, for example, Hegel presents a history of human consciousness as a journey through stages of explanations of the world. Each successive explanation created problems and oppositions within itself, leading to tensions which could only be overcome by adopting a view that could accommodate these oppositions in a higher unity. At the base of spirit lies a rational development. This means that the absolute itself is exactly that rational development. The assertion that "All reality is spirit" means that all of reality rationally orders itself and while doing so creates the oppositions we find in it. Even nature is not different from the spirit since it itself is ordered by the determinations given to us by spirit. Nature, as that which is not spirit is so determined by spirit, therefore it follows that nature is not absolutely other, but understood as other and therefore not essentially alien.

The aim of Hegel was to show that we do not relate to the world as if it is other from us, but that we continue to find ourselves back into that world. With the realisation that both my mind and the world are ordered according to the same rational principles, our access to the world has been made secure, a security which was lost after Kant proclaimed the 'Ding an sich' to be ultimately inaccessible.

The Absolute Idealist position should be distinguished from Berkeleyan Idealism (Berkeley), Transcendental Idealism (Kant), subjective idealism (Fichte), and Objective idealism (Schelling).

German Idealism

Main article: German idealism

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

British idealism

British idealism does not refer to all idealist philosophers who happened to be British (e.g. Berkeley), but rather to a philosophical movement that was influential in Britain from the mid-nineteenth century to the early twentieth century. The leading figures in the movement were T.H. Green (1836-1882), F.H. Bradley (1846-1924), and Bernard Bosanquet (1848-1923). They were succeeded by the second generation of J. M. E. McTaggart, H. H. Joachim, J. H. Muirhead, and G. R. G. Mure. The doctrines of British idealism so provoked the young Cambridge philosophers G. E. Moore and Bertrand Russell that they gave birth to analytic philosophy.

Though much more variegated than some commentaries would seem to suggest, British idealism was generally marked by several broad tendencies: a belief in an Absolute (a single all-encompassing reality that in some sense formed a coherent and all-inclusive system); the assignment of a high place to reason as both the faculty by which the Absolute's structure is grasped and as that structure itself; and a fundamental unwillingness to accept a dichotomy between thought and object, reality consisting of thought-and-object together in a strongly coherent unity.

British idealism largely developed from the German Idealist movement—particularly such philosophers as Immanuel Kant and G.W.F. Hegel, who were characterised by Green, among others, as the salvation of British philosophy after the alleged demise of empiricism. The movement was certainly a reaction against the thinking of John Locke, David Hume, John Stuart Mill, Henry Sidgwick, and other empiricists and utilitarians. Some of those involved would have denied any specific influence, particularly in respect of Hegel. Nevertheless, James Hutchison Stirling's book The Secret of Hegel is believed to have won significant converts in Britain.

British idealism was influenced by Hegel at least in broad outline, and undeniably adopted some of Hegel's terminology and doctrines. Examples include not only the aforementioned Absolute, but also a doctrine of internal relations, a coherence theory of truth, and a concept of a concrete universal. Some commentators have also pointed to a sort of dialectical structure in e.g. some of the writings of Bradley. But none of the British idealists adopted Hegel's philosophy wholesale, and his most significant writings on logic seem to have found no purchase whatsoever in their thought (nor in British thought generally).

On its political side, the British idealists were largely concerned to refute what they regarded as a brittle and "atomistic" form of individualism, as espoused by e.g. Herbert Spencer. In their view, humans are fundamentally social beings in a manner and to a degree not adequately recognized by Spencer and his followers. The British Idealists did not, however, reify the State in the manner that Hegel apparently did; Green in particular spoke of the individual as the sole locus of value and contended that the State's existence was justified only insofar as it contributed to the realization of value in the lives of individual persons.

The hold of British idealism in the UK weakened when Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore, who were educated in the British idealist tradition, turned against it. Moore in particular delivered what quickly came to be accepted as conclusive arguments against Idealism. At that point British philosophy in general revolted once more against metaphysics in general. The later work of R.G. Collingwood was a relatively isolated exception. Among present-day UK philosophers the best-known exponent of absolute idealism is probably Timothy L.S. Sprigge.

British idealism's influence in the United States was somewhat limited. The early thought of Josiah Royce had something of a neo-Hegelian cast, as did that of a handful of his less famous contemporaries. The American rationalist Brand Blanshard was so strongly influenced by Bradley, Bosanquet, and Green (and other British philosophers) that he could almost be classified as a British philosopher himself. Even this limited influence, though, did not last out the twentieth century.

References

  • William Ritchie Sorley, A History of British Philosophy to 1900, is an idiosyncratic account of the British tradition centred in British Idealism, first published 1920 as A History of English Philosophy

Neo-Hegelianism

Neo-Hegelianism is a school (or schools) of thought associated and inspired by the works of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, a German idealist philosopher active around the year 1800. During the late 19th and early 20th century, many European and American philosophers revived interest in Hegel's works, especially those pertaining to the importance of spirit, and the belief that ideas and moral ideals are fundamental.

Hegelianism after Hegel

Although Hegel died in 1831, his philosophy lived on. In politics, there was a developing schism, even before his death, between right Hegelians and left Hegelians. Marxism developed out of the latter group.

In philosophy of religion, Hegel's influence soon became very powerful in the English-speaking world. The British school, called British idealism and partly Hegelian in inspiration, included Thomas Hill Green, William Wallace, F.H. Bradley and Edward Caird. It was primarily directed towards political philosophy.

America saw the development of a school of Hegelian thought in St. Louis, Missouri even when that city was barely past its own frontier stage.

German twentieth-century neo-Hegelians

In Germany there was a neo-Hegelianism (neohegelianismus) of the early twentieth century, partly developing out of the Neo-Kantians. Richard Kroner wrote one of its leading works, a history of German idealism from a Hegelian point of view.

Other notable neo-Hegelians

  • Francis Herbert Bradley (1846 - 1924), a British absolute idealist who adapted Hegel's Metaphysics.
  • Josiah Royce (1855 - 1916), an American defender of absolute idealism.
  • Benedetto Croce (1866 - 1952), an Italian philosopher who defended Hegel's account on how we understand history. Croce wrote primarily on topics of Aesthetics, such as artistic inspiration/intuition and personal expression.
  • Giovanni Gentile (1875-1944), important philosopher within the fascist movement. Ghost-wrote "The Doctrine of Fascism"

Criticisms

Exponents of analytic philosophy, which has been the dominant form of Anglo-American philosophy for most of the last century, have criticised Hegel's work as hopelessly obscure. Existentialists also criticise Hegel for ultimately choosing an essentialistic whole over the particularity of existence. Epistemologically, one of the main problems plaguing Hegel's system is how these thought determinations have bearing on reality as such. A perennial problem of his metaphysics seems to be the question of how spirit externalises itself and how the concepts it generates can say anything true about nature. At the same time, they will have to, because otherwise Hegel's system concepts would say nothing about something that is not itself a concept and the system would come down to being only an intricate game involving vacuous concepts.

Schopenhauer

Schopenhauer noted that Hegel created his absolute idealism after Kant had discredited all proofs of God's existence. The Absolute is a non-personal substitute for the concept of God. It is the one subject that perceives the universe as one object. Individuals share in parts of this perception. Since the universe exists as an idea in the mind of the Absolute, it copies Spinoza's panentheism in which everything is in God or Nature.

Moore and Russell

Famously, G.E. Moore’s rebellion against absolutism found expression in his defense of common sense against the radically counter-intuitive conclusions of absolutism (e.g. time is unreal, change is unreal, separateness is unreal, imperfection is unreal, etc.). G.E. Moore also pioneered the use of logical analysis against the absolutists, which Bertrand Russell promulgated and began the entire tradition of analytic philosophy with its use against the philosophies of his direct predecessors. In recounting his own mental development Russell reports, "For some years after throwing over [absolutism] I had an optimistic riot of opposite beliefs. I thought that whatever Hegel had denied must be true." (Russell in Barrett and Adkins 1962, p.477) Also:

G.E. Moore took the lead in the rebellion, and I followed, with a sense of emancipation. [Absolutism] argued that everything common sense believes in is mere appearance. We reverted to the opposite extreme, and thought that everything is real that common sense, uninfluenced by philosophy or theology, supposes real.

Bertrand Russell; as quoted in Klemke 2000, p.28

Pragmatism

Particularly the works of William James and F.C.S. Schiller, both founding members of pragmatism, made lifelong assaults on Absolute Idealism. James was particularly concerned with the monism that Absolute Idealism engenders, and the consequences this has for the problem of evil, free will, and moral action. Schiller rather attacked Absolute Idealism for being too disconnected with our practical lives, and that its proponents failed to realize thought are merely tools for action rather than for making discoveries about an abstract world that fails to have any impact on us.

Relation to religion

Some form of idealism related to absolute idealism has been a consistent favorite standpoint for earlier religious thinkers and philosophers. It is present in the thinking of many important Christian theologians such as Meister Eckhart. It is also the basis of Advaita Hinduism and several forms of Buddhism, including Zen, Madhyamika, Yogacara, and some interpretations of Pure Land. Classifying these directions under the common denominator 'absolute idealism', though, would be incorrect, because it would blur distinctions which are necessary for comprehending these traditions in their own right.

Relation to science

Absolute idealism or Hegelianism has influenced the Humanities to a great extent. In German they are called "Geisteswissenschaften" and in Dutch "Geesteswetenschappen," a direct influence of the Hegelian notion of spirit (Geist). In sociology for instance the position of important sociologist Ralph Dahrendorf is inspired by Hegel.

Lately American historian Francis Fukuyama was inspired by an alleged thesis of Hegel, namely the End of History, to write an immensely popular book. That Hegel proclaimed the end of history though is a myth popularised by the French Hegel interpreter Aleksandr Kojeve.

In many philosophic circles it is accepted that the philosophy of nature Hegel proposes is outdated, though it was state of the art when he proposed it. A full one third of Hegel's library consisted of hand books on natural science. Currently contributors like Houlgate argue that Hegel's philosophy of nature warrants closer attention and has been unjustifiably relegated to the dust bin of philosophy.

Influence

Absolute idealism has greatly altered the philosophical landscape. Paradoxically, (though, from a Hegelian point of view, maybe not paradoxically at all) this influence is mostly felt in the strong opposition it engendered. Both logical positivism and analytic philosophy grew out of a rebellion against Hegelianism prevalent in England during the 19th century. Continental phenomenology, existentialism and post-modernism also seek to 'free themselves from Hegel's thought'. Martin Heidegger, one of the leading figures of Continental philosophy in the 20th century, sought to distance himself from Hegel's work. One of Heidegger's philosophical themes was "overcoming metaphysics."

See also

Sources

  • Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way (Garfield)
  • Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy (Blackburn)
  • A History of Christian Thought (Tillich)
  • From Socrates to Sartre (Lavine)
  • Hegel: Een inleiding (Ed. Ad Verbrugge et al) (in Dutch)
  • Hegels Idealism, The Satisfactions of Self Consciousness (Pippin)
  • Endings, Questions of Memory in Hegel and Heidegger (Ed. Mc Cumber, Comay)

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.