Difference between revisions of "Idea" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
 
(31 intermediate revisions by 7 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{claimed}}
+
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{Copyedited}}
{{otheruses}}
 
  
An '''idea''' ([[Greek language|Greek]]: {{polytonic|ἰδέα}}) is an [[image]], also concept or abstraction formed and existing in the [[mind]]. Human capability to contemplate ideas is associated with the ability of [[reason]]ing, [[human self-reflection|self-reflection]], and the ability to acquire and apply [[intellect]]. Further, ideas give rise to actual [[concepts]], or mind generalisations, which are the basis for any kind of [[knowledge]] whether [[science]] or [[philosophy]].  
+
An '''idea''' ([[Greek language|Greek]]: {{polytonic|ἰδέα}}) as a philosophical term generally refers to an [[image]] in the mind. [[Concept]]s basically refer to generalized ideas, and [[category|categories]] are the most fundamental concepts.
  
In a popular sense, an idea arises in a reflex, spontanious manner, even without thinking or serious [[reflection]], for example, when we talk about the ''idea'' of a person or a place.
+
Whether ideas exist in the mind alone or as an extra-mental objective existence, whether ideas are generated or exist innately in the mind, whether some types of ideas (such as [[God]], [[soul]], and [[world]]: See [[Kant]]) should be considered special or basically the same, and other questions concerning ideas have been central issues in the history of philosophy. Questions regarding the nature, essence, origin, and types of ideas have been integrated and contextualized into each philosophical thought, both in [[ontology]] and [[epistemology]], and the meaning of idea has thus been configured accordingly.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
[[Plato]] asserted, for example, that ideas or forms ("eidos") are not simply images that exist in the mind, but they are permanent extra-mental forms with which [[Demiurge]], the divine crafter, created the [[cosmos]]. Those ideas or forms are, according to Plato, also inscribed in the [[soul]] prior to experience. Medieval [[scholasticism|scholastics]] understood those ideas as the forms within God's mind by which the Creator created the universe. [[Modern philosophy|Modern philosophers]] since [[Descartes]], however, interpreted ideas as mental images that exist within the mind of a cognitive subject.<ref>Idea of God has an extra-mental existence for Descartes. His perspective to the idea of God is closely tied to his proof of the [[existence of God]].</ref> Ideas were often understood as representations of objects outside of mind. This concept of idea as a mental image is still held today.
  
==History of the term "Idea"==
+
==Etymology==
The word "Idea" originated from [[Greek]] and was carried into [[Latin]] without change. <ref> [[Old Catholic Encyclopedia]] (pg 630 - 634)</ref>. "Idea" meant at first a ''form, shape, or appearance'' but later transitioned with the [[connotation]] of [[nature]] and kind. However in [[classical Greek]] it never lost the meaning of "visual aspect".<ref>''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Vol 4: 118 ''Plato writes of a person "beautiful in idea" meaning "beautiful in visual aspect" or good-looking (Protagoras 315e).'' </ref>
+
The word "Idea" originates from the [[Greek]], and it is the feminine form of, the word {{polytonic|εἶδος}} (Greek ''eidos'': something seen; form, shape; related to ''idein'' "to see," ''eidenai'' "to know" <ref>[http://etymonline.com/index.php?term=-oid Eidos explained in -oed suffix], ''Online Etymology Dictionary''. Retrieved September 19, 2015.</ref>). "Idea" meant at first a ''form, shape, or appearance'' and implied the "visual aspect" of things in [[classical Greek]].<ref>''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' Vol 4: 118 ''Plato writes of a person "beautiful in idea" meaning "beautiful in visual aspect" or good-looking (Protagoras 315e).'' </ref> Accordingly, ideas and forms are used interchangeably for Greek authors.
  
Idea is the feminine form of {{polytonic|εἶδος}} (Greek ''eidos'': something seen; form, shape; related to ''idein'' "to see," ''eidenai'' "to know" <ref>[http://etymonline.com/index.php?term=-oid Eidos explained in -oed suffix, etymology dictionary online]</ref>); [[Stoics]]' adoption of ''idea'' secured its ultimate triumph over ''eidos'' and Plato won its prominent and retained for centuries position in the [[history of philosophy]].  
+
With Plato, idea and/or form became essential concepts in philosophy. The [[Ontology|ontological]] status of idea or form, [[epistemology|epistemological]] roles of ideas or forms, and their [[Ethics|ethical]] implications became central issues in philosophy. In this article, Plato's concept and the modern understanding of ideas are introduced to illustrate two different approaches to ideas.
  
''Idea'', within Plato's philosophy, as contrary to modern acceptance, meant something outside of the mind, i.e. primarily and emphatically objective. It was the  universal [[archetypal]] essence in which all individuals coming under a universal concept participate. According to Plato, by sensuous perception we obtain an imperfect knowledge of individual objects and by notions we reach a higher knowledge of the idea of these objects. In Plato's view, the universal notions (concepts) constitute science (general knowledge) as it is in our mind, there correspond ''ideas'', standing outside of our mind. ''Ideas'' are seen as truly universal. Each universal idea has its own separate, independent existence, which determines the nature of an object related to it. ''Ideas'' dwell in a sort of celestial universe. In contrast with the individual objects of sense experience, which undergo constant change and flux, the ''ideas''are perfect, eternal, and immutable.  
+
==Plato's Theory of Forms or Ideas ("eidos")==
 +
Plato concept of ideas or forms are often capitalized as "Ideas" or "Forms" to distinguish his distinct notion from the modern conception of ideas as mental images. In this section, the term Form is used. But Form and Idea both refer to the same Greek term "eidos." [[Plato]]'s Theory of Forms<ref>The name of this syndrome of Plato's thought is not modern and has not been extracted from certain dialogues by modern scholars. The term was used at least as early as [[Diogenes Laertius]], who called it (Plato's) "Theory of Forms:" {{Polytonic|Πλάτων ἐν τῇ περὶ τῶν ἰδεῶν ὑπολήψει}}…., "Plato" ''Lives of Eminent Philosophers'' Book III, Paragraph 15</ref> asserts that Forms or Ideas, and not the material world of change [[Plato's allegory of the cave|known to us through sensation]], possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality.<ref>Stephen Watt. "Introduction: The Theory of Forms (Books 5-7)" in ''Plato: Republic'' (London: Wordsworth Editions, 1997, ISBN 1853264830), xiv-xvi. </ref> Plato spoke of Forms<ref>''The Great Ideas: A Synopticon of Great Books of the Western World.'' Chapter 28: Form . ''Great Books of the Western World.'' II (I of the Synopticon), 526-542. ''Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc'' 1952, 528 states that Form or Idea get capitalized according to this convention when they refer "to that which is separate from the characteristics of material things and from the ideas in our mind."</ref> in formulating [[Platonic realism|his solution]] to the [[problem of universals]].  
  
Plato felt that there must be some sort of community between the individual object and the corresponding ''idea''. This community consists in "participation." The concrete individual participates, or shares, within the universal idea, and this participation constitutes an individual of a certain kind or nature. The participation seems to consist in [[imitation]]. The ''idea'', that is models and prototypes, while sensible objects are copies, very imperfect, of these models.  ''Ideas'' are reflected in a feeble and obscure way in them. The ''idea'' is the [[archetype]] (original model of a given thing) and individual objects are merely images. Such ratiocinations  posses the questions:
+
===Terminology: The Forms and the forms===
::* What precisely is the celestial universe in which ''ideas'' have eternally existed? (Aristotle and Plato had contrary viewpoints as to a doctrine of independent ''ideas''.)
+
The English word "form" may be used to translate two distinct concepts with which Plato was concerned&mdash;the outward "form" or appearance of something (Greek ''eidos'' and ''idea'' in their conventional, nontechnical senses, or other terms such as ''morphē''), and "Form" in a new, technical sense, apparently invented by Plato (esp. ''eidos,'' ''idea''). These are often distinguished by the use of uncapitalized "form" and capitalized "Form," respectively. In the following summary passage, the two concepts are related to each other:<ref name=summ>[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]] Paragraph 50 a-c, Jowett translation.</ref><blockquote> Suppose a person were to make all kinds of figures ''(schēmata)'' of gold… &mdash;somebody points to one of them and asks what it is (''ti pot'esti''). By far the safest and truest answer is [to say] that it is gold; and not to call the triangle or any other figures which are formed in the gold "these" ''(tauta)'' as though they had existence ''(hōs onta)''… And the same argument applies to the universal nature ''(phusis)'' which receives all bodies ''(sōmata)''&mdash;that must always be called the same; for, while receiving all things, she never departs at all from her own nature, and never… assumes a form ''(morphē)'' like that of any of the things which enter into her; … But the forms which enter into and go out of her are the likenesses ''(mimēmata)'' of real existences ''(tōn ontōn aei)'' modelled after their patterns ''(tupōthenta)'' in a wonderful and inexplicable manner… </blockquote> The forms that we see, according to [[Plato]], are not real, but literally ''mimic'' the real Forms. In the [[Allegory of the cave]] expressed in ''[[The Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'' they are called the shadows of real things. That which the observer understands when he views the mimics are the [[archetype]]s of the many [[type (metaphysics)|types]] and [[property (metaphysics)|properties]] (that is, of [[universal (metaphysics)|universals]]) of things we see all around us. They are not located in the object, which as far as Plato is concerned, is mere smoke and mirrors situated in space (which also is real).
::* What is their relationship to the [[The Form of the Good|Idea of the Good]]? (Here [[Saint Augustine]] allots a unique position in the transcendental region of Plato's ''ideas'' to that relating to a God.)
 
  
===Where ideas come from===
+
===Forms or Ideas ("eidos")===
''Here is given the briefest outline of the doctrine usually taught in the Catholic schools of philosophy. Much criticism of the various theories on the question can be found in [[Catholic]] textbooks on psychology.''
+
The Greek concept of form precedes the attested language and is represented by a number of words mainly having to do with vision: the sight or appearance of a thing. The main words, {{Polytonic|εἶδος}} ''(eidos)'' and {{Polytonic|ἰδέα}} ''(idea)''<ref>This transliteration leads to the unfortunate misnomer "theory of Ideas." The word is not the English "idea," which is a mental concept only, and the famous theory has nothing at all to do with the "ideas" of English speakers.</ref> come from the [[Indo-European]] root *weid-, "see."<ref>[http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?term=idea Idea]. ''Online Etymology Dictionary''. Retrieved September 18, 2015.</ref> Both words are in the works of [[Homer]], the earliest Greek literature.
  
<!--This source continues, on page 633 of the subject "Idea," that—>Given the fact that the [[human mind]] in mature life is in possession of such universal ''ideas'', or [[concepts]], the question arises: '''''How have they been attained?'''''  [[Empiricists]] and [[Materialists]] have endeavoured to explain all our intellectual ideas as refined products of our sensuous faculties. Plato conceives them to be an inheritance through reminiscence from a previous state of existence. Sundry [[Christian]] [[philosophers]] of ultra-spiritualist tendencies have described them as [[innate]], planted in the [[soul]] at its creation by a [[Deity]].
+
These meanings remained the same over the centuries until the beginning of philosophy, when they became equivocal, acquiring additional specialized philosophic meanings. The [[Pre-Socratic philosophy|pre-Socratic philosophers]], starting with [[Thales]], noted that appearances change quite a bit and began to inquire into the essential existence of things, leading some to conclude that things were made of [[Substance theory|substances]], which comprise the actually existing thing being seen. They began to question the relationship between the appearance and the essential existence of things, between the substance and the form; thus, the theory of matter and form (today's [[hylomorphism]]) was born. Starting with at least Plato, and possibly germinal in some of the presocratics, the forms were considered "in" something else, which Plato called nature ''(phusis).'' The latter seemed as a "mother" ([[Matter (philosophy)|matter]] from mater)<ref> [http://dictionary.reference.com/browse/matter "matter"] ''Dictionary.com''. Retrieved September 18, 2015.</ref> of substances.
  
Man has a double set of [[cognitive]] faculties - sensuous and [[intellectual]]. ''Aisthesis'', the "sense," as a faculty, apprehends changing phenomena, and ''nous'', "thought," "reason," "intellect," is presenting to humans the permanent, abiding being. All [[knowledge]] starts from sensuous experience with no [[innate ideas]] <!--according to!?!-->: external objects stimulate the senses and effect a modification of the sensuous faculties which results in a sensuous percipient act, a sensation or perception by which the mind becomes cognizant of the concrete individual object, e.g., some sensible quality of the thing acting on the sense. Because [[sense]] and [[intellect]] are powers of the same [[soul]], the latter is now wakened, as it were, into activity, and lays hold of its own proper object in the sensuous presentation. The object is the essence, or nature of the thing, omitting its individualizing conditions. The act by which the intellect thus apprehends the abstract essence, when viewed as a modification of the intellect, was called by the Schoolmen species intelligibilis; when viewed as the realization or utterance of the thought of the object to itself by the intellect, they termed it the ''verbum mentale.'' In this first stage it prescinds alike from universality and individuality. But the intellect does not stop there. It recognizes its object as capable of indefinite multiplication. In other words it generalizes the abstract essence and thereby constitutes it a reflex or formally universal concept, or idea. By comparison, reflection, and generalization, the elaboration of the ''idea'' is continued until we attain to the distinct and precise concepts, or ''ideas'', which accurate science demands.
+
For Plato, as well as in general speech, there is a form for every object or quality in reality: forms of dogs, human beings, mountains, colors, courage, love, and goodness. While the notion of form served to identify objects, Plato went further and inquired into the Form itself. He supposed that the object is essentially or "really" the Form and that phenomena are mere shadows that mimic the Form; that is, momentary portrayals of the Form under different circumstances. The problem of the universals - how can one thing in general be many things in particular - was solved by presuming that Form was a distinct singular thing but caused plural representations of itself in particular objects.<ref>For example, [[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]] 129: "Nor, again, if a person were to show that all is one by partaking of one, and at the same time many by partaking of many, would that be very astonishing. But if he were to show me that the absolute one was many, or the absolute many one, I should be truly amazed."</ref> Matter was considered particular in itself.
  
It is important to note that in the "Scholastic theory" the immediate object of the intellectual act of perception is not the idea or concept. It is the external reality, the nature or essence of the thing apprehended. The idea, when considered as part of the process of direct perception, is itself the subjective act of cognition, not the thing cognized. It is a vital, immanent operation by which the mind is modified and determined directly to know the object perceived. The psychologist may subsequently reflect upon this intellectual idea and make it the subject of his consideration, or the ordinary man may recall it by memory for purposes of comparison, but in the original act of apprehension it is the means by which the mind knows, not the object which it knows—''est id quo res cognoscitur non id quod cognoscitur''. This constitutes a fundamental point of difference between the Scholastic doctrine of perception and that held by [[Locke]], [[Berkeley]], [[Hume]], and a very large proportion of modern philosophers. For Locke and Berkeley the object immediately perceived is the idea. The existence of material objects, if we believe in them, can, in their view, only be justified as an inference from effect to cause. Berkeley and idealists generally deny the validity of that inference; and if the theory of immediate perception be altogether abandoned, it seems difficult to warrant the claim of the human mind to a genuine knowledge of external reality. In the Scholastic view, knowledge is essentially of reality, and this reality is not dependent on the (finite) mind which knows it. The knower is something apart from his actualized knowing, and the known object is something apart from its being actually known. The thing must be before it can be known; the act of knowledge does not set up but presupposes the object. It is of the object that we are directly conscious, not of the idea. In popular language we sometimes call the object "an idea," but in such cases it is in a totally different sense, and we recognize the term as signifying a purely mental creation.
+
These Forms are the essences of various objects: they are that without which a thing would not be the kind of thing it is. For example, there are countless tables in the world but the Form of table-ness is at the core; it is the essence of all tables.<ref>''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]'' 389: "For neither does every smith, although he may be making the same instrument for the same purpose, make them all of the same iron. The form must be the same, but the material may vary …." </ref> Plato held that the world of Forms is separate from our own world (the world of substances) and also is the true basis of reality. Removed from matter, Forms are the most pure of all things. Furthermore, Plato believed that true knowledge/intelligence is the ability to grasp the world of Forms with one's mind.<ref>For example, ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]'' 185: " the mind, by a power of her own, contemplates the universals in all things."</ref>
  
==Philosophy==
+
A Form is ''aspatial'' (outside the world) and ''atemporal'' (outside time). <ref>The creation of the universe is the creation of time: "For there were no days and nights and months and years … but when he (God) constructed the heaven he created them also." - ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'' paragraph 37. For the creation God used "the pattern of the unchangeable," which is "that which is eternal." - paragraph 29. Therefore "eternal" - ''to aïdion'', "the everlasting" - as applied to Form means atemporal.</ref> Forms are aspatial in that they have no spatial dimensions, and thus no orientation in space, nor do they even (like the point) have a location.<ref>Space answers to matter, the place-holder of form: "… and there is a third nature (besides Form and form), which is space (chōros), and is eternal (aei "always," certainly not atemporal), and admits not of destruction and provides a home for all created things … we say of all existence that it must of necessity be in some place and occupy space …." - ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'' paragraph 52. Some readers will have long since remembered that in Aristotle time and space are accidental forms. Plato does not make this distinction and concerns himself mainly with essential form. In Plato, if time and space were admitted to be form, time would be atemporal and space aspatial.</ref> They are non-physical, but they are not in the mind, and are extra-mental.<ref>These terms produced with the English prefix a- are not ancient. For the usage refer to ''Online Etymology Dictionary'', [http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?term=a- a- (2)]. Retrieved September 18, 2015. They are however customary terms of modern metaphysics; for example, see Martha C. Beck, ''Plato's Self-Corrective Development of the Concepts of Soul, Form and Immortality in Three Arguments of the Phaedo'' (Edwin Mellon Press, 1999, ISBN 0773479503), 148; and see Katherine Hawley, "How Things Persist" (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001, ISBN 019924913X), Chapter 1.</ref>
In [[philosophy]], there is scarcely any term which has been used with so many different shades of meaning. The view that ideas exist in a realm [[separation|separate]] or [[distinction|distinct]] from [[real life]] is referred to as [[innate idea|innate ideas]]. Another view holds that we only discover ideas in the same way that we discover the real world, from personal experiences. The view that humans acquire all or almost all their behavioral traits from [[nurture]] (life experiences) is known as [[tabula rasa]] ("blank slate"). Most of the confusions in the way of ideas arise at least in part from the use of the term "idea" to cover both the representation percept and the object of conceptual thought. This can be illustrated in terms of the doctrines of innate ideas, "[[Abstract object|concrete ideas]] verses [[Abstraction|abstract ideas]]," as well as "simple ideas verses complex ideas." <ref>^ ''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Vol 4: 120 - 121</ref>
 
  
===Plato and Platonism===<!-- This section is linked from [[Noumenon]] >
+
A Form is an objective "blueprint" of perfection.<ref>For example, ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'' 28: "The work of the creator, whenever he looks to the unchangeable and fashions the form and nature of his work after an unchangeable pattern, must necessarily be made fair and perfect …."</ref> The Forms are perfect themselves because they are unchanging. For example, say we have a triangle drawn on a blackboard. A triangle is a polygon with 3 sides. The triangle as it is on the blackboard is far from perfect. However, it is only the intelligibility of the Form "triangle" that allows us to know the drawing on the chalkboard is a triangle, and the Form "triangle" is perfect and unchanging. It is exactly the same whenever anyone chooses to consider it; however, the time is that of the observer and not of the triangle.
The Platonic Forms are sometimes called "Ideas" (Greek {{polytonic|ἰδέαι}} alongside {{polytonic|εἴδη}}). See [[Theory of Forms]].
 
  
===Francesco Petrarch===
+
===The pure land===
[[Petrarch]], founder of [[Renaissance humanism]], was the originator of a new interest in Plato's ideas and [[Platonism]].<sup>¹b</sup> The references to Plato which Petrarch discovered personally in letters of [[Cicero]] led him to proclaim Plato's superiority to Aristotle.[http://etext.virginia.edu/cgi-local/DHI/ot2www-dhi?specfile=/texts/english/dhi/dhi.o2w&act=text&offset=15915470&query=Petrarch&tag=IDEA+OF+RENAISSANCE] Petrarch even declared to four Venetian critics that he possessed a lost manuscript of sixteen [[dialogues]] by Plato of these ancient ideas.[http://etext.virginia.edu/cgi-local/DHI/dhi.cgi?id=dv3-64] It was seen that the Plato ideas throughout the Renaissance were a newly discovered pre-Christian sage whose exciting doctrines, wrapped in [[esoteric]] [[mythology]], challenged the cut and dry teachings of Aristotle.[http://etext.virginia.edu/cgi-local/DHI/ot2www-dhi?specfile=/texts/english/dhi/dhi.o2w&act=text&offset=8744128&query=Petrarch&tag=HUMANISM+IN+ITALY] Platonism played a major role throughout the Renaissance from the time of its introduction by Petrarch as a countervailing force against the traditional Aristotelian teachings. Petrarch's [[Canzoniere]] was the most influential lyric poetry of all time with Augustinian Platonism. Platonism and Petrarchism walked hand in hand throughout the Renaissance.  
+
The Forms exist in a rarefied sector of the universe. For everything on Earth there is a formal counterpart:<ref>''[[Phaedo]],'' paragraph 109.</ref><blockquote>But the true earth is pure ''(katharan)'' and situated in the pure heaven ''(en katharōi ouranōi)'' … and it is the heaven which is commonly spoken by us as the ether ''(aithera)'' … for if any man could arrive at the extreme limit … he would acknowledge that this other world was the place of the true heaven ''(ho alethōs ouranos)'' and the true light ''(to alethinon phōs)'' and the true earth ''(hē hōs alēthōs gē).''</blockquote>
  
Ideas, which are transcendent [[universals]], alone constitute reality as against the shadowy existence of particular material
+
In comparison to it our Earth is "spoilt and corroded as in the sea all things are corroded by the brine."<ref name=p110>''Phaedo,'' Paragraph 110.</ref> There the colors are "brighter far and clearer than ours; there is a purple of wonderful lustre, also the radiance of gold and the white which is in the earth is whiter than any chalk or snow."<ref name=p110/> Moreover the plants are better: "and in this far region everything that grows - trees and flowers and fruits - are in a like degree fairer than any here."<ref name=p110/> Gems lie about like ordinary stones: "and there are hills, having stones … more transparent, and fairer in color than our highly-valued emeralds and sardonyxes …."<ref name=p110/> And for the humans, "… they have no disease, and live much longer than we do, and have sight, and hearing and smell … in far greater perfection. They converse with the gods and see the sun, moon and stars as they truly are …."<ref name=p110/> Indeed, for Plato, "[[god]]" is identical to [[the Form of the Good]].
objects.[http://etext.virginia.edu/cgi-local/DHI/ot2www-dhi?specfile=/texts/english/dhi/dhi.o2w&act=text&offset=14090262&query=universal&tag=PRAGMATISM] Chief among these ''ideas'' is the [[Form of the Good|Idea of the Good]]. This was seen as supreme both as the goal of knowledge and as the guide to morality.[http://etext.virginia.edu/cgi-local/DHI/ot2www-dhi?specfile=/texts/english/dhi/dhi.o2w&act=text&offset=9998107&query=idea+of+the+good&tag=ANCIENT+ROMAN+IDEAS+OF+LAW] Petrarch followed Plato's idea that the only real knowledge was the knowledge of ideas. It was pictured mythically as a sort of reminiscence of the transmigrated soul's earlier existence. The Christianizing tendency of Renaissance Platonists with its ideas of the [[Platonic idealism]] is seen in Petrarch when he says, "Of Plato, Augustine does not in the least doubt that he would have become a Christian if he had come to life again in Augustine's time or had foreseen the future while he lived. Augustine relates also that in his time most of the [[Platonists]] had become Christians and he himself can be supposed to belong to their number." Petrarch wrote a personal book called [[Secretum (book)|Secretum]] which was about the Idea of the Good as related to his moral ideals in imaginary discussions with Augustine.<sup>²a</sup>
 
  
===René Descartes===
+
=== Evidence of Forms ===
[[Descartes]] often wrote of the meaning of ''idea'' as an image or representation, often but not necessarily "in the mind," which was well known in the [[vernacular]]. In spite of the fact that Descartes is usually credited with the invention of the non-Platonic use of the term, we find him at first following this vernacular use.<sup>b</sup> In his [[Meditations on First Philosophy]] he says, "Some of my thoughts are like images of things, and it is to these alone that the name 'idea' properly belongs." He sometimes maintained that ideas were [[Innate idea|innate]] <ref>Ibid. Vol 4: 196 - 198</ref> and uses of the term ''idea'' diverge from the original primary scholastic use. He provides multiple non-equivalent definitions of the term, uses it to refer to as many as six distinct kinds of entities, and divides ''ideas'' inconsistently into various genetic categories. [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ideas] For him knowledge took the form of ideas and philosophical investigation is the deep consideration of these ideas. Many times however his thoughts of knowledge and ideas were like those of [[Plotinus]] and [[Neoplatonism]]. In Neoplatonism the Intelligence ''([[Nous]])'' is the true first principle—the determinate, referential 'foundation' ''(arkhe)''—of all existents; for it is not a self-sufficient entity like the One, but rather possesses the ability or capacity to contemplate both the One, as its prior, as well as its own thoughts, which Plotinus identifies with the Platonic Ideas or Forms ''(eide)''[http://www.iep.utm.edu/p/plotinus.htm]. A non-philosophical definition of ''Nous'' is '''good sense''' (a.k.a. "common sense"). Descartes is quoted as saying, "Of all things, '''good sense''' is the most fairly distributed: everyone thinks he is so well supplied with it that even those who are the hardest to satisfy in every other respect never desire more of it than they already have."[http://en.wikiquote.org/wiki/Ren%C3%A9_Descartes]
+
Plato's main evidence for the existence of Forms is intuitive only and is as follows.
  
===John Locke===  
+
====The argument from human perception====
In striking contrast to Plato’s use of idea <ref>Ibid. Vol 4: 487 - 503</ref> is that of [[John Locke]] in his masterpiece [http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/An_Essay_Concerning_Human_Understanding Essay Concerning Human Understanding] in the Introduction where he defines '''idea''' as "It being that term which, I think, serves best to stand for whatsoever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks, I have used it to express whatever is meant by phantasm, notion, species, or whatever it is which the mind can be employed about in thinking ; and I could not avoid frequently using it." He said he regarded the book necessary to examine our own abilities and see what objects our understandings were, or were not, fitted to deal with. In his philosophy other outstanding figures followed in his footsteps - Hume and Kant in the 18th century, [[Arthur Schopenhauer]] in the 19th century, and [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], and [[Karl Popper]] in the 20th century. Locke always believed in '''good sense''' - not pushing things to extremes and on taking fully into account the plain facts of the matter. He considered his common sense ideas "good-tempered, moderate, and down-to-earth."  <sup>c</sup>
+
To understand Plato's argument from human [[perception]], it is helpful to use the example of the color blue. We call both the sky and blue jeans by the same color: blue. However, clearly a pair of jeans and the sky are not the same color; moreover, the wavelengths of light reflected by the sky at every location and all the millions of blue jeans in every state of fading constantly change, and yet we somehow have an idea of the basic form Blueness as it applies to them. Says Plato:<ref>''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]]'' paragraph 440.</ref><ref>[[Aristotle]] in ''Metaphysics'' A.987a.29-b.14 and M1078b9-32 says that Plato devised the Forms to answer a weakness in the doctrine of [[Heraclitus]], who held that nothing exists, but everything is in a state of flow. If nothing exists it can't be known, and so Plato took the universals of Socrates and made them into distinct beings that can be known. Socrates did not think they were separate beings.</ref><blockquote>But if the very nature of knowledge changes, at the time when the change occurs there will be no knowledge, and, according to this view, there will be no one to know and nothing to be known: but if that which knows and that which is known exist ever, and the beautiful and the good and every other thing also exist, then I do not think that they can resemble a process of flux, as we were just now supposing.</blockquote>
  
===David Hume===
+
====The argument from perfection====
[[David Hume|Hume]] differs from Locke by limiting "idea" to the more or less vague mental reconstructions of perceptions, the perceptual [[Process (general)|process]] being described as an "impression."<ref>Ibid. Vol 4: 74 - 90</ref> Hume shared with Locke the basic empiricist premise that it is only from life experiences (whether our own or other's) that out knowledge of the existence of anything outside of ourselves can be ultimately derived. We shall carry on doing what we are prompted to do by our emotional drives of all kinds. In choosing the means to those ends we shall follow our accustomed association of ideas.<sup>d</sup> Hume is quoted as saying: "Reason is the slave of the passions."
+
No one has ever seen a [[Perfection|perfect]] circle, nor a perfectly straight line, yet everyone knows what a circle and a straight line are. Plato utilizes the tool-maker's blueprint as evidence that Forms are real:<ref>''[[Cratylus (dialogue)|Cratylus]] paragraph 389.</ref><blockquote>… when a man has discovered the instrument which is naturally adapted to each work, he must expess this natural form, and not others which he fancies, in the material ….</blockquote>
[[Image:Printing4 Walk of Ideas Berlin.JPG|left|thumb|135 px|[[Walk of Ideas]]]]
 
  
=== Immanuel Kant ===
+
Given that perceived circles or lines are not exactly circular or straight, and yet idea of a perfect circle or line directs the manufacturer, then it follows that there must exist the idea or Form of a perfect circle or line.
[[Immanuel Kant]] defines an "idea" as opposed to a "[[concept]]." "Regulator ideas" are ideals that one must tend towards, but by definition may not be completely realized. [[Liberty]], according to Kant, is an idea. The [[Wiktionary:Autonomy|autonomy]] of the rational and [[universal proposition|universal]] [[subject (philosophy)|subject]] is opposed to the [[determinism]] of the [[empirical]] subject.<ref>Ibid. Vol 4: 305 - 324</ref> Kant felt that it is precisely in knowing its limits that philosophy exists. The business of philosophy he thought was not to give rules, but to analyze the private judgements of good common sense.<sup>e</sup>
 
  
===Rudolf Steiner===
+
=== Criticisms of Platonic Forms ===
Whereas Kant declares limits to knowledge ("we can never know the thing in itself"), in his [[epistemological]] work, [[Rudolf Steiner]] sees ''ideas'' as "objects of experience" which the mind apprehends, much as the eye apprehends light. In "Goethean Science" (1883), he declares, "Thinking… is no more and no less an organ of perception than the eye or ear. Just as the eye perceives colors and the ear sounds, so thinking perceives ideas." He holds this to be the premise upon which [[Goethe]] made his natural-scientific observations.
+
====Self-criticism====
 +
Plato was well aware of the limitations of his theory, as he offered his own criticisms of it in his dialogue [[Parmenides (dialogue)|''Parmenides'']], in which Socrates is portrayed as a young philosopher acting as junior counterfoil to aged Parmenides.  
  
===Wilhelm Wundt===
+
The dialogue does present a very real difficulty with the Theory of Forms, which was overcome later by Aristotle (but not without rejecting the independently existing world of Forms). It is debated whether Plato viewed these criticisms as conclusively disproving the Theory of Forms. It is worth noting that Aristotle was a student and then a junior colleague of Plato; it is entirely possible that the presentation of ''Parmenides'' "sets up" for Aristotle; that is, they agreed to disagree.
[[Wundt]] widens the term from Kant's usage to include ''conscious representation of some object or process of the external world''. In so doing, he includes not only ideas of [[memory]] and [[imagination]], but also [[perceptual]] processes, whereas other [[psychologist]]s confine the term to the first two groups. One of Wundt's main concerns was to investigate conscious processes in their own context by [[experiment]] and [[introspection]]. He regarded both of these as ''exact methods'', interrelated in that experimentation created optimal conditions for introspection. Where the experimental method failed, he turned to other ''objectively valuable aids'', specifically to ''those products of cultural communal life which lead one to infer particular mental motives. Outstanding among these are speech, myth, and social custom.'' Wundt designed the basic mental activity [[apperception]] - a unifying function which should be understood as an activity of the will. Many aspects of his empirical physiological psychology are used today. One is his principles of mutually enhanced contrasts and of [[assimilation]] and dissimilation (i.e. in color and form perception and his advocacy of ''objective'' methods of expression and of recording results, especially in language. Another is the principle of heterogony of ends - that multiply motivated acts lead to unintended side effects which in turn become motives for new actions.<ref>Ibid. Vol 8: 349 -351</ref>
 
  
===Charles Sanders Peirce===
+
The difficulty lies in the conceptualization of the "participation" of an object in a form (or Form). The young Socrates conceives of his solution to the problem of the universals in another metaphor, which though wonderfully apt, remains to be elucidated:<ref>''[[Parmenides (dialogue)|Parmenides]]'' 131.</ref>
[[C. S. Peirce]] published the first full statement of [[pragmatism]] in his important works [http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/How_to_Make_Our_Ideas_Clear "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878)] and "The Fixation of Belief" (1877). In "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" he proposed that a ''clear idea'' (in his study he uses [[concept]] and ''idea'' as synonymic) is defined as one, when it is apprehended such as it will be recognized wherever it is met, and no other will be mistaken for it. If it fails of this clearness, it is said to be obscure. He argued that to understand an idea clearly we should ask ourselves what difference its application would make to our evaluation of a proposed solution to the problem at hand. Pragmatism (a term he appropriated for use in this context), he defended, was a method for ascertaining the meaning of terms (as a theory of meaning). The originality of his ideas is in their rejection of what was accepted as a view and understanding of knowledge by scientists for some 250 years, i.e. that, he pointed, knowledge was an impersonal fact. Peirce contended that we acquire knowledge as ''participants'', not as ''spectators''. He felt "the real" is which, sooner or later, information acquired through ideas and knowledge with the application of logical reasoning would finally result in. He also published many papers on logic in relation to ''ideas''.
+
:Nay, but the idea may be like the day which is one and the same in many places at once, and yet continuous with itself; in this way each idea may be one and the same in all at the same time.  
  
===G. F. Stout and J. M. Baldwin===
+
But exactly how is a Form like the day in being everywhere at once? The solution calls for a distinct form, in which the particular instances that are not identical to the form participate; i.e., the form is shared like the day in many places. The concept of "participate," represented in Greek by more than one word, is as obscure in Greek as it is in English. Plato hypothesized that distinctness meant existence as an independent being, thus opening himself up to the famous [[Third Man Argument]] of Parmenides,<ref>The name is at least as old as [[Aristotle]], who says in ''Metaphysics'' A.IX.990b.15: "(The argument) they call the third man." A summary of the argument and the quote from Aristotle can be found in the venerable George Grote. "App I Aristotle's Objections to Plato's Theory" in ''Aristotle, Second Edition with Additions.'' (London: John Murray, 1880), 559-560, note b (downloadable Google Books). Grote points out that more likely than not Aristotle lifted this argument from the ''Parmenides'' of Plato; certainly, his words indicate the argument was already well-known under that name. </ref> which proves that forms cannot independently exist and be participated.<ref>Analysis of the argument has been going on for centuries, and some analyses are complex, technical and perhaps tedious for the general reader. Those who are interested in the more technical analyses can find more of a presentation in Steven D. Hales, [http://www.bloomu.edu/departments/philosophy/pages/content/hales/articlepdf/thirdman.pdf "The Recurring Problem of the Third Man"] ''Auslegung'' 17 (1)(1991): 67-80. Retrieved September 18, 2015. </ref> and <ref>Michael Durham, "Two Men and the Third Man" ''The Dualist: Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy'' (Stanford University) 4 (1997).</ref>
G. F. Stout and [[James Mark Baldwin|J. M. Baldwin]], in the ''Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology'' [http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/Baldwin/Dictionary], define "idea" as "the reproduction with a more or less adequate [[image]], of an object not actually present to the senses." They point out that an idea and a perception are by various authorities contrasted in various ways. "Difference in degree of intensity," "comparative absence of bodily movement on the part of the subject," "comparative dependence on mental activity," are suggested by psychologists as characteristic of an idea as compared with a [[perception]].
 
  
It should be observed that an idea, in the narrower and generally accepted sense of a mental reproduction, is frequently composite. That is, as in the example given above of the idea of chair, a great many objects, differing materially in detail, all call a single idea. When a man, for example, has obtained an idea of chairs in general by comparison with which he can say "This is a chair, that is a stool," he has what is known as an "abstract idea" distinct from the reproduction in his mind of any particular chair (see [[abstraction]]). Furthermore a complex idea may not have any corresponding physical object, though its particular constituent elements may severally be the reproductions of actual perceptions. Thus the idea of a [[centaur]] is a complex mental picture composed of the ideas of [[man]] and [[horse]], that of a [[mermaid]] of a [[woman]] and a [[fish]].
+
If universal and particulars - say man or greatness - all exist and are the same, then the Form is not one but is multiple. If they are only like each other then they contain a form that is the same and others that are different. Thus if the Form and a particular are alike then there must be another, or third, man or greatness by possession of which they are alike. An infinite [[Infinite regress|regression]] must result (consequently the mathematicians often call the argument the Third Man Regression); that is, an endless series of third men. The ultimate participant, greatness, rendering the entire series great, is missing. Moreover, any Form is not unitary but is composed of infinite parts, none of which is the proper Form.
  
== In anthropology and the social sciences ==
+
The young Socrates (some may say the young Plato) did not give up the Theory of Forms over the Third Man but took another tack, that the particulars do not exist as such. Whatever they are, they "mime" the Forms, appearing to be particulars. This is a clear dip into [[Representative realism|representationalism]], that we cannot observe the objects as they are in themselves but only their representations. That view has the weakness that if only the mimes can be observed then the real Forms cannot be known at all and the observer can have no idea of what the representations are supposed to represent or that they are representations.
[[Diffusion (anthropology)|Diffusion]] studies explore the spread of ideas from culture to culture. Some anthropological theories hold that all cultures imitate ideas from one or a few original cultures, the Adam of the Bible or several cultural circles that overlap. Evolutionary diffusion theory holds that cultures are influenced by one another, but that similar ideas can be developed in isolation.
 
  
In mid-20th century, social scientists began to study how and why ideas spread from one person or culture to another. [[Everett Rogers]] pioneered [[diffusion of innovations]] studies, using research to prove factors in adoption and profiles of adopters of ideas. In 1976, [[Richard Dawkins]] suggested applying biological [[evolution|evolutionary]] theories to spread of ideas. He coined the term '[[meme]]' to describe an abstract unit of [[selection]], equivalent to the [[gene]] in [[evolutionary biology]].
+
Plato's later answer would be that men already know the Forms because they were in the world of Forms before birth. The mimes only recall these Forms to memory.<ref>Plato to a large extent identifies what today is called [[insight]] with recollection: "whenever on seeing one thing you conceived another whether like or unlike, there must surely have been an act of recollection?" - [[Phaedo]] paragraph 229. Thus geometric reasoning on the part of persons who know no geometry is not insight but is  recollection. He does recognize insight: "... with a sudden flash there shines forth understanding about every problem ..." (with regard to "the course of scrutiny") - ''[[The Seventh Letter]]'' 344b.</ref>  Unfortunately the hidden world can in no way be verified in this lifetime and its otherworldness can only be a matter of speculation (in those times before the knowledge of [[revelation]] and [[faith]]).<ref>Plato was aware of the problem: "How real existence is to be studied or discovered is, I suspect, beyond you and me." - ''[[Cratylus]]'' paragraph 439.</ref>
  
==Validity of ideas==
+
====Aristotelian criticism====
 +
The topic of Aristotelian criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms is quite extensive and continues to expand, for many reasons. First, Aristotle did not just criticize Plato but Platonism typically without distinguishing individuals. Moreover, rather than quote Plato directly he chose to summarize him often in one-liners that are not comprehensible without considerable exegesis, and sometimes not then. As a historian of prior thought, Aristotle often uses the prior arguments as a foil to present his own ideas. Consequently, in presenting the Aristotelian criticisms it is necessary to distinguish what Aristotle wrote, what he meant, what Plato meant, the validity of Aristotle's understanding of Plato's thoughts, and the relationship between Plato's thought and Aristotle's concepts: a formidable task extending over centuries of scholarship. This article presents a few sample arguments addressed by a few sample scholars. Readers may pursue the topic more fully through the citations and bibliography.
  
In the objective worth of our ''ideas'' there remains the problem of the [[validity]]. As all [[cognition]] is by ''ideas'', it is obvious that the question of the validity of ''our ideas'' in this broad sense is that of the [[truth]] of our [[knowledge]] as a whole. Otherwise to dispute this is to take up the position of [[scepticism]]. This has often been pointed out as a means intellectual suicide. Any chain of reasoning (common sense) by which it is attempted to demonstrate the falsity of our ''ideas'' has to employ the very concept of ''ideas'' itself.  Then in so far as it demands assent to the conclusion, it implies belief in the validity of all the ''ideas'' employed in the premises of the argument.  
+
In the summary passage quoted above<ref name=summ/> Plato distinguishes between real and non-real "existing things," where the latter term is used of substance. The figures, which the artificer places in the gold, are not substance, but gold is. Aristotle, after stating that according to Plato all things studied by the sciences have Form, asserts that Plato considered only substance to have Form giving rise to the contradiction of Forms existing as the objects of the sciences but not existing as non-substance.<ref name=rossXI>Sir David Ross, ''Plato's Theory of Ideas'' (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1951), Chapter XI, initial.</ref>
  
To assent the fundamental mathematical and logical [[axioms]], including that of the principle of [[contradiction]], implies admission of the truth of the ''ideas'' expressed in these principles. With respect to the objective worth of ideas, as involved in [[perception]] generally, the question raised is that of the existence of an independent material world comprising other human beings. The [[idealism]] of [[David Hume]] and [[John Stuart Mill]] would lead logically to [[solipsism]] (the denial of any others besides ourselves). The main foundation of all idealism and scepticism is the assumption (explicit or implicit), that the mind can never know what is outside of itself. This is to say that an ''idea'' as a [[cognition]] can never go outside of itself. This can be further expressed as we can never reach to and mentally apprehend anything outside of anything of what is actually a present state of our own consciousness.
+
Despite Ross's objection that Aristotle is wrong in his assumption, that Plato considers many non-substances to be Forms, such as Sameness, Difference, Rest, Motion, the criticism remains and is major, for it seems that Plato did not know where to draw the line between Form and non-Form. As Cornford points out,<ref>Francis MacDonald Cornford, ''Plato and Parmenides'' (New York: The Liberal Arts Press, 1957), 82-83.</ref> things about which the young Socrates (and Plato) asserted "I have often been puzzled about these things"<ref>''[[Parmenides (dialogue)]]'' paragraph 130c.</ref> referring to Man, Fire and Water, appear as Forms in his later works, but others do not, such as Hair, Mud, Dirt, about which Socrates is made to assert: "it would be too absurd to suppose that they have a Form."
  
* First, this is based on a prior assumption for which no real proof is or can be given
+
Another argument of Aristotle attacked by Ross<ref name=rossXI/> is that Socrates posits a Form, Otherness, to account for the differences between Forms. Apparently Otherness is existing non-existence: the Not-tall, the Not-beautiful, etc., so that every particular object participates in a Form causing it not to be one essence; that is, a Form to exclude the essence but allow all others. According to Ross, however, Plato never made the leap from "A is not B" to "A is Not-B." Otherness only applies to its own particulars and not to the other Forms; for example, there is no Form, Non-Greek, only particulars of Otherness that suppress Greek.
* Second, it is not only not self-evident, but directly contrary to what our mind affirms to be our direct intellectual experience.  
 
  
What is possible for a human mind to apprehend cannot be laid down beforehand. It must be ascertained by careful observation and by study of the process of cognition. This postulates that the mind cannot apprehend or cognize any reality existing outside of itself and is not only a self-evident proposition, it is directly contrary to what such observation and the testimony of mankind affirms to be our actual intellectual experience.  
+
However, this objection does not evade the question. Whether or not Socrates meant that the particulars of Otherness are Not-Greek, Not-tall, Not-beautiful, etc., such a particular still operates only on specific essences. If it were a general exclusiveness every Form would be excluded and nothing be anything in particular. If the exclusion excludes one essence then either Otherness is not unitary or multiple Othernesses exist, each one excluding one essence. It is something and it is not something; it allows and does not allow, which are contradictory properties of the one Form.
  
[[John Stuart Mill]] and most extreme idealists have to admit the validity of memory and expectation. This is to say that in every act of memory or expectation which refers to any experience outside the present instant, our cognition is transcending the present modifications of the mind and judging about reality beyond and distinct from the present states of consciousness. Considering the question as specially concerned with [[universal (metaphysics)|universal concepts]], only the theory of moderate realism adopted by [[Aristotle]] and [[Thomas Aquinas|Saint Thomas]] can claim to guarantee objective value to our ideas. According to the [[nominalist]] and [[conceptualist]] theories there is no true correlate in ''rerum naturâ'' corresponding to the universal term.  
+
Though familiar with [[insight]], Plato had postulated that we know Forms through remembrance. [[Aristotle]] successfully makes [[Epistemology|epistemological]] arguments against this view. In Plato the particulars do not really exist. Countering "... for that which is non-existent cannot be known"<ref>''[[Posterior Analytics]]'' 71b.25.</ref> Aristotle points out that proof rests on prior knowledge of universals and that if we did not know what universals are we would have no idea of what we were trying to prove and could not be trying to prove it. Knowledge of the universal is given from even one particular; in fact, the [[Inductive reasoning|inductive]] method of proof depends on it.<ref>''[[Posterior Analytics]]'' 71a-b.</ref>
  
Mathematics, astronomy, physics, chemistry, and the rest claim that their universal propositions are true and deal with [[reality|realities]]. It is involved in the very notion of science that the physical laws formulated by the mind do mirror the working of agents in the external universe. The general terms of these sciences and ''the ideas'' which they signify have objective correlatives in the common natures and essences of the objects with which these sciences deal.
+
This epistemology sets up for the main attack on Platonism (though not named) in ''[[Metaphysics (Aristotle)|Metaphysics]].''<ref>Aristotle, ''Metaphysics,'' Book III Chapters 3-4, Paragraphs 999a-b, otherwise known as Β 3-4.</ref> In brief, universal and particulars imply each other; one is logically prior or posterior to the other. If they are to be regarded as distinct, then they cannot be universal and particulars; that is, there is no reason to understand the universal from the objects that are supposed to be particulars. It is not the case that if a universal A might be supposed to have particulars a1, a2, etc., A is missing or a1, a2, etc. are missing. A does not exist at all and a1, a2, etc. are unrelated objects.
Otherwise these general statements are unreal and each science is nothing more than a consistently arranged system of barren propositions deduced from empty arbitrary definitions. These [[postulates]] then have no more genuine objective value than any other coherently devised scheme of artificial symbols standing for imaginary beings. However the fruitfulness of science and the constant verifications of its predictions are incompatible with such a [[hypothesis]].[http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/07630a.htm]
+
 
 +
==Ideas as Representations: Modern Representative Theory of Perception ==
 +
The concept of ideas as images in mind in [[modern philosophy]] appeared within the context of the Representative Theory of Perception, a common framework of thought in modern philosophy.
 +
 
 +
The Representative Theory of Perception, also known as Indirect realism, "epistemological dualism," and "The veil of perception," is a [[philosophy|philosophical]] concept. It states that we do not (and can not) perceive the external world directly; instead we know only our ideas or interpretations of objects in the world. Thus, a barrier or a veil of perception prevents first-hand knowledge of anything beyond it. The "veil" exists between the mind and the existing world.
 +
 
 +
The debate then occurs about where our ideas come from, and what this place is like. An indirect realist believes our ideas come from [[sense data]] of a real, material, external world. The doctrine states that in any act of [[perception]], the immediate (direct) object of perception is only a sense-datum that represents an external object.
 +
 
 +
[[Aristotle]] was the first to provide an in-depth description of Indirect realism. In his work, ''[[On the Soul]],'' he describes how the eye must be affected by changes in an intervening medium rather than by objects themselves. He then speculates on how these sense impressions can form our experience of seeing and reasons that an endless regress would occur unless the sense itself were self aware. He concludes by proposing that the mind is the things it thinks. He calls the images in the mind "ideas."
 +
 
 +
The way that indirect realism involves intermediate stages between objects and perceptions immediately raises a question: How well do sense-data represent external objects, properties, and events? Indirect realism creates deep [[epistemology|epistemological]] problems, such as [[solipsism]] and the [[problem of the external world]]. Nonetheless, Indirect realism has been popular in the history of philosophy and has been developed by many philosophers including [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Spinoza]], [[René Descartes]], and [[John Locke]].
 +
 
 +
==John Locke==
 +
In striking contrast to Plato’s use of idea <ref>''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' Vol 4: 487 - 503</ref> is that of [[John Locke]] in his masterpiece [http://en.wikisource.org/wiki/An_Essay_Concerning_Human_Understanding Essay Concerning Human Understanding] in the Introduction where he defines '''idea''' as "It being that term which, I think, serves best to stand for whatsoever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks, I have used it to express whatever is meant by phantasm, notion, species, or whatever it is which the mind can be employed about in thinking ; and I could not avoid frequently using it." He said he regarded the book necessary to examine our own abilities and see what objects our understandings were, or were not, fitted to deal with. In his philosophy other outstanding figures followed in his footsteps - [[Hume]] and [[Kant]] in the eighteenth century, [[Arthur Schopenhauer]] in the nineteenth century, and [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], and [[Karl Popper]] in the twentieth century. Locke always believed in '''good sense''' - not pushing things to extremes and taking fully into account the plain facts of the matter. He considered his common sense ideas "good-tempered, moderate, and down-to-earth."  <sup>c</sup>
 +
 
 +
==David Hume==
 +
[[David Hume|Hume]] differs from Locke by limiting "idea" to the more or less vague mental reconstructions of [[perception]]s, the perceptual [[Process (general)|process]] being described as an "impression."<ref>''The Encyclopedia of Philosophy,'' Vol 4: 74 - 90</ref> Hume shared with Locke the basic empiricist premise that it is only from life experiences (whether our own or other's) that out knowledge of the existence of anything outside of ourselves can be ultimately derived. We shall carry on doing what we are prompted to do by our emotional drives of all kinds. In choosing the means to those ends we shall follow our accustomed association of ideas.<sup>d</sup> Hume is quoted as saying: "Reason is the slave of the passions."
 +
 
 +
==History of ideas==
 +
[[Image:Printing4 Walk of Ideas Berlin.JPG|right|thumb|200px|[[Walk of Ideas]]]]
 +
The '''history of ideas''' is a field of [[research]] in [[history]] that deals with the expression, preservation, and change of human [[idea]]s over time. The history of ideas is a sister-discipline to, or a particular approach within, [[intellectual history]]. Work in the history of ideas may involve interdisciplinary research in the [[history of philosophy]], the [[history of science]], or the [[history of literature]]. In [[Sweden]], the history of ideas has been a distinct university subject since the 1930s, when [[Johan Nordström]], a scholar of literature, was appointed professor of the new discipline at [[Uppsala University]]. Today, several universities across the world provide courses in this field, usually as part of a graduate program.
 +
 
 +
===The Lovejoy approach=== 
 +
The historian [[Arthur O. Lovejoy]] (1873–1962) coined the phrase ''history of ideas'' and initiated its systematic study, in the early decades of the twentieth century. For decades Lovejoy presided over the regular meetings of the ''History of Ideas Club'' at [[Johns Hopkins University]], where he worked as a professor of history from 1910 to 1939.
 +
 
 +
Aside from his students and colleagues engaged in related projects (such as [[René Wellek]] and [[Leo Spitzer]], with whom Lovejoy engaged in extended debates), scholars such as [[Isaiah Berlin]], [[Michel Foucault]], [[John Edward Christopher Hill|Christopher Hill]], [[J. G. A. Pocock]] and others have continued to work in a spirit close to that with which Lovejoy pursued the history of ideas. The first chapter/lecture of Lovejoy's book ''[[The Great Chain of Being]]'' lays out a general overview of what is intended (or at least what he intended) to be the program and scope of the study of the history of ideas.
 +
 
 +
===Unit-ideas===
 +
Lovejoy's history of ideas takes as its basic unit of analysis the '''unit-idea''', or the individual concept. These unit-ideas work as the building-blocks of the history of ideas: though they are relatively unchanged in themselves over the course of time, unit-ideas recombine in new patterns and gain expression in new forms in different historical eras. As Lovejoy saw it, the historian of ideas had the task of identifying such unit-ideas and of describing their historical emergence and recession in new forms and combinations.
 +
 
 +
===Modern work===
 +
[[Quentin Skinner]] has been influential with his critique of Lovejoy's "unit-idea" methodology. Instead, he proposes a sensitivity to the cultural context of the texts being analysed and the ideas they contained.
  
 
==See also==  
 
==See also==  
{{Wikisource}}
 
{{Wikibooks}}
 
{{Wikiquote}}
 
{{Wikiversity}}
 
 
*[[Form#Form in philosophy|Form]]
 
*[[Form#Form in philosophy|Form]]
 
*[[Meme]]
 
*[[Meme]]
Line 98: Line 119:
 
*[[Mental image]]
 
*[[Mental image]]
 
*[[Brainstorming]]
 
*[[Brainstorming]]
*[[Portal: thinking]]
 
*[[List of perception-related topics|Perception related]]
 
 
*[[Object of the mind]]
 
*[[Object of the mind]]
*[[Notion (philosophy)]]
 
 
*[[Thought experiment]]
 
*[[Thought experiment]]
*[[Diffusion of innovations]]
 
*[[Universal (metaphysics)]]
 
 
*[[Introspection]] and [[Extrospection]]
 
*[[Introspection]] and [[Extrospection]]
 +
 
==Notes==
 
==Notes==
 
<references/>
 
<references/>
==Bibliography==
 
  
*A.G. Balz, ''Idea and Essence in the Philosophy of Hobbes and Spinoza'' (New York 1918)
+
==References==
*An Encyclopedia of World Literature
+
 
*Dictionary of the History of Ideas Charles Scribner's Sons, New York , 1973-74. ISBN 684-16425-6
+
*Balz, A. G. A. ''Idea and essence in the philosophies of Hobbes and Spinoza.'' New York: Columbia University Press,  1918.
*E. Garin, ''La Theorie de I'idee suivant I'ecole thomiste (Paris 1932)
+
*Beck, Martha C. ''Plato's Self-Corrective Development of the Concepts of Soul, Form and Immortality in Three Arguments of the Phaedo.'' Edwin Mellon Press, 1999. ISBN 0773479503
*J. W. Yolton, ''John Locke and the Way of Ideas'' (Oxford 1956)
+
*Berlin, I., and H. Hardy. ''Against the current essays in the history of ideas.'' Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001. ISBN 0691090262
*Lawrence Lessig, ''[[The Future of Ideas]]'' (New York 2001)
+
*Bevir, M. ''The logic of the history of ideas.'' Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999. ISBN 0521640342
*M.H. Carre, ''Realists and Nominalists'' (Oxford 1946)
+
*Cornford, Francis MacDonald. Plato and Parmenides. New York: The Liberal Arts Press, 1957.
*Melchert, Norman (2002). The Great Conversation: A Historical Introduction to Philosophy. McGraw Hill. ISBN 0-19-517510-7.
+
*Durham, Michael. "Two Men and the Third Man." ''The Dualist: Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy'' (Stanford University) (1997): 4
*Paul Natorp, ''Platons Ideenlehre (Leipzig 1930)
+
*Fine, Gail. ''On Ideas: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms.'' Oxford University Press, 1992. ISBN 0198235496. Reviewed by Gerson, Lloyd P . Gail Fine, ''On Ideas. Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms''. Bryn Mawr Classical Review 04.05.25 (1993).
*Peter Watson, ''Ideas: a history from fire to Freud'', Weidenfeld & Nicolson (London 2005).
+
*Grote, George, "App I Aristotle's Objections to Plato's Theory." ''Aristotle,'' Second Edition with Additions, London: John Murray, 1880.
*The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, MacMillian Publishing Company, New York, 1973 ISBN 0028949501 ISBN 978-0028949505
+
*Lessig, L. ''The future of ideas the fate of the commons in a connected world.'' New York: Random House, 2001. ISBN 0375505784
*The Reader's Encyclopedia, 2nd Edition 1965, Thomas Y. Crowell Company
+
*Lovejoy, A. O. ''The Great chain of being a study of the history of an idea.'' Cambridge: The William James lectures delivered at Harvard University, 1933; MA, Harvard University Press, 1974. ISBN 0674361539
*The Story of Philosophy, Dorling Kindersley Publishing, 2001, ISBN 0-7894-7994-X
+
*Lovejoy, A. O. ''Essays in the history of ideas.'' Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1978. ISBN 0313205043
*The Story of Thought, DK Publishing, Bryan Magee, London, 1998, ISBN 0-7894-4455-0
+
*Ross, Sir David. ''Plato's Theory of Ideas.'' Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1951.  
*W.D. Ross, ''Plato's Theory of Ideas '' (Oxford 1951)
+
*The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, MacMillian Publishing Company, New York, 1973. ISBN 0028949501  
*William Rose Benet, The Reader's Encyclopedia 1965.
+
*Watson, Peter. ''Ideas: a history from fire to Freud.'' London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 2005.
 +
*Watt, Stephen. "Introduction: The Theory of Forms (Books 5-7)," Plato: ''Republic.'' London: Wordsworth Editions, 1997. ISBN 1853264830
 +
*Wiener, P. P. ''Dictionary of the history of ideas studies of selected pivotal ideas.'' New York: Scribner, 1973. ISBN 0684132931
 +
*Yolton, J. W. ''John Locke and the way of ideas.'' [London]: Oxford University Press, 1956.
 +
 
 +
*{{1911}}
 +
* This article incorporates text from the ''Old Catholic Encyclopedia'' of 1914, a publication now in the public domain.
 +
* This article incorporates text from the ''Schaff-Herzog Encyclopedia of Religious Knowledge'', a publication now in the public domain.
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
* [http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/07630a.htm Catholic Encyclopedia entry "idea"]
+
All links retrieved February 24, 2018.
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-metaphysics Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology]
+
* [http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/07630a.htm Catholic Encyclopedia entry "idea"].
* [http://www.ammas.com/a1/advisors/index.cfm?r=va&qid=89600&cid=3340600&bid=0&topicid=40 Sunil Thacker Procedure for Patenting/Copyrighting an idea]
+
* [http://www.historyguide.org/intellect/humanism.html Francesco Petrarch and his relationship to Renaissance Humanism].
* [http://www.historyguide.org/intellect/humanism.html Francesco Petrarch and his relationship to Renaissance Humanism]
+
* Philip P. Wiener (ed.), [http://xtf.lib.virginia.edu/xtf/view?docId=DicHist/uvaBook/tei/DicHist1.xml ''Dictionary of the History of Ideas: Studies of Selected Pivotal Ideas''].
 +
*Marc Cohen. [http://faculty.washington.edu/smcohen/320/thforms.htm Theory of Forms] Philosophy 320: History of Ancient Philosophy, University of Washington Philosophy Department
 +
*Tim Ruggiero, [http://www.philosophicalsociety.com/Archives/Plato%20And%20The%20Theory%20Of%20Forms.htm#I.%20Theory%20of%20Forms Plato And The Theory of Forms] Philosophical Society.com.
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-metaphysics/ Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
 
 
===General Philosophy Sources===
 
===General Philosophy Sources===
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].  
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].  
*[http://www.epistemelinks.com/  Philosophy Sources on Internet EpistemeLinks]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].  
*[http://www.earlham.edu/~peters/gpi/index.htm Guide to Philosophy on the Internet]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
 
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]. Retrieved December 7, 2007.
 
 
 
 
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[Category:philosophy]]
 
[[Category:philosophy]]
  
{{credit|143920209}}
+
{{credit|Idea|143920209|History_of_ideas|163293010|Theory_of_forms|17477267|Representative_realism|174214851}}
* This article incorporates text from the [[old Catholic Encyclopedia]] of 1914, a publication now in the public domain.
 
* This article incorporates text from the [[Schaff-Herzog Encyclopedia of Religious Knowledge]], a publication now in the public domain.
 
*{{1911}}
 

Latest revision as of 22:29, 24 February 2018


An idea (Greek: ἰδέα) as a philosophical term generally refers to an image in the mind. Concepts basically refer to generalized ideas, and categories are the most fundamental concepts.

Whether ideas exist in the mind alone or as an extra-mental objective existence, whether ideas are generated or exist innately in the mind, whether some types of ideas (such as God, soul, and world: See Kant) should be considered special or basically the same, and other questions concerning ideas have been central issues in the history of philosophy. Questions regarding the nature, essence, origin, and types of ideas have been integrated and contextualized into each philosophical thought, both in ontology and epistemology, and the meaning of idea has thus been configured accordingly.

Plato asserted, for example, that ideas or forms ("eidos") are not simply images that exist in the mind, but they are permanent extra-mental forms with which Demiurge, the divine crafter, created the cosmos. Those ideas or forms are, according to Plato, also inscribed in the soul prior to experience. Medieval scholastics understood those ideas as the forms within God's mind by which the Creator created the universe. Modern philosophers since Descartes, however, interpreted ideas as mental images that exist within the mind of a cognitive subject.[1] Ideas were often understood as representations of objects outside of mind. This concept of idea as a mental image is still held today.

Etymology

The word "Idea" originates from the Greek, and it is the feminine form of, the word εἶδος (Greek eidos: something seen; form, shape; related to idein "to see," eidenai "to know" [2]). "Idea" meant at first a form, shape, or appearance and implied the "visual aspect" of things in classical Greek.[3] Accordingly, ideas and forms are used interchangeably for Greek authors.

With Plato, idea and/or form became essential concepts in philosophy. The ontological status of idea or form, epistemological roles of ideas or forms, and their ethical implications became central issues in philosophy. In this article, Plato's concept and the modern understanding of ideas are introduced to illustrate two different approaches to ideas.

Plato's Theory of Forms or Ideas ("eidos")

Plato concept of ideas or forms are often capitalized as "Ideas" or "Forms" to distinguish his distinct notion from the modern conception of ideas as mental images. In this section, the term Form is used. But Form and Idea both refer to the same Greek term "eidos." Plato's Theory of Forms[4] asserts that Forms or Ideas, and not the material world of change known to us through sensation, possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality.[5] Plato spoke of Forms[6] in formulating his solution to the problem of universals.

Terminology: The Forms and the forms

The English word "form" may be used to translate two distinct concepts with which Plato was concerned—the outward "form" or appearance of something (Greek eidos and idea in their conventional, nontechnical senses, or other terms such as morphē), and "Form" in a new, technical sense, apparently invented by Plato (esp. eidos, idea). These are often distinguished by the use of uncapitalized "form" and capitalized "Form," respectively. In the following summary passage, the two concepts are related to each other:[7]

Suppose a person were to make all kinds of figures (schēmata) of gold… —somebody points to one of them and asks what it is (ti pot'esti). By far the safest and truest answer is [to say] that it is gold; and not to call the triangle or any other figures which are formed in the gold "these" (tauta) as though they had existence (hōs onta)… And the same argument applies to the universal nature (phusis) which receives all bodies (sōmata)—that must always be called the same; for, while receiving all things, she never departs at all from her own nature, and never… assumes a form (morphē) like that of any of the things which enter into her; … But the forms which enter into and go out of her are the likenesses (mimēmata) of real existences (tōn ontōn aei) modelled after their patterns (tupōthenta) in a wonderful and inexplicable manner…

The forms that we see, according to Plato, are not real, but literally mimic the real Forms. In the Allegory of the cave expressed in Republic they are called the shadows of real things. That which the observer understands when he views the mimics are the archetypes of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things we see all around us. They are not located in the object, which as far as Plato is concerned, is mere smoke and mirrors situated in space (which also is real).

Forms or Ideas ("eidos")

The Greek concept of form precedes the attested language and is represented by a number of words mainly having to do with vision: the sight or appearance of a thing. The main words, εἶδος (eidos) and ἰδέα (idea)[8] come from the Indo-European root *weid-, "see."[9] Both words are in the works of Homer, the earliest Greek literature.

These meanings remained the same over the centuries until the beginning of philosophy, when they became equivocal, acquiring additional specialized philosophic meanings. The pre-Socratic philosophers, starting with Thales, noted that appearances change quite a bit and began to inquire into the essential existence of things, leading some to conclude that things were made of substances, which comprise the actually existing thing being seen. They began to question the relationship between the appearance and the essential existence of things, between the substance and the form; thus, the theory of matter and form (today's hylomorphism) was born. Starting with at least Plato, and possibly germinal in some of the presocratics, the forms were considered "in" something else, which Plato called nature (phusis). The latter seemed as a "mother" (matter from mater)[10] of substances.

For Plato, as well as in general speech, there is a form for every object or quality in reality: forms of dogs, human beings, mountains, colors, courage, love, and goodness. While the notion of form served to identify objects, Plato went further and inquired into the Form itself. He supposed that the object is essentially or "really" the Form and that phenomena are mere shadows that mimic the Form; that is, momentary portrayals of the Form under different circumstances. The problem of the universals - how can one thing in general be many things in particular - was solved by presuming that Form was a distinct singular thing but caused plural representations of itself in particular objects.[11] Matter was considered particular in itself.

These Forms are the essences of various objects: they are that without which a thing would not be the kind of thing it is. For example, there are countless tables in the world but the Form of table-ness is at the core; it is the essence of all tables.[12] Plato held that the world of Forms is separate from our own world (the world of substances) and also is the true basis of reality. Removed from matter, Forms are the most pure of all things. Furthermore, Plato believed that true knowledge/intelligence is the ability to grasp the world of Forms with one's mind.[13]

A Form is aspatial (outside the world) and atemporal (outside time). [14] Forms are aspatial in that they have no spatial dimensions, and thus no orientation in space, nor do they even (like the point) have a location.[15] They are non-physical, but they are not in the mind, and are extra-mental.[16]

A Form is an objective "blueprint" of perfection.[17] The Forms are perfect themselves because they are unchanging. For example, say we have a triangle drawn on a blackboard. A triangle is a polygon with 3 sides. The triangle as it is on the blackboard is far from perfect. However, it is only the intelligibility of the Form "triangle" that allows us to know the drawing on the chalkboard is a triangle, and the Form "triangle" is perfect and unchanging. It is exactly the same whenever anyone chooses to consider it; however, the time is that of the observer and not of the triangle.

The pure land

The Forms exist in a rarefied sector of the universe. For everything on Earth there is a formal counterpart:[18]

But the true earth is pure (katharan) and situated in the pure heaven (en katharōi ouranōi) … and it is the heaven which is commonly spoken by us as the ether (aithera) … for if any man could arrive at the extreme limit … he would acknowledge that this other world was the place of the true heaven (ho alethōs ouranos) and the true light (to alethinon phōs) and the true earth (hē hōs alēthōs gē).

In comparison to it our Earth is "spoilt and corroded as in the sea all things are corroded by the brine."[19] There the colors are "brighter far and clearer than ours; there is a purple of wonderful lustre, also the radiance of gold and the white which is in the earth is whiter than any chalk or snow."[19] Moreover the plants are better: "and in this far region everything that grows - trees and flowers and fruits - are in a like degree fairer than any here."[19] Gems lie about like ordinary stones: "and there are hills, having stones … more transparent, and fairer in color than our highly-valued emeralds and sardonyxes …."[19] And for the humans, "… they have no disease, and live much longer than we do, and have sight, and hearing and smell … in far greater perfection. They converse with the gods and see the sun, moon and stars as they truly are …."[19] Indeed, for Plato, "god" is identical to the Form of the Good.

Evidence of Forms

Plato's main evidence for the existence of Forms is intuitive only and is as follows.

The argument from human perception

To understand Plato's argument from human perception, it is helpful to use the example of the color blue. We call both the sky and blue jeans by the same color: blue. However, clearly a pair of jeans and the sky are not the same color; moreover, the wavelengths of light reflected by the sky at every location and all the millions of blue jeans in every state of fading constantly change, and yet we somehow have an idea of the basic form Blueness as it applies to them. Says Plato:[20][21]

But if the very nature of knowledge changes, at the time when the change occurs there will be no knowledge, and, according to this view, there will be no one to know and nothing to be known: but if that which knows and that which is known exist ever, and the beautiful and the good and every other thing also exist, then I do not think that they can resemble a process of flux, as we were just now supposing.

The argument from perfection

No one has ever seen a perfect circle, nor a perfectly straight line, yet everyone knows what a circle and a straight line are. Plato utilizes the tool-maker's blueprint as evidence that Forms are real:[22]

… when a man has discovered the instrument which is naturally adapted to each work, he must expess this natural form, and not others which he fancies, in the material ….

Given that perceived circles or lines are not exactly circular or straight, and yet idea of a perfect circle or line directs the manufacturer, then it follows that there must exist the idea or Form of a perfect circle or line.

Criticisms of Platonic Forms

Self-criticism

Plato was well aware of the limitations of his theory, as he offered his own criticisms of it in his dialogue Parmenides, in which Socrates is portrayed as a young philosopher acting as junior counterfoil to aged Parmenides.

The dialogue does present a very real difficulty with the Theory of Forms, which was overcome later by Aristotle (but not without rejecting the independently existing world of Forms). It is debated whether Plato viewed these criticisms as conclusively disproving the Theory of Forms. It is worth noting that Aristotle was a student and then a junior colleague of Plato; it is entirely possible that the presentation of Parmenides "sets up" for Aristotle; that is, they agreed to disagree.

The difficulty lies in the conceptualization of the "participation" of an object in a form (or Form). The young Socrates conceives of his solution to the problem of the universals in another metaphor, which though wonderfully apt, remains to be elucidated:[23]

Nay, but the idea may be like the day which is one and the same in many places at once, and yet continuous with itself; in this way each idea may be one and the same in all at the same time.

But exactly how is a Form like the day in being everywhere at once? The solution calls for a distinct form, in which the particular instances that are not identical to the form participate; i.e., the form is shared like the day in many places. The concept of "participate," represented in Greek by more than one word, is as obscure in Greek as it is in English. Plato hypothesized that distinctness meant existence as an independent being, thus opening himself up to the famous Third Man Argument of Parmenides,[24] which proves that forms cannot independently exist and be participated.[25] and [26]

If universal and particulars - say man or greatness - all exist and are the same, then the Form is not one but is multiple. If they are only like each other then they contain a form that is the same and others that are different. Thus if the Form and a particular are alike then there must be another, or third, man or greatness by possession of which they are alike. An infinite regression must result (consequently the mathematicians often call the argument the Third Man Regression); that is, an endless series of third men. The ultimate participant, greatness, rendering the entire series great, is missing. Moreover, any Form is not unitary but is composed of infinite parts, none of which is the proper Form.

The young Socrates (some may say the young Plato) did not give up the Theory of Forms over the Third Man but took another tack, that the particulars do not exist as such. Whatever they are, they "mime" the Forms, appearing to be particulars. This is a clear dip into representationalism, that we cannot observe the objects as they are in themselves but only their representations. That view has the weakness that if only the mimes can be observed then the real Forms cannot be known at all and the observer can have no idea of what the representations are supposed to represent or that they are representations.

Plato's later answer would be that men already know the Forms because they were in the world of Forms before birth. The mimes only recall these Forms to memory.[27] Unfortunately the hidden world can in no way be verified in this lifetime and its otherworldness can only be a matter of speculation (in those times before the knowledge of revelation and faith).[28]

Aristotelian criticism

The topic of Aristotelian criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms is quite extensive and continues to expand, for many reasons. First, Aristotle did not just criticize Plato but Platonism typically without distinguishing individuals. Moreover, rather than quote Plato directly he chose to summarize him often in one-liners that are not comprehensible without considerable exegesis, and sometimes not then. As a historian of prior thought, Aristotle often uses the prior arguments as a foil to present his own ideas. Consequently, in presenting the Aristotelian criticisms it is necessary to distinguish what Aristotle wrote, what he meant, what Plato meant, the validity of Aristotle's understanding of Plato's thoughts, and the relationship between Plato's thought and Aristotle's concepts: a formidable task extending over centuries of scholarship. This article presents a few sample arguments addressed by a few sample scholars. Readers may pursue the topic more fully through the citations and bibliography.

In the summary passage quoted above[7] Plato distinguishes between real and non-real "existing things," where the latter term is used of substance. The figures, which the artificer places in the gold, are not substance, but gold is. Aristotle, after stating that according to Plato all things studied by the sciences have Form, asserts that Plato considered only substance to have Form giving rise to the contradiction of Forms existing as the objects of the sciences but not existing as non-substance.[29]

Despite Ross's objection that Aristotle is wrong in his assumption, that Plato considers many non-substances to be Forms, such as Sameness, Difference, Rest, Motion, the criticism remains and is major, for it seems that Plato did not know where to draw the line between Form and non-Form. As Cornford points out,[30] things about which the young Socrates (and Plato) asserted "I have often been puzzled about these things"[31] referring to Man, Fire and Water, appear as Forms in his later works, but others do not, such as Hair, Mud, Dirt, about which Socrates is made to assert: "it would be too absurd to suppose that they have a Form."

Another argument of Aristotle attacked by Ross[29] is that Socrates posits a Form, Otherness, to account for the differences between Forms. Apparently Otherness is existing non-existence: the Not-tall, the Not-beautiful, etc., so that every particular object participates in a Form causing it not to be one essence; that is, a Form to exclude the essence but allow all others. According to Ross, however, Plato never made the leap from "A is not B" to "A is Not-B." Otherness only applies to its own particulars and not to the other Forms; for example, there is no Form, Non-Greek, only particulars of Otherness that suppress Greek.

However, this objection does not evade the question. Whether or not Socrates meant that the particulars of Otherness are Not-Greek, Not-tall, Not-beautiful, etc., such a particular still operates only on specific essences. If it were a general exclusiveness every Form would be excluded and nothing be anything in particular. If the exclusion excludes one essence then either Otherness is not unitary or multiple Othernesses exist, each one excluding one essence. It is something and it is not something; it allows and does not allow, which are contradictory properties of the one Form.

Though familiar with insight, Plato had postulated that we know Forms through remembrance. Aristotle successfully makes epistemological arguments against this view. In Plato the particulars do not really exist. Countering "... for that which is non-existent cannot be known"[32] Aristotle points out that proof rests on prior knowledge of universals and that if we did not know what universals are we would have no idea of what we were trying to prove and could not be trying to prove it. Knowledge of the universal is given from even one particular; in fact, the inductive method of proof depends on it.[33]

This epistemology sets up for the main attack on Platonism (though not named) in Metaphysics.[34] In brief, universal and particulars imply each other; one is logically prior or posterior to the other. If they are to be regarded as distinct, then they cannot be universal and particulars; that is, there is no reason to understand the universal from the objects that are supposed to be particulars. It is not the case that if a universal A might be supposed to have particulars a1, a2, etc., A is missing or a1, a2, etc. are missing. A does not exist at all and a1, a2, etc. are unrelated objects.

Ideas as Representations: Modern Representative Theory of Perception

The concept of ideas as images in mind in modern philosophy appeared within the context of the Representative Theory of Perception, a common framework of thought in modern philosophy.

The Representative Theory of Perception, also known as Indirect realism, "epistemological dualism," and "The veil of perception," is a philosophical concept. It states that we do not (and can not) perceive the external world directly; instead we know only our ideas or interpretations of objects in the world. Thus, a barrier or a veil of perception prevents first-hand knowledge of anything beyond it. The "veil" exists between the mind and the existing world.

The debate then occurs about where our ideas come from, and what this place is like. An indirect realist believes our ideas come from sense data of a real, material, external world. The doctrine states that in any act of perception, the immediate (direct) object of perception is only a sense-datum that represents an external object.

Aristotle was the first to provide an in-depth description of Indirect realism. In his work, On the Soul, he describes how the eye must be affected by changes in an intervening medium rather than by objects themselves. He then speculates on how these sense impressions can form our experience of seeing and reasons that an endless regress would occur unless the sense itself were self aware. He concludes by proposing that the mind is the things it thinks. He calls the images in the mind "ideas."

The way that indirect realism involves intermediate stages between objects and perceptions immediately raises a question: How well do sense-data represent external objects, properties, and events? Indirect realism creates deep epistemological problems, such as solipsism and the problem of the external world. Nonetheless, Indirect realism has been popular in the history of philosophy and has been developed by many philosophers including Bertrand Russell, Spinoza, René Descartes, and John Locke.

John Locke

In striking contrast to Plato’s use of idea [35] is that of John Locke in his masterpiece Essay Concerning Human Understanding in the Introduction where he defines idea as "It being that term which, I think, serves best to stand for whatsoever is the object of the understanding when a man thinks, I have used it to express whatever is meant by phantasm, notion, species, or whatever it is which the mind can be employed about in thinking ; and I could not avoid frequently using it." He said he regarded the book necessary to examine our own abilities and see what objects our understandings were, or were not, fitted to deal with. In his philosophy other outstanding figures followed in his footsteps - Hume and Kant in the eighteenth century, Arthur Schopenhauer in the nineteenth century, and Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Karl Popper in the twentieth century. Locke always believed in good sense - not pushing things to extremes and taking fully into account the plain facts of the matter. He considered his common sense ideas "good-tempered, moderate, and down-to-earth." c

David Hume

Hume differs from Locke by limiting "idea" to the more or less vague mental reconstructions of perceptions, the perceptual process being described as an "impression."[36] Hume shared with Locke the basic empiricist premise that it is only from life experiences (whether our own or other's) that out knowledge of the existence of anything outside of ourselves can be ultimately derived. We shall carry on doing what we are prompted to do by our emotional drives of all kinds. In choosing the means to those ends we shall follow our accustomed association of ideas.d Hume is quoted as saying: "Reason is the slave of the passions."

History of ideas

Walk of Ideas

The history of ideas is a field of research in history that deals with the expression, preservation, and change of human ideas over time. The history of ideas is a sister-discipline to, or a particular approach within, intellectual history. Work in the history of ideas may involve interdisciplinary research in the history of philosophy, the history of science, or the history of literature. In Sweden, the history of ideas has been a distinct university subject since the 1930s, when Johan Nordström, a scholar of literature, was appointed professor of the new discipline at Uppsala University. Today, several universities across the world provide courses in this field, usually as part of a graduate program.

The Lovejoy approach

The historian Arthur O. Lovejoy (1873–1962) coined the phrase history of ideas and initiated its systematic study, in the early decades of the twentieth century. For decades Lovejoy presided over the regular meetings of the History of Ideas Club at Johns Hopkins University, where he worked as a professor of history from 1910 to 1939.

Aside from his students and colleagues engaged in related projects (such as René Wellek and Leo Spitzer, with whom Lovejoy engaged in extended debates), scholars such as Isaiah Berlin, Michel Foucault, Christopher Hill, J. G. A. Pocock and others have continued to work in a spirit close to that with which Lovejoy pursued the history of ideas. The first chapter/lecture of Lovejoy's book The Great Chain of Being lays out a general overview of what is intended (or at least what he intended) to be the program and scope of the study of the history of ideas.

Unit-ideas

Lovejoy's history of ideas takes as its basic unit of analysis the unit-idea, or the individual concept. These unit-ideas work as the building-blocks of the history of ideas: though they are relatively unchanged in themselves over the course of time, unit-ideas recombine in new patterns and gain expression in new forms in different historical eras. As Lovejoy saw it, the historian of ideas had the task of identifying such unit-ideas and of describing their historical emergence and recession in new forms and combinations.

Modern work

Quentin Skinner has been influential with his critique of Lovejoy's "unit-idea" methodology. Instead, he proposes a sensitivity to the cultural context of the texts being analysed and the ideas they contained.

See also

Notes

  1. Idea of God has an extra-mental existence for Descartes. His perspective to the idea of God is closely tied to his proof of the existence of God.
  2. Eidos explained in -oed suffix, Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved September 19, 2015.
  3. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 4: 118 Plato writes of a person "beautiful in idea" meaning "beautiful in visual aspect" or good-looking (Protagoras 315e).
  4. The name of this syndrome of Plato's thought is not modern and has not been extracted from certain dialogues by modern scholars. The term was used at least as early as Diogenes Laertius, who called it (Plato's) "Theory of Forms:" Πλάτων ἐν τῇ περὶ τῶν ἰδεῶν ὑπολήψει…., "Plato" Lives of Eminent Philosophers Book III, Paragraph 15
  5. Stephen Watt. "Introduction: The Theory of Forms (Books 5-7)" in Plato: Republic (London: Wordsworth Editions, 1997, ISBN 1853264830), xiv-xvi.
  6. The Great Ideas: A Synopticon of Great Books of the Western World. Chapter 28: Form . Great Books of the Western World. II (I of the Synopticon), 526-542. Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc 1952, 528 states that Form or Idea get capitalized according to this convention when they refer "to that which is separate from the characteristics of material things and from the ideas in our mind."
  7. 7.0 7.1 Timaeus Paragraph 50 a-c, Jowett translation.
  8. This transliteration leads to the unfortunate misnomer "theory of Ideas." The word is not the English "idea," which is a mental concept only, and the famous theory has nothing at all to do with the "ideas" of English speakers.
  9. Idea. Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved September 18, 2015.
  10. "matter" Dictionary.com. Retrieved September 18, 2015.
  11. For example, Parmenides 129: "Nor, again, if a person were to show that all is one by partaking of one, and at the same time many by partaking of many, would that be very astonishing. But if he were to show me that the absolute one was many, or the absolute many one, I should be truly amazed."
  12. Cratylus 389: "For neither does every smith, although he may be making the same instrument for the same purpose, make them all of the same iron. The form must be the same, but the material may vary …."
  13. For example, Theaetetus 185: " the mind, by a power of her own, contemplates the universals in all things."
  14. The creation of the universe is the creation of time: "For there were no days and nights and months and years … but when he (God) constructed the heaven he created them also." - Timaeus paragraph 37. For the creation God used "the pattern of the unchangeable," which is "that which is eternal." - paragraph 29. Therefore "eternal" - to aïdion, "the everlasting" - as applied to Form means atemporal.
  15. Space answers to matter, the place-holder of form: "… and there is a third nature (besides Form and form), which is space (chōros), and is eternal (aei "always," certainly not atemporal), and admits not of destruction and provides a home for all created things … we say of all existence that it must of necessity be in some place and occupy space …." - Timaeus paragraph 52. Some readers will have long since remembered that in Aristotle time and space are accidental forms. Plato does not make this distinction and concerns himself mainly with essential form. In Plato, if time and space were admitted to be form, time would be atemporal and space aspatial.
  16. These terms produced with the English prefix a- are not ancient. For the usage refer to Online Etymology Dictionary, a- (2). Retrieved September 18, 2015. They are however customary terms of modern metaphysics; for example, see Martha C. Beck, Plato's Self-Corrective Development of the Concepts of Soul, Form and Immortality in Three Arguments of the Phaedo (Edwin Mellon Press, 1999, ISBN 0773479503), 148; and see Katherine Hawley, "How Things Persist" (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001, ISBN 019924913X), Chapter 1.
  17. For example, Timaeus 28: "The work of the creator, whenever he looks to the unchangeable and fashions the form and nature of his work after an unchangeable pattern, must necessarily be made fair and perfect …."
  18. Phaedo, paragraph 109.
  19. 19.0 19.1 19.2 19.3 19.4 Phaedo, Paragraph 110.
  20. Cratylus paragraph 440.
  21. Aristotle in Metaphysics A.987a.29-b.14 and M1078b9-32 says that Plato devised the Forms to answer a weakness in the doctrine of Heraclitus, who held that nothing exists, but everything is in a state of flow. If nothing exists it can't be known, and so Plato took the universals of Socrates and made them into distinct beings that can be known. Socrates did not think they were separate beings.
  22. Cratylus paragraph 389.
  23. Parmenides 131.
  24. The name is at least as old as Aristotle, who says in Metaphysics A.IX.990b.15: "(The argument) they call the third man." A summary of the argument and the quote from Aristotle can be found in the venerable George Grote. "App I Aristotle's Objections to Plato's Theory" in Aristotle, Second Edition with Additions. (London: John Murray, 1880), 559-560, note b (downloadable Google Books). Grote points out that more likely than not Aristotle lifted this argument from the Parmenides of Plato; certainly, his words indicate the argument was already well-known under that name.
  25. Analysis of the argument has been going on for centuries, and some analyses are complex, technical and perhaps tedious for the general reader. Those who are interested in the more technical analyses can find more of a presentation in Steven D. Hales, "The Recurring Problem of the Third Man" Auslegung 17 (1)(1991): 67-80. Retrieved September 18, 2015.
  26. Michael Durham, "Two Men and the Third Man" The Dualist: Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy (Stanford University) 4 (1997).
  27. Plato to a large extent identifies what today is called insight with recollection: "whenever on seeing one thing you conceived another whether like or unlike, there must surely have been an act of recollection?" - Phaedo paragraph 229. Thus geometric reasoning on the part of persons who know no geometry is not insight but is recollection. He does recognize insight: "... with a sudden flash there shines forth understanding about every problem ..." (with regard to "the course of scrutiny") - The Seventh Letter 344b.
  28. Plato was aware of the problem: "How real existence is to be studied or discovered is, I suspect, beyond you and me." - Cratylus paragraph 439.
  29. 29.0 29.1 Sir David Ross, Plato's Theory of Ideas (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1951), Chapter XI, initial.
  30. Francis MacDonald Cornford, Plato and Parmenides (New York: The Liberal Arts Press, 1957), 82-83.
  31. Parmenides (dialogue) paragraph 130c.
  32. Posterior Analytics 71b.25.
  33. Posterior Analytics 71a-b.
  34. Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book III Chapters 3-4, Paragraphs 999a-b, otherwise known as Β 3-4.
  35. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vol 4: 487 - 503
  36. The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Vol 4: 74 - 90

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Balz, A. G. A. Idea and essence in the philosophies of Hobbes and Spinoza. New York: Columbia University Press, 1918.
  • Beck, Martha C. Plato's Self-Corrective Development of the Concepts of Soul, Form and Immortality in Three Arguments of the Phaedo. Edwin Mellon Press, 1999. ISBN 0773479503
  • Berlin, I., and H. Hardy. Against the current essays in the history of ideas. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001. ISBN 0691090262
  • Bevir, M. The logic of the history of ideas. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999. ISBN 0521640342
  • Cornford, Francis MacDonald. Plato and Parmenides. New York: The Liberal Arts Press, 1957.
  • Durham, Michael. "Two Men and the Third Man." The Dualist: Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy (Stanford University) (1997): 4
  • Fine, Gail. On Ideas: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms. Oxford University Press, 1992. ISBN 0198235496. Reviewed by Gerson, Lloyd P . Gail Fine, On Ideas. Aristotle's Criticism of Plato's Theory of Forms. Bryn Mawr Classical Review 04.05.25 (1993).
  • Grote, George, "App I Aristotle's Objections to Plato's Theory." Aristotle, Second Edition with Additions, London: John Murray, 1880.
  • Lessig, L. The future of ideas the fate of the commons in a connected world. New York: Random House, 2001. ISBN 0375505784
  • Lovejoy, A. O. The Great chain of being a study of the history of an idea. Cambridge: The William James lectures delivered at Harvard University, 1933; MA, Harvard University Press, 1974. ISBN 0674361539
  • Lovejoy, A. O. Essays in the history of ideas. Westport, CT: Greenwood Press, 1978. ISBN 0313205043
  • Ross, Sir David. Plato's Theory of Ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1951.
  • The Encyclopedia of Philosophy, MacMillian Publishing Company, New York, 1973. ISBN 0028949501
  • Watson, Peter. Ideas: a history from fire to Freud. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 2005.
  • Watt, Stephen. "Introduction: The Theory of Forms (Books 5-7)," Plato: Republic. London: Wordsworth Editions, 1997. ISBN 1853264830
  • Wiener, P. P. Dictionary of the history of ideas studies of selected pivotal ideas. New York: Scribner, 1973. ISBN 0684132931
  • Yolton, J. W. John Locke and the way of ideas. [London]: Oxford University Press, 1956.
  • This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.
  • This article incorporates text from the Old Catholic Encyclopedia of 1914, a publication now in the public domain.
  • This article incorporates text from the Schaff-Herzog Encyclopedia of Religious Knowledge, a publication now in the public domain.

External links

All links retrieved February 24, 2018.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.