Difference between revisions of "Morality" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
 
(26 intermediate revisions by 9 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{claimed}}
+
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{copyedited}}
{{Refimprove|date=March 2007}}
+
In its "everyday sense" '''morality''' (from [[Latin]] ''{{lang|la|moralitas}}'' "manner, character, proper behavior") refers to a ''code of conduct,'' by which human beings regulate their lives. Theoretical interest in morality arises from the distinct sorts of questions that might be asked about this code of conduct.  
<br/>{{Ethics}}
 
'''Morality ''' (from the [[Latin]] ''{{lang|la|moralitas}}'' "manner, character, proper behaviour") has three principal meanings. In its first descriptive usage, morality means a code of conduct held to be authoritative in matters of right and wrong, whether by society, philosophy, religion, or individual conscience. In its second, normative and universal, sense, morality refers to an ideal code of conduct, one which would be espoused in preference to alternatives by all rational people, under specified conditions. To deny 'morality' in this sense is a position known as [[moral skepticism]].<ref>http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/</ref> In its third usage 'morality' is synonymous with [[ethics]], the systematic philosophical study of the moral domain.<ref>http://www.philosophyblog.com.au/ethics-vs-morality-the-distinction-between-ethics-and-morals/</ref> Ethics seeks to address questions such as how a moral outcome can be achieved in a specific situation ([[applied ethics]]), how moral values should be determined ([[normative ethics]]), what morals people actually abide by ([[descriptive ethics]]), what is the fundamental nature of ethics or morality itself, including whether it has any objective justification ([[meta-ethics]]), and how moral capacity or moral agency develops and what its nature is ([[moral psychology]]).<ref>http://www.iep.utm.edu/e/ethics.htm</ref> In applied ethics, for example, the prohibition against taking human life is controversial with respect to [[capital punishment]], [[abortion]] and wars of [[invasion]]. In normative ethics, a typical question might be whether a lie told for the sake of protecting someone from harm is justified. In meta-ethics, a key issue is the meaning of the terms "right" or "wrong." [[Moral realism]] would hold that there are true moral statements which report objective moral facts, whereas moral [[anti-realism]] would hold that morality: is derived from any one of the [[norm (sociology)|norms]] prevalent in society ([[cultural relativism]]); the edicts of a god ([[divine command theory]]); is merely an expression of the speakers' sentiments ([[emotivism]]); an implied imperative ([[prescriptivism (philosophy)|prescriptivism]]); falsely presupposes that there are objective moral facts ([[error theory]]). Some thinkers hold that there is no correct definition of right behavior, that morality can only be judged with respect to particular situations, within the standards of particular belief systems and socio-historical contexts.  This position, known as [[moral relativism]], often cites empirical evidence from anthropology as evidence to support its claims.<ref>http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-relativism/</ref> The opposite view, that there are universal, eternal moral truths is known as [[moral absolutism]].  Moral absolutists might concede that forces of social [[conformity (psychology)|conformity]] significantly shape moral decisions, but deny that cultural norms and [[convention (norm)|custom]]s define morally right behavior.
 
  
==Religion as a source of moral authority==
+
One question asks the kinds of practical rules people actually use to govern their lives. This is a descriptive question, an attempt to understand the actual practices of various societies, groups of people, and individuals. The results of such an attempt will constitute the meaning of "morality" in a descriptive sense. Given that different groups of people adhere to different codes of conduct, there can be said to be more than one standard of morality.
  
{{Main|Divine Command Theory}}
+
A second question questions the validity of the codes of conduct by which people adhere to. This is the area of [[moral philosophy]], which attempts to ascertain the rules that people ''ought'' to use in guidance of their conduct. (The rules identified by moral philosophy as prescribing how human beings should live need not coincide with actual practices and accepted moral principles.) The results of this inquiry will constitute the meaning of "morality" in its normative sense.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
A third set of questions asks whether the practical rules that make up a kind of morality are objective, or whether they are simply expressions of our basic feelings of approval and disapproval; it asks whether they are universally valid, or relative to the groups who uphold them. Finally, it asks whether or not they depend on [[religion]]. This is the province of [[meta-ethics]], which attempts to understand the nature of codes of correct behavior.
  
Religious belief systems usually include the idea of divine will and divine [[Last Judgment|judgment]] and usually correspond to a moral code of conduct.
+
==Descriptive morality==
 +
Morality in a descriptive sense may be defined as a code of conduct endorsed and adhered to by a society, group or—much less frequently—individual. Moral codes in this sense will, therefore, differ both from society to society, within societies, and amongst individuals. In its descriptive sense, morality is whatever a society, group, or individual, says it is. For example, descriptive "morality" may include norms of correct behavior according to which [[cannibalism]] and [rape]] are morally permissible. Nor is it the case that descriptive "moralities" must always be consistent in their application of moral rules (even within a culture). Historically speaking, different moral rules were held to apply to [[slavery|slaves]] and free men and women in societies in which slave owning was permitted.  
  
== Anthropological perspectives==
+
In its descriptive sense, then, "morality" refers to the codes of conduct regulating how people behave, and without inquiring as to whether they ought to adhere to these codes. Descriptive morality is of central interest to [[anthropology|anthropologists]], [[history|historians]], and [[sociology|sociologists]]. It is not a primary concern of philosophical inquiry except insofar as the results of research in the social sciences bear upon questions concerning the nature of morality.
{{section-stub}}
 
  
=== Tribal and territorial moralities ===
+
Within the sphere of descriptive morality, a distinction between moral rules, legal rules, and norms of [[etiquette]] is recognized. Firstly, there is a high degree of overlap between morality and [[law]]. Many moral rules are also legal prohibitions or requirements. For example, murder is generally held to be both immoral and illegalHowever, some moral rules do not correspond to legal rules, and so violating a moral code does not necessarily lead to judicial punishment. For example, one is not legally punished for lying in one’s personal life. Conversely, some legal rules do not correspond to moral rules. For example, a system of law contains many proscriptions and requirements regulating bureaucratic procedures, which do not pertain to morality. Even more fundamentally, legal violations are not necessarily moral violations. Unintentionally parking in a designated zone will not count as a moral wrong, although one may still be liable to legal sanction, such as a fine.
[[Celia Green]] has made a distinction between tribal and territorial morality.<ref name = "Green">Green, Celia (2004). ''Letters from Exile: Observations on a Culture in Decline''. Oxford: Oxford Forum. Chapters I-XX. </ref>  She characterizes the latter as predominantly negative and proscriptive: it defines a person’s territory, including his or her property and dependants, which is not to be damaged or interfered withApart from these proscriptions, territorial morality is permissive, allowing the individual whatever behaviour does not interfere with the territory of another. By contrast, tribal morality is prescriptive, imposing the norms of the collective on the individual. These norms will be arbitrary, culturally dependent and ‘flexible’, whereas territorial morality aims at rules which are universal and absolute, such as [[Kant]]’s ‘[[categorical imperative]]’.  Green relates the development of territorial morality to the rise of the concept of private property, and the ascendancy of contract over status.
 
  
=== In-Group and Out-Group ===
+
The distinction between moral rules and norms of etiquette is somewhat sharper than the difference between law and morality. In general, it seems that norms of etiquette (or custom) are of less importance than those of morality. It is polite to arrive on time for a dinner party, but one will not have violated a rule of morality by being late. Conversely, it does violence to one's language to say that one who has committed a robbery has broken the rules of etiquette. In some cases, however, this distinction is blurred. For example, in some places and cultural groups, it may be polite—a matter of etiquette, perhaps—for women to cover their legs while shading into a question of moral right and wrong in other groups.
{{section-stub}}
 
Some observers hold that individuals have distinct sets of moral rules that they apply to different groups of people. There is the "ingroup," which includes the individual and those they believe to be of the same culture or race, and there is the "outgroup," whose members  are not entitled to be treated according to the same rules. Some biologists, anthropologists and [[evolutionary psychology|evolutionary psychologists]] believe this ingroup/outgroup difference is an evolutionary mechanism, one which evolved due to its enhanced survival aspects. [[Gary R. Johnson]] and [[V.S. Falger]] have argued that [[nationalism]] and [[patriotism]] are forms of this ingroup/outgroup boundary.
 
  
=== Comparing cultures ===
+
==Normative morality==  
[[Fons Trompenaars]], author of [[Did the Pedestrian Die?]], tested members of different cultures with various moral dilemmas. One of these was whether the driver of a car would have his friend, a passenger riding in the car, lie in order to protect the driver from the consequences of driving too fast and hitting a pedestrian. Trompenaars found that different cultures had quite different expectations (from none to almost certain)<!--, and in some cultures it mattered whether the pedestrian had died to how much assistance would be expected—>.
+
In its normative sense, morality may be defined as a code of conduct that would be accepted by all rational people under certain idealized conditions. In simpler terms, "morality" is the set of correct moral principles, which, though they probably will never be universally adopted, ought to be adopted. Specifying the nature of such a system of morality is the province of moral philosophy, which seeks, firstly, to formulate a set of principles with which all rational agents ought to comply, and secondly, to explain why this system ought to be adopted. (Some philosophers argue that morality ought not to be characterized in terms of a set of principles at all.)
  
== Evolutionary perspectives ==
+
There is considerable philosophical disagreement as to what this universal system of morality would look like. "There are many rival theories, each expounding a different conception of [what morality is…] and what it means to live morally" (Rachels 1995, p. 1). There is therefore a sense in which the nature of morality itself hinges on these disagreements: the question “what is morality?” in its normative sense, cannot be answered until moral philosophy has resolved its disagreements. In what follows, therefore, the most important attempts define morality will be outlined. The conceptions of morality that currently dominate the philosophical terrain are consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics. Each of these come in various forms and will be briefly discussed.
{{section-stub}}
 
{{Main|Altruism#Altruism in ethology and evolutionary biology}}
 
  
Evolutionary biologists start from the assumption that morality is a product of evolutionary forces.{{Fact|date=September 2007}} On this view, moral codes are ultimately founded on emotional instincts and intuitions that were selected for in the past because they aided survival and reproduction ([[inclusive fitness]]). The strength of the [[maternal bond]] is one example. Another is the [[Imprinting (psychology)#Westermarck effect|Westermarck effect]], seen as underpinning [[Incest taboo|taboos against incest]], which decreases the likelihood of [[defective offspring|inbreeding depression]].  
+
===Consequentialism===
 +
[[Consequentialism]] offers a general definition of morality in terms of the value of consequences brought about, but is independent of any account as to what consequences these may be. The most important version of consequentialism is [[utilitarianism]].
  
Christopher Boehm (1982) has hypothesized that the incremental development of moral complexity throughout [[Hominidae|hominid]] evolution was due to the increasing need to avoid disputes and injuries in moving to open savanna and developing stone weapons. Other theories are that increasing complexity was simply a correlate of increasing group size and brain size, and in particular the development of [[theory of mind]] abilities.  
+
According to classical utilitarian philosophers such as [[John Stuart Mill]] and [[Jeremy Bentham]], morality is defined in terms of actions conforming to the principle of utility, the fundamental principle of morality. According to this principle, an action is moral (or right) if and only if it produces the greatest balance of overall happiness (or well being). By utilitarian standards then, acts of [[euthanasia]] may be considered morally right as insofar as it reduces overall suffering. This differs significantly from many religious moral codes, which maintain that actions such as taking another life (whether it be called murder, assisted suicide, or euthanasia) are never permissible. 
<!--kinship altruism theory—>
 
<!--handicap altruism theory—>
 
<!--reputation theory—>
 
<!--reciprocity theory—>
 
The phenomenon of '[[reciprocity]]' in nature is seen by evolutionary biologists as one way to begin to understand human morality.  Its function is typically to ensure a reliable supply of essential resources, especially for animals living in a habitat where food quantity or quality fluctuates unpredictably. For example, on any given night for [[vampire bat]]s, some individuals fail to feed on prey while others consume a surplus of blood. Bats that have successfully fed then regurgitate part of their blood meal to save a conspecific from starvation. Since these animals live in close-knit groups over many years, an individual can count on other group members to return the favor on nights when it goes hungry (Wilkinson, 1984)
 
  
The evolution of abilities for deception, and social 'politics' have also been studied, in chimpanzees and other group-living organsims.<ref>[http://www.amazon.com/dp/0674356616].</ref> These have been used, in combination with theories of indirect [[reciprocal altruism]] and the importance of reputation, to suggest possible evolutionary bases for moral [[hypocrisy]] and [[gossip]] in humans.  
+
Some of the main criticisms of the utilitarian account of morality—according to which all rational agents ought to follow the utilitarian principle--include the following. Firstly, it is almost impossible in many situations to weigh up overall good; secondly, that the theory does not properly accommodate [[justice]] and [[punishment]]; thirdly, that promise keeping and act utilitarianism are in conflict.
  
These explanations for the existence of morality do not, however, necessarily assist in deciding what is truly ''right'' for future actions. Should an individual's own morality really be determined by what is best for their genetic offspring ([[Wiktionary:Colloquial|colloquially]], but inaccurately, "the good of the species" ''see'' [[group selection]]) Viewholders counter that evolutionary psychology extends millions of years of [[empirical]] justification for our moral sense, provided that sense is indeed innate &mdash; more than recorded history could demonstrate. They claim sensible people would behave with morality knowing [[subconsciousness|subconsciously]] that it has succeeded in the past. Still, an explanation of why and how humans could have a moral basis does not imply that they ''ought'' to hold these views.
+
===Deontological morality===
 +
[[Deontological ethics]] or deontology (Greek: δέον (deon) meaning obligation or duty) defines morality in terms of a system of moral rules. It is probably the moral theory closest to ordinary ways of moral thinking, or at least those adhered to by most Westerners, no doubt a result of the influence of Jewish law and [[Christianity]] on their moral thought. The system of morality articulated by the [[Ten Commandments]] is, for example, deontological in character.
  
==Neuroscientific and psychiatric perspectives==
+
The best-known and most important version of a philosophical deontology is [[Immanuel Kant]]’s theory. The fundamental principle of Kant’s deontology is the [[Categorical Imperative]], which is said to underlie all commonly recognized moral principles. The Categorical Imperative is a principle of consistency, demanding that we act on reasons which all rational agents could endorse, that is, universally acceptable reasons.  This is often compared to the biblical Golden Rule, “Do unto to others as you would have them do unto you”—although there are some important differences. For Kant then, a moral principal is one everyone could follow; if it were made into a universal law it would not be self-defeating. 
=== Mirror-neurons ===
 
  
Research on ''[[mirror neurons]]'', since their discovery in 1996<ref>Giacomo Rizzolatti et al. (1996). ''Premotor cortex and the recognition of motor actions'', Cognitive Brain Research 3 131-141</ref>, suggests that they may have a strong role to play in [[empathy]]. Social neuroscientist [[Jean Decety]] thinks that the ability to recognize and vicariously experience what another creature is undergoing was a key step forward in the evolution of social behavior, and ultimately, morality.<ref>http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2007/05/27/AR2007052701056_pf.html</ref> The inability to feel empathy is one of the defining characteristic of [[psychopath]]y, and this would appear to lend support to Decety's view.<ref>{{cite journal |author=de Wied M, Goudena PP, Matthys W |title=Empathy in boys with disruptive behavior disorders |journal=Journal of child psychology and psychiatry, and allied disciplines |volume=46 |issue=8 |pages=867-80 |year=2005 |pmid=16033635 |doi=10.1111/j.1469-7610.2004.00389.x}}</ref> <ref>{{cite journal |author=Fernandez YM, Marshall WL |title=Victim empathy, social self-esteem, and psychopathy in rapists |journal=Sexual abuse : a journal of research and treatment |volume=15 |issue=1 |pages=11-26 |year=2003 |pmid=12616926 |doi=10.1023/A:1020611606754}}</ref>
+
One important feature of Kant’s conception of morality is that it is absolute. There are no exceptions to moral rules; it is always wrong to murder, tell a lie, or break a promise. One criticism of this view is that sometimes telling a lie could save a life so that it would be unreasonable and even immoral to tell the truth in such a situation.
  
==Psychological perspectives==
+
===Intuitionism===
 +
The best-known form of [[intuitionism]] is probably that presented by [[W.D. Ross]] in ''The Right and the Good''. Ross argues that humans are able to intuit a number of irreducible prima facie duties (to keep promises, to refrain from harming the innocent, and so on), none of which take precedence over any other. In this respect, Ross accepts a form of moral pluralism, since he does not think that right action can be reduced to a single criterion. Here he sets himself up against Utilitarianism and Kantianism, which are both versions of monism because they recognize a single basic moral principle. Ross thinks that the right action (one’s duty proper) in a given situation is determined by a careful weighing of various moral principles that apply in the context. In other words, intuitionism does not claim that there is any one characteristic that all morally correct acts share.
  
{{section-stub}}
+
One significant consequence of intuitionism is that it suggests that morality does not admit of a neat definition. Morality is itself a composite of competing requirements, which cannot be formally unified.
  
== Morality as maladaptive and universal ==
+
===Virtue ethics===
 +
[[Virtue|Virtue ethics]] was the dominant ethical tradition in ancient Greek philosophy and through the [[Middle Ages]]. It has once again risen to prominence in recent times to become one of the three major normative strands (along with [[deontology]] and [[consequentialism]]).
  
Phil Roberts, Jr. has offered a perspective in which morality, and specifically the capacity for guilt, is viewed as a maladaptive byproduct of the evolution of rationality:
+
[[Virtue|Virtue ethics]] downplays, or even denies, the existence of universal rules to which actions must conform. Consequently, it sometimes locates itself in opposition to the notion of morality ''per se,'' which is identified as systems of rules or categorical imperatives. Insofar as ethics is understood as a broader domain in which questions about correct living are posed, virtue ethics may be understood as offering a criticism of morality itself.
  
<blockquote>
+
According to virtue ethics, ethics is not fundamentally about duties or following rules (deontology) or about consequences of actions (consequentialism), but rather about cultivating virtuous dispositions of character, a moral characterA disposition is a tendency to have certain responses in particular situations: responses such as emotions, perceptions, and actions. The virtuous person is someone who acts rightly in response to requirements that are unique to the situation. He or she is someone who is able to perceive what the situation requires and act accordingly by exercising practical wisdom (phronesis). Virtuous habits and behavior (arête) will be those that ultimately lead to the "good life" (or eudaimonia).
Guilt is a maladaptive manifestation of our need to justify our existence, in this case by conforming to a shared subconscious theory of rationality in which 'being rational' is simply a matter of 'being objective', as exemplified in the moral maxim, 'Love (intrinsically value) your neighbor as you love (intrinsically value) yourself'Although none of us can actually measure up to this standard, we nonetheless come to experience feelings of worthlessness (guilt) along with a corresponding reduction in the will to survive (depression) when we deviate from the standard to an unreasonable degree. In other words, a capacity for guilt (having a conscience) is a part of the price we humans have had to pay for having become a little too objective (too rational) for our own good.[http://www.rationology.net]
 
</blockquote>
 
Diller
 
  
==Morality in judicial systems==
+
==Morality and philosophical method==
In most systems, the lack of morality of the individual can also be a sufficient cause for punishment{{Fact|date=July 2007}}, or can be an element for the grading of the punishment.
+
If moral theories disagree in fundamental ways about the very ''nature of morality,'' as they do, then how should one proceed to adjudicate between these views? What sorts of outcomes are possible for moral philosophy? Can morality in the normative sense be defined after all? These are questions of philosophical method.
  
Especially in the systems where [[modesty]] (i.e., with reference to sexual crimes) is legally protected or otherwise regulated, the definition of morality as a legal element and in order to determine the cases of infringement, is usually left to the vision and appreciation of the single judge and hardly ever precisely specified. In such cases, it is common to verify an application of the prevalent common morality of the interested community, that consequently becomes enforced by the law for further reference.
+
The most widely held view about possibility for reaching philosophical agreement on the nature of morality depends on the notion of [[reflective equilibrium]]. In explanation, consider, firstly, that there seems to be (significant) overlap in the kinds of things that most people regard as right and wrong. For example, most people, and most societies, regard the killing of innocent people as morally wrong. Call this moral system "shared morality" (or pre-rational morality). "Shared morality" is, for the most part, a system of moral rules that sets limits to one's conduct (for example, thou shall not to murder or steal). "Shared morality" can also incorporate acts that people are not required to do but would be morally significant if one did do them, such as act of charity. Actions that are morally admirable to do but not strictly required, are called [[supererogatory action]]s.  
  
The government of [[South Africa]] is attempting to create a Moral Regeneration movement. Part of this is a proposed [[Bill of Morals]], which will bring a biblical-based "moral code" into the realm of law. This move by a nominally secular democracy has attracted relatively little criticism.
+
The conflict between the prescriptions of a moral theory and our common ways of thinking raises a question about how moral theories are to be evaluated. If a moral theory conflicts with our commonsense, pre-reflective morality, it could be that the theory is wrong or one's moral convictions are wrong. The most sensible approach seems to be trying to find a reflective equilibrium between one's moral theories and one's intuitive judgments of moral rightness and wrongness. The strategy is to anchor one's moral theories in some of one's most deeply rooted judgments. Intuitions regarding murder, theft, and rape are perhaps so central that if a theory does not accommodate the point that (for example) rape is always wrong, this is a deficiency of the theory. However, part of the point of moral theorizing is to gain a better understanding of the properties of actions that make them right and wrong. Once a theory is justified by a significant number of deep intuitions, one may refine our moral judgments based on insights gained from the theory.  Once this has been achieved it can be said that one's morality has been internalized (as opposed to being shaped from outside influences such as family and society) and that a shift has occurred from pre-"rational" or "group" morality to "rational" or "reflective" morality.
  
 +
==Morality and ethics==
 +
What is the relation between morality and [[ethics]]? Many philosophers hold that there is no substantial difference between the two concepts, and use the terms "ethics" and "moral philosophy" interchangeably.
  
 +
There is, however, another group, who place a great emphasis on maintaining a distinction. Indeed, philosophers such as [[Nietzsche]], [[Bernard Williams]] and [[Elizabeth Anscombe]], may be understood as arguing that "morality," or the "morality system" is an out-moded and indeed pernicious component of ethics. The contrast is drawn between morality as system of absolute rules or moral obligations, such as those issued in the [[Ten Commandments]], and reaching its philosophical apotheosis in [[Kant]]'s theory, and other more promising notions pertaining to how to live a maximally happy life (typically associated with [[virtue]]).
  
==Morality and politics==
+
[[Nietzsche]]’s criticism of "morality" revolves around his notion of slave morality. Slave morality, which corresponds closely to Judeo-Christian morality, with its focus on duty and self-sacrifice, originates in the resentment of the weak and oppressed. Slave morality is a subversion of master morality—the natural states of the strong—in which noble and life affirming values have been transformed in vices, and the contrary, slavish and life-negating values, transformed in values. Slave morality is the outcome of weak people’s coming to regard the qualities of the naturally strong as evil, and transforming their own resentment into current conceptions of morality, which have greatly debilitated human life. Nietzsche may, it seems, be interpreted as saying that morality—understood as slave morality—is life negating and should be abolished.
  
If morality is the answer to the question 'how ought we to live' at the individual level, politics can be seen as addressing the same question at the social level. It is therefore unsurprising that evidence has been found of a relationship between attitudes in morality and politics. [[Jonathan Haidt]] and [[Jesse Graham]] have studied the differences between [[liberals]] and [[conservatives]], in this regard.<ref name = "Haidt">Haidt, Johan and Graham, Jesse (2006). [http://faculty.virginia.edu/haidtlab/articles/haidt.graham.when-morality-opposes-justice.doc ''When morality opposes justice: Conservatives have moral intuitions that liberals may not recognize''] Social Justice Research.</ref><ref>[http://www.newyorker.com/online/video/conference/2007/haidt]</ref><ref>[http://dangerousintersection.org/?p=1445]</ref> According to their model, political conservatives make their moral choices using five moral variables (harm/care, fairness/reciprocity, ingroup loyalty, authority/respect, purity/sanctity), whereas liberals use only two (harm/care and fairness/reciprocity). Haidt also hypothesizes that the origin of this division in the United States can be traced to geohistorical factors, with conservatism strongest in closely knit, ethnically homogenous communities, in contrast to [[port]]-cities, where the cultural mix is greater, thus requiring more liberalism.
+
Similarly, in an article, “Modern Moral Philosophy,” [[Elizabeth Anscombe]] argues that duty based conceptions of morality are conceptually incoherent, for they are based on the idea of a "law without a lawgiver." The point is that a system of morality conceived along the lines of the [[Ten Commandments]], as a system of rules for action, depends (she claims) on someone having actually made these rules. However, in a modern climate, which is unwilling to accept that morality depends on God in this way, the rule-based conception of morality is stripped of its metaphysical foundation. Anscombe recommends a return the eudaimonistic ethical theories of the ancients, particularly [[Aristotle]], which ground morality in the interests and well being of human moral agents, and can do so without appealing to any questionable metaphysics. Again, Anscombe’s point may be understood in terms of the abolition of morality and the return to ethics.
  
Group morality develops from shared [[concept]]s and [[belief]]s and is often codified to regulate behavior within a [[culture]] or community. Various defined actions come to be called moral or immoral. Individuals who choose moral action are popularly held to possess "moral fiber," whereas those who indulge in immoral behavior may be labeled as socially [[degenerate]]. The continued existence of a group may depend on widespread conformity to codes of morality; an inability to adjust moral codes in response to new challenges is sometimes credited with the demise of a community (a positive example would be the function of [[Cistercian]] reform in reviving monasticism; a negative example would be the role of the [[Empress Dowager Cixi|Dowager Empress]] in the subjugation of China to European interests). Within [[nationalist]] movements, there has been some tendency to feel that a nation will not survive or prosper without acknowledging one common morality, regardless of in what it consists.
+
==Morality and Meta-ethics ==
 +
Unlike the normative theories discussed above, [[meta-ethics]] does not propound any moral principles or goals, but is involved entirely in philosophical analysis. It is concerned with the nature of judgments of right and wrong, as well as with defining ethical terms, such as value terms such as "good" and "bad." In other words, metaethics attempts to answer epistemological, logical, and semantic questions relating to ethics. In the Anglophone world, twentieth century philosophers have focused tremendously on meta-ethics rather than normative ethics.  
  
== Moral codes ==
+
===Moral relativism===
 +
As discussed initially under descriptive morality, morality in the sense of actual codes of conduct may be specific to societies, groups, or individual. Some philosophers conclude from this apparent fact of cultural disagreement that moral rules are nothing other than social conventions of particular cultural groups. This entails that the judgment, for example, that lying is always wrong is simply an expression of the beliefs of a group of people, and it is their beliefs about the matter that make it true. This view is called [[moral relativism]]. According to moral relativism, there is no objective and universally valid moral principles. Morality itself is nothing but a matter of convention.
  
Codified morality is generally distinguished from [[norm|custom]], another way for a community to define appropriate activity, by the former's derivation from [[Natural rights|natural]] or universal principles. In certain religious communities, the [[divinity|Divine]] is said to provide these principles through [[revelation]], sometimes in great detail. Such codes may be called laws, as in the [[Torah|Law of Moses]], or community morality may be defined through commentary on the texts of revelation, as in [[Sharia|Islamic law]]. Such codes are distinguished from legal or judicial [[right]], including [[civil rights]], which are based on the accumulated traditions, decrees and legislation of a political authority, though these latter often invoke the authority of the moral law.
+
===Emotivism and prescriptivism===
 +
[[Emotivism]], which is first articulated in the work of [[David Hume]], but is developed to a greater degree of sophistication by writers such as [[A.J. Ayer]] and [[C.L. Stevenson]], holds that evaluations express the speaker’s feelings and attitudes: Saying that kindness is good is a way of expressing one’s approval of kindness. Therefore, moral judgments are not objective and do not state any sort of morally truths; rather they are simply expressions of emotions. Similarly, [[R.M. Hare]] argues that evaluations (moral judgments) are prescriptions (commands): Saying that kindness is good is a way of telling people that they should be kind. Moral evaluative judgments are then understood as emotive or prescriptive, and are contrasted with descriptive judgments. Descriptive judgments are appraisable as true or false whereas evaluative judgments are not.
  
Morality can also be seen as the collection of beliefs as to what constitutes a good life. Since throughout most of [[human]] [[history]], [[religion]]s have provided both visions and regulations for an [[ideal]] life, morality is often confused with religious [[precept]]s. In secular communities, [[lifestyle]] choices, which represent an [[individual]]'s conception of the good life, are often discussed in terms of "morality." Individuals sometimes feel that making an appropriate lifestyle choice invokes a true morality, and that accepted codes of conduct within their chosen community are fundamentally moral, even when such codes deviate from more general social principles.  
+
===Moral skepticism===
 +
Moral skepticism is the view that humans have no moral knowledge. Extreme moral skeptics have claimed that all moral beliefs are false, a view which is known as moral [[nihilism]]. Nihilists such as J.L. Mackie argue that moral claims are false because they implicitly presuppose objective values which do not exist. Other skeptics take a less extreme position adopting a line of argument that builds on moral relativism by claiming that outside cultural influences are so strong that there is no way one can ever objectively assess morality, and that this inevitable bias makes moral beliefs unjustifiable. Arguing from the other direction are skeptics such as [[Richard Joyce]], who argue that it is not outside or cultural influences that make moral claims unjustifiable, but rather the fact that morality is so internalized that makes objective moral truths impossible. Joyce argues that mankind has evolved to hold moral beliefs and we would hold them regardless of whether they are right or wrong, this is known as the argument from [[evolution]].
  
Moral codes are often complex definitions of right and wrong that are based upon well-defined [[value systems]]. Although some people might think that a moral code is simple, rarely is there anything simple about one's [[Value (personal and cultural)|values]], [[ethics]], etc. or, for that matter, the judgment of those of others. The difficulty lies in the fact that morals are often part of a [[religion]] and more often than not about [[culture]] codes. Sometimes, moral codes give way to [[legal code]]s, which couple penalties or corrective actions with particular practices. Note that while many legal codes are merely built on a foundation of religious and/or cultural moral codes, ofttimes they are one and the same.
+
==References==
 
+
*Anscombe, G.E.M. Modern Moral Philosophy. In ''Philosophy'' 33, 1958.
Examples of moral codes include the [[Ethic of reciprocity|Golden Rule]]; the [[Noble Eightfold Path]] of [[Buddhism]]; the ancient Egyptian code of [[Ma'at]] ;the [[Ten Commandments|ten commandments]] of [[Judaism]], [[Christianity]], and [[Islam]]; the [[yamas]] and [[niyama]] of the Hindu scriptures; the [[ten Indian commandments]]; and the principle of the [[Dessek]].
+
*Aristotle and Martin Oswald. ''The Nichomachean Ethics.'' New York: The Bobs-Merrill Company, 1962.  
 
+
*Aquinas, T. and T. Gilby. ''Summa theologiae.'' London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1963.  
Another related concept is the [[moral core]] which is assumed to be innate in each individual, to those who accept that differences between individuals are more important than posited Creators or their rules. This, in some religious systems (e.g. [[Taoism]] and [[Gnosticism]]), is assumed to be the basis of all [[aesthetics]] and thus moral choice. Moral codes as such are therefore seen as coercive—part of human [[politics]].
+
*Bentham, J. and Laurence J Lafleur. ''An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation.'' New York: Hafner Pub. Co., 1948.  
 
+
*DeMarco, Joseph P. ''Moral Theory: A Contemporary Overview.'' Boston: Jones & Bartlett Publishers, 1996. ISBN 978-0867209549
==Moral Psychology==
+
*Feldman, F. ''Introductory Ethics.'' Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1978. ISBN 978-0135017838
===Religiosity and Morality===
+
*Frankena, William K. ''Ethics,'' 2nd edition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1973. {{ASIN|B002EB8QO0}}
 
+
*Hegel, G.W.F. ''Philosophy of Right.'' Trans. Knox. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1942.
In the scientific literature, the degree of religiosity is generally found to be associated with higher ethical attitudes.<ref>As is expressed in the review of literature on this topic by: {{cite journal | author=Conroy, S.J. and Emerson, T.L.N. | title=[http://www.springerlink.com/content/r30712pn2q513456 Business Ethics and Religion: Religiosity as a Predictor of Ethical Awareness Among Students] | journal=Journal of Business Ethics | year=2004 | volume=50 | number=4 | pages=383—396}} DOI:10.1023/B:BUSI.0000025040.41263.09</ref> Although a recent study by [[Gregory S. Paul]] published in the ''Journal of Religion and Society'' argues for a positive correlation between the degree of ''public religiosity'' in a society and certain measures of dysfunction,<ref>{{cite journal| url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2005/2005-11.html| journal=Journal of Religion and Society| title=Cross-National Correlations of Quantifiable Societal Health with Popular Religiosity and Secularism in the Prosperous Democracies: A First Look| first=Gregory S.| last=Paul| location=Baltimore, Maryland| year=2005| volume=7}}</ref> an analysis published later in the same journal contends that a number of methodological problems undermine any findings or conclusions to be taken from the research.<ref>{{cite journal| url=http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2006/2006-1.html| journal=Journal of Religion and Society| title=Religiosity, Secularism, and Social Health| author=Gerson Moreno-Riaño| coauthors=Mark Caleb Smith, Thomas Mach|location=Cedarville University| year=2006| volume=8}}</ref> In a response <ref name = "Jensen">Gary F. Jensen (2006)  Department of Sociology,  Vanderbilt University  ''Religious Cosmologies and Homicide Rates among Nations: A Closer Look'' http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/2006/2006-7.html http://moses.creighton.edu/JRS/pdf/2006-7.pdf  Journal of Religion and Society, Volume 8, ISSN 1522-5658 http://purl.org/JRS </ref> to the study by Paul, Gary F. Jensen  builds on and refines Paul's study. His conclusion, after carrying out elaborate multivariate statistical studies, is that there is a correlation (and perhaps a causal relationship) of higher homicide rates, not with Christianity, but with ''dualism in Christianity'', that is to say with the proportion of the population who believe the devil and hell exist. Excerpt: "A multiple regression analysis reveals a complex relationship with some dimensions of religiosity encouraging homicide and other dimensions discouraging it." Meanwhile, other studies seem to show positive links in the relationship between religiosity and moral behavior<ref>KERLEY, KENT R., MATTHEWS, TODD L. & BLANCHARD, TROY C. (2005) Religiosity, Religious Participation, and Negative Prison Behaviors. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion '''44''' (4), 443-457. {{doi|10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00296.x}}</ref> <ref>SAROGLOU, VASSILIS, PICHON, ISABELLE, TROMPETTE, LAURENCE, VERSCHUEREN, MARIJKE & DERNELLE, REBECCA (2005) Prosocial Behavior and Religion: New Evidence Based on Projective Measures and Peer Ratings. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion '''44''' (3), 323-348. {{doi|10.1111/j.1468-5906.2005.00289.x}}</ref> <ref>Regnerus, Mark D. & Burdette, Amy (2006)
+
*Hobbes, T. ''Leviathan''. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998. ISBN 0585193282.  
RELIGIOUS CHANGE AND ADOLESCENT FAMILY DYNAMICS. The Sociological Quarterly '''47''' (1), 175-194. {{doi|10.1111/j.1533-8525.2006.00042.x}}</ref>—for example, surveys suggesting a positive connection between faith and altruism.<ref>eg [http://www.ropercenter.uconn.edu/data_access/data/datasets/social_capital_community_survey.html a survey] by [[Robert Putnam]] showing that membership of religious groups was positively correlated with membership of voluntary organisations</ref> Modern research in [[criminology]] also acknowledges an ''inverse'' relationship between religion and crime,<ref>As is stated in: Doris C. Chu (2007). Religiosity and Desistance From Drug Use. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 2007; 34; 661 originally published online Mar 7, 2007; DOI: 10.1177/0093854806293485</ref> with many studies establishing this beneficial connection (though some claim it is a modest one).<ref>
+
*Hume, D. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. In ''Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals''. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975. ISBN 0198245351.
For example:
+
*Hume, D. ''Treatise of Human Nature''.  Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978. ISBN 0198245874.
*Albrecht, S. I., Chadwick, B. A., & Alcorn, D. S. (1977). Religiosity and deviance:Application of an attitude-behavior contingent consistency model. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 16, 263-274.
+
*Kant, I. and Herbert James Paton. ''The Moral Law: Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals.'' London: Hutchinson, 1981. ISBN 009036032X.
*Burkett, S.,& White, M. (1974). Hellfire and delinquency:Another look. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion,13,455-462.
+
*MacIntyre, A. ''After Virtue''. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981. ISBN 026800594X.  
*Chard-Wierschem, D. (1998). In pursuit of the “true” relationship: A longitudinal study of the effects of religiosity on delinquency and substance abuse. Ann Arbor, MI: UMI Dissertation.
+
*Mill, J.S. ''Utilitarianism.'' IndyPublish.com, 2005. ISBN 1421928760.  
*Cochran, J. K.,& Akers, R. L. (1989). Beyond hellfire:An explanation of the variable effects of religiosity on adolescent marijuana and alcohol use. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 26, 198-225.
+
*Moore, G.E. ''Principia Ethica''. Cambridge University Press, 1903.
*Evans, T. D.,Cullen, F. T.,Burton, V. S.,Jr.,Dunaway, R. G.,Payne, G. L.,& Kethineni, S. R. (1996). Religion, social bonds, and delinquency. Deviant Behavior, 17, 43-70.
+
*Nietzsche, F. ''On the Genealogy of Morals.'' Edited by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books, 1989. ISBN 0679724621.
*Grasmick, H. G., Bursik, R. J., & Cochran, J. K. (1991). “Render unto Caesar what is Caesar’s”: Religiosity and taxpayer’s inclinations to cheat. The Sociological Quarterly, 32, 251-266.
+
*Rachels, James. ''The Elements of Moral Philosophy,'' 2nd edition. McGraw-Hill, Inc., 1993.
*Higgins, P. C., & Albrecht, G. L. (1977). Hellfire and delinquency revisited. Social Forces, 55, 952-958.
+
*Rawls, J. ''A Theory of Justice''. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971. ISBN 0674880102.
*Johnson, B. R.,Larson, D. B.,DeLi,S.,& Jang, S. J. (2000). Escaping from the crime of inner cities:Church attendance and religious salience among disadvantaged youth. Justice Quarterly, 17, 377-391.
+
*Sartre, Jean Paul. ''Existentialism is Humanism''. Trans by P. Mairet. London: Methuen, 1974. ISBN 041331300X.  
*Johnson, R. E., Marcos, A. C., & Bahr, S. J. (1987). The role of peers in the complex etiology of adolescent drug use. Criminology, 25, 323-340.
+
*Sidgwick, H. ''The Methods of Ethics''. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.
*Powell, K. (1997). Correlates of violent and nonviolent behavior among vulnerable inner-city youths. Family and Community Health, 20, 38-47.
+
*Williams, B. ''Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy''. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985. ISBN 0674268571.
</ref> Indeed, a meta-analysis of 60 studies on religion and crime concluded, “religious behaviors and beliefs exert a moderate deterrent effect on individuals’ criminal behavior”.<ref>Baier, C. J.,& Wright, B. R. (2001). “If you love me, keep my commandments”:A meta-analysis of the effect of religion on crime. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency,38,3-21.</ref>
 
 
 
== See also ==
 
* [[Ethics]]
 
* [[Secular ethics]]
 
* [[Mores]]
 
* [[Ethos]]
 
* [[Norms]]
 
* [[Moral relativism]]
 
* [[Moral absolutism]]
 
* [[Consequentialism]]
 
* [[Deontology]]
 
* [[Applied ethics]]
 
* [[Moral particularism]]
 
* [[Guilt]]
 
* [[Criticism of Atheism]]
 
* [[Criticism of Religion]]
 
* [[Conscience]]
 
* [[Kohlberg's stages of moral development]]
 
* [[Public morality]]
 
* [[The ends justify the means]]
 
* [[Moral Zeitgeist]]
 
 
 
==Footnotes==
 
<div class="references-small">
 
<!--See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Wikipedia:Footnotes for an explanation of how to generate footnotes using the <ref(erences/)> tags—>
 
<references/>
 
</div>
 
 
 
==Bibliography==
 
* Walker, Martin G. ''LIFE! Why We Exist...And What We Must Do to Survive'' ([http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/LIFE_Why_We_Exist...] Wiki Book Page) ([http://www.meaninginmylife.com] Web Site), Dog Ear Publishing, 2006, ISBN 1-59858-243-7
 
* Trompenaars, Fons. ''Did the Pedestrian Die?'' ISBN 1-84112-436-2
 
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
* [http://www.in-mind.org/artikelen/fairness-judgments-genuine-morality-or-disguised-egocentrism.html Fairness Judgments: Genuine Morality or Disguised Egoism?] Psychological Article on Fairness (registration required)
+
All links retrieved November 9, 2022.
* [http://selfhelpinspiration.com/article/morals_in_society.html Morals and Conscience in Society]
 
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/ The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy on the Definition of Morality]
 
* [http://www.percepp.com/morality.htm Objective Morality An evolutionary approach]
 
* [http://www.examinethetruth.com/page_morale_01.htm Christian and Muslim debates on Morality]
 
* [http://www.chabad.org/search/keyword.asp?kid=1222 Morality and Judaism] chabad.org
 
* [http://www.geeta-kavita.com/article.asp?article=biology_morals_dharma An article that focuses on the Biological basis of morality is available at Geeta-kavita.com]
 
* [http://www.worldmoralmovement.org Wiki site for discussing and taking action on shared morals (WorldMoralMovement.org)]
 
* [http://moralsandethics.wordpress.com/ Morals and Ethics in Islam]
 
* [http://www.examinethetruth.com/moralitydebate.htm Understanding the Islam, Christianity Debate]
 
* [http://www.libchrist.com/bible/howsexsin.html How Sex Was Made A Sin]                                                            {{Philosophy (navigation)}}
 
  
[[Category:Morality]]
+
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/ Morality] ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''.
[[Category:Ethics]]
+
* [https://www.chabad.org/search/keyword_cdo/kid/1222/jewish/Morality-Ethics-Values.htm Morality; Ethics; Values] ''Chabad.org''.
[[Category:Virtues]]
+
* [http://moralsandethics.wordpress.com/ Morals and Ethics in Islam].
 +
===General philosophy sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
 +
 +
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 +
[[Category:philosophy]]
  
[[sq:Morali]]
 
 
{{credits|Morality|169616904}}
 
{{credits|Morality|169616904}}

Latest revision as of 21:20, 9 November 2022

In its "everyday sense" morality (from Latin moralitas "manner, character, proper behavior") refers to a code of conduct, by which human beings regulate their lives. Theoretical interest in morality arises from the distinct sorts of questions that might be asked about this code of conduct.

One question asks the kinds of practical rules people actually use to govern their lives. This is a descriptive question, an attempt to understand the actual practices of various societies, groups of people, and individuals. The results of such an attempt will constitute the meaning of "morality" in a descriptive sense. Given that different groups of people adhere to different codes of conduct, there can be said to be more than one standard of morality.

A second question questions the validity of the codes of conduct by which people adhere to. This is the area of moral philosophy, which attempts to ascertain the rules that people ought to use in guidance of their conduct. (The rules identified by moral philosophy as prescribing how human beings should live need not coincide with actual practices and accepted moral principles.) The results of this inquiry will constitute the meaning of "morality" in its normative sense.

A third set of questions asks whether the practical rules that make up a kind of morality are objective, or whether they are simply expressions of our basic feelings of approval and disapproval; it asks whether they are universally valid, or relative to the groups who uphold them. Finally, it asks whether or not they depend on religion. This is the province of meta-ethics, which attempts to understand the nature of codes of correct behavior.

Descriptive morality

Morality in a descriptive sense may be defined as a code of conduct endorsed and adhered to by a society, group or—much less frequently—individual. Moral codes in this sense will, therefore, differ both from society to society, within societies, and amongst individuals. In its descriptive sense, morality is whatever a society, group, or individual, says it is. For example, descriptive "morality" may include norms of correct behavior according to which cannibalism and [rape]] are morally permissible. Nor is it the case that descriptive "moralities" must always be consistent in their application of moral rules (even within a culture). Historically speaking, different moral rules were held to apply to slaves and free men and women in societies in which slave owning was permitted.

In its descriptive sense, then, "morality" refers to the codes of conduct regulating how people behave, and without inquiring as to whether they ought to adhere to these codes. Descriptive morality is of central interest to anthropologists, historians, and sociologists. It is not a primary concern of philosophical inquiry except insofar as the results of research in the social sciences bear upon questions concerning the nature of morality.

Within the sphere of descriptive morality, a distinction between moral rules, legal rules, and norms of etiquette is recognized. Firstly, there is a high degree of overlap between morality and law. Many moral rules are also legal prohibitions or requirements. For example, murder is generally held to be both immoral and illegal. However, some moral rules do not correspond to legal rules, and so violating a moral code does not necessarily lead to judicial punishment. For example, one is not legally punished for lying in one’s personal life. Conversely, some legal rules do not correspond to moral rules. For example, a system of law contains many proscriptions and requirements regulating bureaucratic procedures, which do not pertain to morality. Even more fundamentally, legal violations are not necessarily moral violations. Unintentionally parking in a designated zone will not count as a moral wrong, although one may still be liable to legal sanction, such as a fine.

The distinction between moral rules and norms of etiquette is somewhat sharper than the difference between law and morality. In general, it seems that norms of etiquette (or custom) are of less importance than those of morality. It is polite to arrive on time for a dinner party, but one will not have violated a rule of morality by being late. Conversely, it does violence to one's language to say that one who has committed a robbery has broken the rules of etiquette. In some cases, however, this distinction is blurred. For example, in some places and cultural groups, it may be polite—a matter of etiquette, perhaps—for women to cover their legs while shading into a question of moral right and wrong in other groups.

Normative morality

In its normative sense, morality may be defined as a code of conduct that would be accepted by all rational people under certain idealized conditions. In simpler terms, "morality" is the set of correct moral principles, which, though they probably will never be universally adopted, ought to be adopted. Specifying the nature of such a system of morality is the province of moral philosophy, which seeks, firstly, to formulate a set of principles with which all rational agents ought to comply, and secondly, to explain why this system ought to be adopted. (Some philosophers argue that morality ought not to be characterized in terms of a set of principles at all.)

There is considerable philosophical disagreement as to what this universal system of morality would look like. "There are many rival theories, each expounding a different conception of [what morality is…] and what it means to live morally" (Rachels 1995, p. 1). There is therefore a sense in which the nature of morality itself hinges on these disagreements: the question “what is morality?” in its normative sense, cannot be answered until moral philosophy has resolved its disagreements. In what follows, therefore, the most important attempts define morality will be outlined. The conceptions of morality that currently dominate the philosophical terrain are consequentialism, deontology, and virtue ethics. Each of these come in various forms and will be briefly discussed.

Consequentialism

Consequentialism offers a general definition of morality in terms of the value of consequences brought about, but is independent of any account as to what consequences these may be. The most important version of consequentialism is utilitarianism.

According to classical utilitarian philosophers such as John Stuart Mill and Jeremy Bentham, morality is defined in terms of actions conforming to the principle of utility, the fundamental principle of morality. According to this principle, an action is moral (or right) if and only if it produces the greatest balance of overall happiness (or well being). By utilitarian standards then, acts of euthanasia may be considered morally right as insofar as it reduces overall suffering. This differs significantly from many religious moral codes, which maintain that actions such as taking another life (whether it be called murder, assisted suicide, or euthanasia) are never permissible.

Some of the main criticisms of the utilitarian account of morality—according to which all rational agents ought to follow the utilitarian principle—include the following. Firstly, it is almost impossible in many situations to weigh up overall good; secondly, that the theory does not properly accommodate justice and punishment; thirdly, that promise keeping and act utilitarianism are in conflict.

Deontological morality

Deontological ethics or deontology (Greek: δέον (deon) meaning obligation or duty) defines morality in terms of a system of moral rules. It is probably the moral theory closest to ordinary ways of moral thinking, or at least those adhered to by most Westerners, no doubt a result of the influence of Jewish law and Christianity on their moral thought. The system of morality articulated by the Ten Commandments is, for example, deontological in character.

The best-known and most important version of a philosophical deontology is Immanuel Kant’s theory. The fundamental principle of Kant’s deontology is the Categorical Imperative, which is said to underlie all commonly recognized moral principles. The Categorical Imperative is a principle of consistency, demanding that we act on reasons which all rational agents could endorse, that is, universally acceptable reasons. This is often compared to the biblical Golden Rule, “Do unto to others as you would have them do unto you”—although there are some important differences. For Kant then, a moral principal is one everyone could follow; if it were made into a universal law it would not be self-defeating.

One important feature of Kant’s conception of morality is that it is absolute. There are no exceptions to moral rules; it is always wrong to murder, tell a lie, or break a promise. One criticism of this view is that sometimes telling a lie could save a life so that it would be unreasonable and even immoral to tell the truth in such a situation.

Intuitionism

The best-known form of intuitionism is probably that presented by W.D. Ross in The Right and the Good. Ross argues that humans are able to intuit a number of irreducible prima facie duties (to keep promises, to refrain from harming the innocent, and so on), none of which take precedence over any other. In this respect, Ross accepts a form of moral pluralism, since he does not think that right action can be reduced to a single criterion. Here he sets himself up against Utilitarianism and Kantianism, which are both versions of monism because they recognize a single basic moral principle. Ross thinks that the right action (one’s duty proper) in a given situation is determined by a careful weighing of various moral principles that apply in the context. In other words, intuitionism does not claim that there is any one characteristic that all morally correct acts share.

One significant consequence of intuitionism is that it suggests that morality does not admit of a neat definition. Morality is itself a composite of competing requirements, which cannot be formally unified.

Virtue ethics

Virtue ethics was the dominant ethical tradition in ancient Greek philosophy and through the Middle Ages. It has once again risen to prominence in recent times to become one of the three major normative strands (along with deontology and consequentialism).

Virtue ethics downplays, or even denies, the existence of universal rules to which actions must conform. Consequently, it sometimes locates itself in opposition to the notion of morality per se, which is identified as systems of rules or categorical imperatives. Insofar as ethics is understood as a broader domain in which questions about correct living are posed, virtue ethics may be understood as offering a criticism of morality itself.

According to virtue ethics, ethics is not fundamentally about duties or following rules (deontology) or about consequences of actions (consequentialism), but rather about cultivating virtuous dispositions of character, a moral character. A disposition is a tendency to have certain responses in particular situations: responses such as emotions, perceptions, and actions. The virtuous person is someone who acts rightly in response to requirements that are unique to the situation. He or she is someone who is able to perceive what the situation requires and act accordingly by exercising practical wisdom (phronesis). Virtuous habits and behavior (arête) will be those that ultimately lead to the "good life" (or eudaimonia).

Morality and philosophical method

If moral theories disagree in fundamental ways about the very nature of morality, as they do, then how should one proceed to adjudicate between these views? What sorts of outcomes are possible for moral philosophy? Can morality in the normative sense be defined after all? These are questions of philosophical method.

The most widely held view about possibility for reaching philosophical agreement on the nature of morality depends on the notion of reflective equilibrium. In explanation, consider, firstly, that there seems to be (significant) overlap in the kinds of things that most people regard as right and wrong. For example, most people, and most societies, regard the killing of innocent people as morally wrong. Call this moral system "shared morality" (or pre-rational morality). "Shared morality" is, for the most part, a system of moral rules that sets limits to one's conduct (for example, thou shall not to murder or steal). "Shared morality" can also incorporate acts that people are not required to do but would be morally significant if one did do them, such as act of charity. Actions that are morally admirable to do but not strictly required, are called supererogatory actions.

The conflict between the prescriptions of a moral theory and our common ways of thinking raises a question about how moral theories are to be evaluated. If a moral theory conflicts with our commonsense, pre-reflective morality, it could be that the theory is wrong or one's moral convictions are wrong. The most sensible approach seems to be trying to find a reflective equilibrium between one's moral theories and one's intuitive judgments of moral rightness and wrongness. The strategy is to anchor one's moral theories in some of one's most deeply rooted judgments. Intuitions regarding murder, theft, and rape are perhaps so central that if a theory does not accommodate the point that (for example) rape is always wrong, this is a deficiency of the theory. However, part of the point of moral theorizing is to gain a better understanding of the properties of actions that make them right and wrong. Once a theory is justified by a significant number of deep intuitions, one may refine our moral judgments based on insights gained from the theory. Once this has been achieved it can be said that one's morality has been internalized (as opposed to being shaped from outside influences such as family and society) and that a shift has occurred from pre-"rational" or "group" morality to "rational" or "reflective" morality.

Morality and ethics

What is the relation between morality and ethics? Many philosophers hold that there is no substantial difference between the two concepts, and use the terms "ethics" and "moral philosophy" interchangeably.

There is, however, another group, who place a great emphasis on maintaining a distinction. Indeed, philosophers such as Nietzsche, Bernard Williams and Elizabeth Anscombe, may be understood as arguing that "morality," or the "morality system" is an out-moded and indeed pernicious component of ethics. The contrast is drawn between morality as system of absolute rules or moral obligations, such as those issued in the Ten Commandments, and reaching its philosophical apotheosis in Kant's theory, and other more promising notions pertaining to how to live a maximally happy life (typically associated with virtue).

Nietzsche’s criticism of "morality" revolves around his notion of slave morality. Slave morality, which corresponds closely to Judeo-Christian morality, with its focus on duty and self-sacrifice, originates in the resentment of the weak and oppressed. Slave morality is a subversion of master morality—the natural states of the strong—in which noble and life affirming values have been transformed in vices, and the contrary, slavish and life-negating values, transformed in values. Slave morality is the outcome of weak people’s coming to regard the qualities of the naturally strong as evil, and transforming their own resentment into current conceptions of morality, which have greatly debilitated human life. Nietzsche may, it seems, be interpreted as saying that morality—understood as slave morality—is life negating and should be abolished.

Similarly, in an article, “Modern Moral Philosophy,” Elizabeth Anscombe argues that duty based conceptions of morality are conceptually incoherent, for they are based on the idea of a "law without a lawgiver." The point is that a system of morality conceived along the lines of the Ten Commandments, as a system of rules for action, depends (she claims) on someone having actually made these rules. However, in a modern climate, which is unwilling to accept that morality depends on God in this way, the rule-based conception of morality is stripped of its metaphysical foundation. Anscombe recommends a return the eudaimonistic ethical theories of the ancients, particularly Aristotle, which ground morality in the interests and well being of human moral agents, and can do so without appealing to any questionable metaphysics. Again, Anscombe’s point may be understood in terms of the abolition of morality and the return to ethics.

Morality and Meta-ethics

Unlike the normative theories discussed above, meta-ethics does not propound any moral principles or goals, but is involved entirely in philosophical analysis. It is concerned with the nature of judgments of right and wrong, as well as with defining ethical terms, such as value terms such as "good" and "bad." In other words, metaethics attempts to answer epistemological, logical, and semantic questions relating to ethics. In the Anglophone world, twentieth century philosophers have focused tremendously on meta-ethics rather than normative ethics.

Moral relativism

As discussed initially under descriptive morality, morality in the sense of actual codes of conduct may be specific to societies, groups, or individual. Some philosophers conclude from this apparent fact of cultural disagreement that moral rules are nothing other than social conventions of particular cultural groups. This entails that the judgment, for example, that lying is always wrong is simply an expression of the beliefs of a group of people, and it is their beliefs about the matter that make it true. This view is called moral relativism. According to moral relativism, there is no objective and universally valid moral principles. Morality itself is nothing but a matter of convention.

Emotivism and prescriptivism

Emotivism, which is first articulated in the work of David Hume, but is developed to a greater degree of sophistication by writers such as A.J. Ayer and C.L. Stevenson, holds that evaluations express the speaker’s feelings and attitudes: Saying that kindness is good is a way of expressing one’s approval of kindness. Therefore, moral judgments are not objective and do not state any sort of morally truths; rather they are simply expressions of emotions. Similarly, R.M. Hare argues that evaluations (moral judgments) are prescriptions (commands): Saying that kindness is good is a way of telling people that they should be kind. Moral evaluative judgments are then understood as emotive or prescriptive, and are contrasted with descriptive judgments. Descriptive judgments are appraisable as true or false whereas evaluative judgments are not.

Moral skepticism

Moral skepticism is the view that humans have no moral knowledge. Extreme moral skeptics have claimed that all moral beliefs are false, a view which is known as moral nihilism. Nihilists such as J.L. Mackie argue that moral claims are false because they implicitly presuppose objective values which do not exist. Other skeptics take a less extreme position adopting a line of argument that builds on moral relativism by claiming that outside cultural influences are so strong that there is no way one can ever objectively assess morality, and that this inevitable bias makes moral beliefs unjustifiable. Arguing from the other direction are skeptics such as Richard Joyce, who argue that it is not outside or cultural influences that make moral claims unjustifiable, but rather the fact that morality is so internalized that makes objective moral truths impossible. Joyce argues that mankind has evolved to hold moral beliefs and we would hold them regardless of whether they are right or wrong, this is known as the argument from evolution.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. Modern Moral Philosophy. In Philosophy 33, 1958.
  • Aristotle and Martin Oswald. The Nichomachean Ethics. New York: The Bobs-Merrill Company, 1962.
  • Aquinas, T. and T. Gilby. Summa theologiae. London: Eyre & Spottiswoode, 1963.
  • Bentham, J. and Laurence J Lafleur. An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. New York: Hafner Pub. Co., 1948.
  • DeMarco, Joseph P. Moral Theory: A Contemporary Overview. Boston: Jones & Bartlett Publishers, 1996. ISBN 978-0867209549
  • Feldman, F. Introductory Ethics. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1978. ISBN 978-0135017838
  • Frankena, William K. Ethics, 2nd edition. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, Inc., 1973. ASIN B002EB8QO0
  • Hegel, G.W.F. Philosophy of Right. Trans. Knox. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1942.
  • Hobbes, T. Leviathan. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998. ISBN 0585193282.
  • Hume, D. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. In Enquiries Concerning Human Understanding and Concerning the Principles of Morals. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975. ISBN 0198245351.
  • Hume, D. Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978. ISBN 0198245874.
  • Kant, I. and Herbert James Paton. The Moral Law: Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. London: Hutchinson, 1981. ISBN 009036032X.
  • MacIntyre, A. After Virtue. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 1981. ISBN 026800594X.
  • Mill, J.S. Utilitarianism. IndyPublish.com, 2005. ISBN 1421928760.
  • Moore, G.E. Principia Ethica. Cambridge University Press, 1903.
  • Nietzsche, F. On the Genealogy of Morals. Edited by Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books, 1989. ISBN 0679724621.
  • Rachels, James. The Elements of Moral Philosophy, 2nd edition. McGraw-Hill, Inc., 1993.
  • Rawls, J. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1971. ISBN 0674880102.
  • Sartre, Jean Paul. Existentialism is Humanism. Trans by P. Mairet. London: Methuen, 1974. ISBN 041331300X.
  • Sidgwick, H. The Methods of Ethics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962.
  • Williams, B. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1985. ISBN 0674268571.

External links

All links retrieved November 9, 2022.

General philosophy sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.