Mill, John Stuart

From New World Encyclopedia
(re-importing the lastest version from wiki)
 
(27 intermediate revisions by 11 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
{{Ebcompleted}}{{2Copyedited}}{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Copyedited}}
 +
{{epname|Mill, John Stuart}}
 
{{Infobox_Philosopher |
 
{{Infobox_Philosopher |
 
   <!-- Scroll down to edit this page —>
 
   <!-- Scroll down to edit this page —>
 
   <!-- Philosopher Category —>
 
   <!-- Philosopher Category —>
 
   region          = Western Philosophy |
 
   region          = Western Philosophy |
   era            = [[19th-century philosophy]] |
+
   era            = Nineteenth-century philosophy |
 
   color          = #B0C4DE |
 
   color          = #B0C4DE |
  
Line 12: Line 14:
 
   <!-- Information —>
 
   <!-- Information —>
 
   name            = John Stuart Mill |
 
   name            = John Stuart Mill |
   birth            = [[May 20]], [[1806]] ([[Pentonville]], [[London]], [[England]]) |
+
   birth            = May 20, 1806 (Pentonville, [[London]], [[England]]) |
   death            = [[May 8]], [[1873]] ([[Avignon]], [[France]]) |
+
   death            = May 8, 1873 (Avignon, [[France]]) |
 
   school_tradition = [[Empiricism]], [[Utilitarianism]] |
 
   school_tradition = [[Empiricism]], [[Utilitarianism]] |
   main_interests  = [[Political philosophy]], [[Ethics]], [[Economics]], [[Inductive reasoning|Inductive Logic]] |
+
   main_interests  = [[Political philosophy]], [[Ethics]], [[Economics]], [[Logic|Inductive Logic]] |
 
   influences      = [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas]], [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]], [[Adam Smith|Smith]], [[David Ricardo|Ricardo]], [[Alexis de Tocqueville|Tocqueville]], [[James Mill]], [[Claude Henri de Rouvroy, comte de Saint-Simon|Saint-Simon]] ([[Utopian socialism|Utopian Socialists)]]<ref>{{cite journal|author=[[Friedrich Hayek]]|title=The Counter-Revolution of Science|year=1941|journal=Economica|volume=8|issue=31|pages=281-320|doi=10.2307/2549335}}</ref> |
 
   influences      = [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas]], [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]], [[Adam Smith|Smith]], [[David Ricardo|Ricardo]], [[Alexis de Tocqueville|Tocqueville]], [[James Mill]], [[Claude Henri de Rouvroy, comte de Saint-Simon|Saint-Simon]] ([[Utopian socialism|Utopian Socialists)]]<ref>{{cite journal|author=[[Friedrich Hayek]]|title=The Counter-Revolution of Science|year=1941|journal=Economica|volume=8|issue=31|pages=281-320|doi=10.2307/2549335}}</ref> |
 
   influenced      = Many philosophers after him, including [[John Rawls]], [[Robert Nozick]], [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Karl Popper]], [[Ronald Dworkin]], [[H.L.A. Hart]], [[Peter Singer]] |
 
   influenced      = Many philosophers after him, including [[John Rawls]], [[Robert Nozick]], [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Karl Popper]], [[Ronald Dworkin]], [[H.L.A. Hart]], [[Peter Singer]] |
Line 21: Line 23:
 
}}
 
}}
  
'''John Stuart Mill''' ([[May 20]], [[1806]] &ndash; [[May 8]], [[1873]]), an [[England|English]] [[philosopher]] and [[political economy|political economist]], was an influential [[liberalism|liberal]] thinker of the [[19th century]]. He was an advocate of [[utilitarianism]], the ethical theory that was systemised by his godfather, [[Jeremy Bentham]], but adapted to [[German romanticism]]. It is usually suggested that Mill is an advocate of [[Negative liberty]]. However, this has been contested by many academics, notably Dr. David Walker of [[Newcastle University]] in England.
+
'''John Stuart Mill''' (May 20, 1806 - May 8, 1873), an [[United Kingdom|English]] [[philosopher]] and [[political economy|political economist]], was an influential [[liberalism|liberal]] thinker of the nineteenth century. John Stuart Mill refined and developed [[utilitarianism]], which was originally formulated by [[Jeremy Bentham]] (1748-1832), his godfather and a close friend of his father [[James Mill]]. John Stewart Mill worked for most of his life in the examiner’s office of the [[British East India Company]], while producing a number of books and essays, many of which were published in ''Westminster Review, The Examiner, Tait’s Magazine, The London Review, The Jurist,'' and ''The Monthly Repository.'' He remains of lasting interest as an ethicist, a social political thinker, and a logician.  
 +
{{toc}}
 +
Mill formulated the “greatest happiness principle,” which held that one must always act so as to produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people, and distinguished among the quality of different types of happiness. As a logician, in ''A System of Logic,'' Mill describes the five basic principles of induction which have come to be known as "Mill's Methods." Among his most well-known and significant works are ''A System of Logic, Principles of Political Economy, On Liberty, Utilitarianism, The Subjection of Women, Three Essays on Religion,'' and his ''Autobiography.'' Mill's ''On Liberty'' emphasized that freedom was not determined by majority rule alone. A free society had the responsibility to protect and guarantee the right of the minority to hold and propagate its views and thus possibly eventually become the majority view within society.  
  
== Biography ==
+
== Life ==
John Stuart Mill was born in [[Pentonville]], [[London]], the oldest son of the [[Scotland|Scottish]] philosopher and historian [[James Mill]]. John Stuart was educated by his father, with the advice and assistance of [[Jeremy Bentham]] and [[Francis Place]]. He was given an extremely rigorous, some would say harsh, upbringing, and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings. His father, a follower of [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]] and an adherent of [[associationism]], had as his explicit aim to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of [[utilitarianism]] and its implementation after he and Bentham were dead.
+
John Stuart Mill was born May 20, 1806 in Pentonville, [[London]], the oldest son of the [[Scotland|Scottish]] philosopher and historian [[James Mill]]. John Stuart Mill was given an extremely rigorous upbringing, and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings. He was educated exclusively by his father, a strict disciplinarian, with the advice of [[Jeremy Bentham]] and [[Francis Place]]. His father, a follower of Bentham and an adherent of [[associationism]], wanted to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of [[utilitarianism]] and its implementation after he and Bentham were dead. John Stuart's feats as a child were exceptional; at the age of three he was taught the [[Greek alphabet]] and long lists of Greek words with their English equivalents. By the age of eight he had read [[Aesop|Aesop's]] ''Fables,'' [[Xenophon]]'s ''Anabasis,'' and the whole of [[Herodotus]], and was acquainted with [[Lucian]], [[Diogenes Laertius|Diogenes Laërtius]], Isocrates and six dialogues of [[Plato]] (see his ''Autobiography''). He had also read a great deal of history in [[English]] and had been taught [[arithmetic]].
  
John Stuart's feats as a child were exceptional; at the age of three he was taught the [[Greek alphabet]] and long lists of Greek words with their English equivalents. By the age of eight he had read [[Aesop|Aesop's]] ''[[Aesop's Fables|Fables]]'', [[Xenophon]]'s ''[[Anabasis (Xenophon)|Anabasis]],'' and the whole of [[Herodotus]], and was acquainted with [[Lucian]], [[Diogenes Laërtius]], [[Isocrates]] and six dialogues of [[Plato]] (see his Autobiography). He had also read a great deal of history in English and had been taught [[arithmetic]].
+
A contemporary record of Mill's studies from ages eight to thirteen, published in [[Alexander Bain|Bain]]'s sketch of his life, suggests that his autobiography understated the amount of work he did as a child. At the age of eight he began learning [[Latin]], [[Euclid]], and [[algebra]], and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family. His main reading was still history, but he went through all the Latin and [[Greek language|Greek]] authors commonly read in the schools and universities at the time. He was not taught to compose either in Latin or in Greek, and he was never an exact scholar; he was required to read  for the subject matter, and by the age of ten he could read [[Plato]] and [[Demosthenes]] with ease. His father's ''History of India'' was published in 1818; immediately afterwards, at about the age of 12, John began a thorough study of [[scholastic]] [[logic]], at the same time reading [[Aristotle]]'s logical treatises in the original language. In the following year he was introduced to [[political economy]] and studied [[Adam Smith]] and [[David Ricardo]] with his father, ultimately completing their [[Classical economics|classical economic view]] of [[factors of production]]. Mill’s childhood was not unhappy, but he suffered from the lack of natural, unforced development and his mental health and state of mind were affected.
  
A contemporary record of Mill's studies from eight to thirteen is published in [[Alexander Bain|Bain]]'s sketch of his life. It suggests that his autobiography rather understates the amount of work done. At the age of eight he began learning [[Latin]], [[Euclid]], and [[algebra]], and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family. His main reading was still history, but he went through all the Latin and [[Greek language|Greek]] authors commonly read in the schools and universities at the time. He was not taught to compose either in Latin or in Greek, and he was never an exact scholar; it was for the subject matter that he was required to read, and by the age of ten he could read [[Plato]] and [[Demosthenes]] with ease. His father's ''History of India'' was published in 1818; immediately thereafter, about the age of twelve, John began a thorough study of the [[scholastic]] [[logic]], at the same time reading [[Aristotle]]'s logical treatises in the original language. In the following year he was introduced to [[political economy]] and studied [[Adam Smith]] and [[David Ricardo]] with his father—ultimately completing their [[Classical economics|classical economic view]] of [[factors of production]].
+
===In France===
 +
Mill spent the period from May 1820 until July 1821 in France with the family of Sir Samuel Bentham, the brother of the English [[utilitarianism|Utilitarian]] philosopher [[Jeremy Bentham]]. Extracts from his diary at that time show that he studied [[chemistry]], [[botany]], and advanced [[mathematics]]; methodically read and wrote; and made notes on the scenery and the customs of the [[France|French]] people, while becoming fluent in French. On his return to [[England]] in 1821, Mill refused to study at [[Oxford University]] or [[University of Cambridge|Cambridge University]], because he refused to take [[Church of England|Anglican]] orders, a requirement at that time.<ref name="bio">Nicholas Capaldi. ''John Stuart Mill: A Biography.'' (Cambridge, 2004, ISBN 0521620244), 33.</ref> Instead he studied [[psychology]] and began to read [[ancient Rome|Roman]] law with [[John Austin]]; his father was preparing him for a career in law. In 1823, however, at the age of eighteen, he entered the examiner’s office of the India House. In 1828 he was promoted to assistant examiner, and after his father’s death in 1836, he was put in charge of the [[British East India Company|British East India Company]]’s relations with the Indian states. He carried this responsibility for 20 years, and in 1856 became chief of the examiner’s office.  
  
This intensive study however had injurious effects on Mill's mental health, and state of mind.  At the age of 21 he suffered a [[nervous breakdown]]; as explained in chapter V of his ''Autobiography'', this was caused by the great physical and mental arduousness of his studies which had suppressed any [[feeling]]s he might have developed normally in childhood. Nevertheless, this depression eventually began to dissipate, as he began to find solace in the poetry of [[William Wordsworth]]. His capacity for emotion resurfaced, Mill remarking that the "cloud gradually drew off".
+
Mill was an outspoken critic of the flaws which he perceived in Parliament and in the British legal system. He became a contributor to the ''Westminster Review,'' founded in April, 1824, as the organ of the philosophical radicals. In 1825 he began work on Bentham’s ''Rationale of Judicial Evidence'' (1827). He enjoyed discussions with the intellectuals  who visited his father’s house, and participated in a reading society which began meeting at the home of the English historian [[George Grote]] in 1825. The same year he joined the London Debating Society, where he began to question the values with which he had been brought up. His father had had little use for poetry, friendship and private emotions; John Stuart Mill began to change his views and to have a more moderate and practical approach to political ideals and the meaning of human happiness. He came to believe that the purpose of a political philosophy was not to define ideal political institutions and or the ideal structure of society, but to define ideal political principles which could be used to construct institutions appropriate to the many different circumstances of the real world.  
  
Mill refused to study at [[Oxford University]] or [[University of Cambridge|Cambridge University]], because he refused to take [[Anglican]] orders.<ref name="bio">Capaldi, Nicholas. ''John Stuart Mill: A Biography.'' p.33, Cambridge, 2004, ISBN 0-521-62024-4.</ref> Instead he followed his father to work for the [[British East India Company]] until 1858. Between the years 1865-1868 he served as Lord Rector of the [[University of St. Andrews]], where he gave an inaugural speech on the value of Culture.
+
At the age of 21 Mill suffered a [[nervous breakdown]]; as he explained in chapter V of his ''Autobiography,'' this was caused by the great physical and mental arduousness of his studies which had suppressed any feelings he might have developed normally in childhood. This depression eventually began to dissipate, and he began to find solace in the poetry of [[William Wordsworth]]. His capacity for emotion resurfaced, Mill remarking that the "cloud gradually drew off." Letters published by Mill in ''The Examiner'' during the autumn of 1830, just after he met some young political liberals in [[Paris]], indicated that he had regained some optimism. In 1831 ''The Examiner'' published a series of articles by Mill on The ''Spirit of the Age,'' and during 1832 and 1833 he contributed essays to ''Tait’s Magazine, The Jurist,'' and ''The Monthly Repository.'' In 1835 he was made editor of ''The London Review'' when it was founded by Sir William Molesworth, and he continued as editor when it was combined with ''The Westminster'' into ''The London and Westminster Review,'' until 1840. After 1840, he published several articles in the ''Edinburgh Review.''
 
+
   
During the same period, 1865-8, he was an independent [[Member of Parliament]], representing the City and Westminster constituency from 1865 to 1868. <ref name="bi2o">Ibid. p.321-322</ref> During his time as an MP, Mill advocated easing the burdens on [[Ireland]], and became the first person in parliament to call for women to be given the right to vote. In ''Considerations on Representative Government'', Mill called for various reforms of Parliament and voting, especially [[proportional representation]], the [[Single Transferable Vote]], and the extension of [[suffrage]].  He was godfather to [[Bertrand Russell]].
+
In 1843, John Stuart Mill published the first edition of ''A System of Logic,'' an attempt to formulate the methods of scientific investigation and to amalgate old and new forms of logic. Mill himself distinguished three stages in his development as a political economist. In ''Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy,'' five essays proposing solutions to problems of economics published in 1844, he appeared to follow [[David Ricardo]], striving for precision and exploring future consequences. His ''Principles of Political Economy,'' published in two volumes in 1848, 1849, and 1852, showed more originality and independent thought, proposing the creation of peasant proprietorships as a solution for the poverty and social disorder in Ireland.  
  
 +
===Social concern===
 +
In his third stage, he became increasingly interested in social problems rather than political problems, no longer regarding property ownership as sacred and recognizing that the changing structure of society required new methods of economic organization in order to ensure a tolerable life for the working classes. He claimed that he was influenced in this direction by his wife, Harriet Taylor Mill, whom he married in 1851 after a friendship of 21 years. Brilliant in her own right, Taylor was a significant influence on Mill's work and ideas during both their friendship and marriage. She reinforced Mill's advocacy of [[women's rights]]. He cited her influence in his final revision of ''On Liberty,'' which was published shortly after her death, and she appeared to be obliquely referenced in ''The Subjection of Women.'' 
 
[[Image:Taylor-harriet.jpg|left|frame|Harriet Taylor]]
 
[[Image:Taylor-harriet.jpg|left|frame|Harriet Taylor]]
  
In 1851, Mill married [[Harriet Taylor Mill|Harriet Taylor]] after 21 years of an intimate friendship. Taylor was married when they met, and their relationship was close but chaste during the years before her first husband died. Brilliant in her own right, Taylor was a significant influence on Mill's work and ideas during both friendship and marriage. His relationship with Harriet Taylor reinforced Mill's advocacy of [[Womens' rights|women's rights]]. He cites her influence in his final revision of ''On Liberty'', which was published shortly after her death, and she appears to be obliquely referenced in ''[[The Subjection of Women]]''.  Taylor died in 1858 after developing severe [[lung]] congestion, only seven years into her marriage to Mill.
+
During the seven years of his marriage, Mill was fully occupied with his work in the British East India Company. He became head of the examiner’s office in 1856 and served until the [[British East India Company]] was dissolved and its powers transferred to the government of Britain. Mill opposed this move, and as head of the office it was his responsibility to write the defense of the British East India Company’s government of [[India]]. He was offered a position on the new governing council, but took retirement instead. Shortly afterwards, Harriet Taylor Mill died in Avignon in 1858 after developing severe [[lung]] congestion. Mill spent the rest of his life mostly at a villa in Saint-Véran, near Avignon, returning to England only for a short period in each year. He published a series of books and essays on politics and ethics, including ''On Liberty'' (1859), ''Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform'' (1859), ''Considerations on Representative Government'' (1861), and ''Utilitarianism'' (in ''''Fraser's Magazine'''', 1861; separate publication, 1863). In 1865 he published two philosophical works, ''Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy'' and ''Auguste Comte and Positivism,'' and in 1869 he republished his father's ''Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind'' with additional illustrations and explanatory notes.  
 
 
He died in [[Avignon]], [[France]] in [[1873]], and is buried alongside his wife.
 
 
 
==Works==
 
===Theory of liberty===
 
  
Mill's ''[[On Liberty]]'' is one of the founding texts of [[liberalism]] and one of the most important treatises ever written on the concept of liberty. The book explores the nature and limits of the power that can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual. One argument that Mill develops further than any previous philosopher is the [[harm principle]]. The harm principle holds that each individual has the right to act as he wants, so long as these actions do not harm others. If the action is self-regarding, that is, if it only directly affects the person undertaking the action, then society has no right to intervene, even if it feels the actor is harming himself. Mill excuses those who are "incapable of self-government" from this principle, such as young children or those living in “backward states of society". It is important to emphasise that Mill did not consider giving offence to constitute “harm”; an action could not be restricted because it violated the conventions or morals of a given society.  
+
Mill remained engaged in politics. He supported the North in the [[United States Civil War]], making it clear that the real issue behind the war was abolition of [[slavery]]. In 1865 he ran for election as the parliamentary candidate for Westminster. <ref name="bi2o">Capaldi, 321-322</ref> According to his principles, he did no campaigning, but was elected. He was instrumental in shaping the 1867 ''Reform Bill'' to prevent certain corrupt practices, and argued for the reform of land tenure in [[Ireland]] (see his ''England and Ireland,'' 1868, and his ''Chapters and Speeches on the Irish Land Question,'' 1870), women’s suffrage, the reduction of the national debt, the reform of [[London]] government, and the abrogation of the Declaration of Paris (1856), concerning the carriage of property at sea during the [[Crimean War]]. He also advocated England's duty to intervene in foreign politics in support of freedom. In ''Considerations on Representative Government,'' Mill called for various reforms of Parliament and voting, especially [[proportional representation]], the [[Single Transferable Vote]], and the extension of [[suffrage]]. His advocacy of reform made him unpopular with “moderate Liberals” and he lost the general parliamentary election in 1868. Between the years 1865-1868 he served as Lord Rector of the [[University of Saint Andrews]], where he gave an inaugural speech on the value of culture.
  
''On Liberty'' involves an impassioned defence of free speech. Mill argues that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress. We can never be sure, he contends, if a silenced opinion does not contain some element of the truth. He also argues that allowing people to air false opinions is productive for two reasons. First, individuals are more likely to abandon erroneous beliefs if they are engaged in an open exchange of ideas. Second, by forcing other individuals to re-examine and re-affirm their beliefs in the process of debate, these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma. It is not enough for Mill that one simply has an unexamined belief that happens to be true; one must understand why the belief in question is the true one.  
+
Mill retired to Avignon, but continued his writing, publishing essays on endowments, on land, on labor, and on metaphysical and psychological questions in the ''Fortnightly Review'' (compiled in the fourth volume of his ''Dissertations,'' 1875). In 1867 he had helped to found the first [[women's suffrage]] society, later the National Union of Women's Suffrage Societies, and in 1869 he published ''The Subjection of Women'' (written 1861), the classical theoretical statement of the case for woman suffrage. His last public activity was involvement with the starting of the Land Tenure Reform Association, for which he wrote in ''The Examiner'' and made a public speech a few months before his death. Mill was also an enthusiastic botanist and frequently contributed papers and short articles to the ''Phytologist.'' He was godfather to [[Bertrand Russell]].
  
Mill's statement of the harm principle in Chapter 1 of ''On Liberty'' — "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not sufficient warrant" — seems clear, but in fact entails a number of complications. For example, Mill explicitly states that “harms” may include acts of omission as well as acts of commission. Thus, failing to rescue a drowning child counts as a harmful act, as does failing to pay taxes, or failing to appear as a witness in court. All such harmful omissions may be regulated, according to Mill. By contrast, it does not count as harming someone if (without force or fraud) the affected individual consents to assume the risk: thus one may permissibly offer unsafe employment to others, provided there is no deception involved. (Mill does, however, recognise one limit to consent: society should not permit people to sell themselves into slavery). In these and other cases, it is important to keep in mind that the arguments in ''On Liberty'' are grounded on the principle of Utility, and not on appeals to [[natural rights]]. The question of what counts as a self-regarding action and what actions, whether of omission or commission, constitute harmful actions subject to regulation, continues to exercise interpreters of Mill.
+
John Stuart Mill died at Avignon, France, on May 8, 1873 and was buried alongside his wife. His ''Autobiography'' and ''Three Essays on Religion'' (1874) were published posthumously.
  
Mill is also famous for being one of the earliest and strongest supporters of women's liberation. His book ''[[The Subjection of Women]]'' is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author.  He felt that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times, a set of prejudices that severely impeded the progress of humanity.
+
A bronze statue of Mill stands on the Thames embankment in [[London]], and G.F. Watts's copy of his original portrait of Mill hangs in the National Gallery there.
  
===Utilitarianism===
+
==Theory of Liberty==
 +
Mill's ''On Liberty,'' a founding text of [[liberalism]] and one of the most important treatises ever written on the concept of liberty, explored the nature and limits of the power that can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual. Mill developed further than any previous philosopher the concept of the “harm principle,” which holds that each individual has the right to act as he wants, so long as these actions do not harm others. If an action is self-regarding, that is, if it only directly affects the person undertaking the action, then society has no right to intervene, even if it feels the actor is harming himself. Mill excused those who are "incapable of self-government" from this principle, such as young children or those living in “backward states of society." It is important to emphasize that Mill did not consider that giving offence to someone constituted “harm;” an action could not be restricted because it violated the conventions or morals of a given society.
  
The canonical statement of Mill's Utilitarianism can be found in ''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]].''  This philosophy has a long tradition, arguably beginning, albeit in different forms, with [[Aristotle]], although Mill's account is primarily influenced by [[Jeremy Bentham]], and Mill's father [[James Mill]]. Mill’s famous formulation of Utilitarianism is known as the “greatest happiness principle.” It holds that one must always act so as to produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people. One of Mill's major contributions to Utilitarianism is his argument for the qualitative separation of pleasures. Bentham treats all forms of happiness as equal, whereas Mill argues that intellectual and moral pleasures are superior to more physical forms of pleasure. Mill distinguishes between "happiness" and "contentment," claiming that the former is of higher value than the latter, a belief wittily encapsulated in his statement that it is better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.
+
''On Liberty'' included an impassioned defense of free speech. Mill argued that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress. We can never be sure, he contended, if a silenced opinion does not contain some element of the truth. He also argued that allowing people to air false opinions is productive for two reasons. Individuals are more likely to abandon erroneous beliefs if they are engaged in an open exchange of ideas. By forcing other individuals to re-examine and re-affirm their beliefs in the process of debate, these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma. It was not enough for Mill that one simply has an unexamined belief that happens to be true; one must understand why the belief in question is the true one.  
  
The qualitative account of happiness Mill advocates thus sheds light on his account presented in ''On Liberty''. As Mill suggests in that text, utility is to be conceived in relation to mankind "as a progressive being," which includes the development and exercise of our rational capacities as we strive to achieve a “higher mode of existence". Thus the rejection of censorship and paternalism is intended to provide the necessary social conditions for the achievement of knowledge and the greatest ability for the greatest number to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities.  
+
Mill's statement of the "harm principle" in Chapter 1 of ''On Liberty,'' "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not sufficient warrant," entails a number of complications. For example, Mill explicitly stated that “harms” may include acts of omission as well as acts of commission. Thus, failing to rescue a drowning child counts as a harmful act, as does failing to pay taxes, or failing to appear as a witness in court. All such harmful omissions may be regulated, according to Mill. By contrast, it does not count as harming someone if (without force or [[fraud]]) the affected individual consents to assume the risk; one may permissibly offer unsafe employment to others, provided there is no deception involved. (Mill does, however, recognize one limit to consent: society should not permit people to sell themselves into [[slavery]]). In these and other cases, it is important to keep in mind that the arguments in ''On Liberty'' are grounded on the principle of Utility, and not on appeals to [[natural rights]]. The question of what counts as a self-regarding action and what actions, whether of omission or commission, constitute harmful actions subject to regulation, is still under debate.  
  
===Economic philosophy===
+
Mill was an early and strong supporter of women's rights. His book ''The Subjection of Women'' is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author. He felt that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times, a set of prejudices that severely impeded the progress of humanity.
  
Mill's early economic philosophy was one of [[free market]]s. However, he accepted interventions in the economy, such as a tax on alcohol, if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds. He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare. [http://www.ifaw.org/ifaw/dfiles/file_285.pdf] Mill believed that "equality of taxation" meant "equality of sacrifice" and that [[progressive tax]]ation penalised those who worked harder and saved more and was therefore "a mild form of robbery".[http://www.irefeurope.org/col_docs/doc_51_fr.pdf]
+
==Utilitarianism==
 +
The canonical statement of Mill's [[Utilitarianism]] can be found in ''Utilitarianism,'' written to defend his ethical system. The concept of the greatest good for the greatest number goes back to [[Aristotle]]; Mill's account is primarily influenced by [[Jeremy Bentham]], and Mill's father [[James Mill]]. Mill’s famous formulation of Utilitarianism is known as the “greatest happiness principle.” It holds that one must always act so as to produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people. One of Mill's major contributions to Utilitarianism was his argument for the qualitative separation of pleasures. Bentham treated all forms of happiness as equal, whereas Mill argued that intellectual and moral pleasures are superior to more physical forms of pleasure. Mill distinguishes between "happiness" and "contentment," claiming that the former is of higher value than the latter, a belief wittily encapsulated in his statement that it is “better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.” Mill included in his definition of “utility” the pleasures of the imagination and the gratification of the higher emotions.  
  
Mill's ''Principles of Political Economy'', first published in 1848, was one of the most widely read of all books on economics in the period.<ref>{{cite book
+
In ''On Liberty,'' Mill suggests that utility is to be conceived in relation to man as "a progressive being," whose rational capacities are constantly being developed and exercised as he strives to achieve a “higher mode of existence." His rejection of censorship and paternalism is intended to create the necessary social conditions for the achievement of knowledge, and the possibility for the greatest number of people to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities.  
  | author=Ekelund, Robert B., Jr. and Hébert, Robert F.  
 
  | title=A history of economic theory and method
 
  | edition=4th
 
  | Publisher=Waveland Press [Long Grove, Illinois]
 
  | year=1997
 
  | id=ISBN 1-57766-381-0
 
  | page=172}}</ref>  As Adam Smith's ''Wealth of Nations'' had during an earlier period, Mill's ''Principles'' dominated economics teaching. (In the case of Oxford University it was the standard text until 1919, probably because the text that replaced it was written by Cambridge's Alfred Marshall). Mill was the last great ''political economist'' who championed the market system.{{fact}} After him the great economic thinkers eschewed value judgements and stuck to developing theory while allowing others to decide on policy choices.{{fact}}
 
  
Later in life, Mill moved to favor more socialist-oriented politics.[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/#PolEco]
+
==Economic Philosophy==
 +
In his early years as an economic philosopher, Mill advocated a [[free market economy]]. However, he accepted interventions in the economy, such as a tax on alcohol, if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds. He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare. <ref> "The Morality of Hunting with Dogs" [http://www.ifaw.org/ifaw/dfiles/file_285.pdf] ''International Fund for Animal Welfare''. Retrieved April 20, 2008. </ref>  Mill believed that "equality of taxation" meant "equality of sacrifice" and that [[progressive tax]]ation penalized those who worked harder and saved more and was therefore "a mild form of robbery." <ref> Daniel Pellerin. "Taxation and Justice." [http://www.irefeurope.org/col_docs/doc_51_fr.pdf] ''irefeurope.org''. Retrieved April 20, 2008.</ref>
  
===Logic===
+
Mill's ''Principles of Political Economy,'' first published in 1848, was one of the most widely read of all books on [[economics]] in the period.<ref>Robert B. Ekelund, Jr. and Robert F. Hébert. ''A history of economic theory and method,'' 4th ed.([Long Grove, Illinois]: Waveland Press, 1997. ISBN 1577663810), 172</ref> As Adam Smith's ''Wealth of Nations'' had during an earlier period, Mill's ''Principles'' dominated the teaching of economics. At Oxford University it was the standard text until 1919, probably because the text that replaced it had been written by Cambridge's Alfred Marshall). Mill was the last great ''political economist'' who championed the market system. The great economic thinkers who followed him eschewed value judgments in favor of developing theory while allowing others to formulate policy. Later in life, Mill favored more socialist-oriented politics which assured a certain level of well-being for all members of a society. <ref>"John Stuart Mills, Political Economy"[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/#PolEco]''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. Retrieved September 10, 2008.</ref>
  
Mill's ''[[magnum opus]]'' was his ''[[A System of Logic]], Ratiocinative and Inductive'', which went through several revisions and editions. [[William Whewell]]'s ''History of the Inductive Sciences'' ([[1837]]) was a chief influence. The reputation of this work is largely due to his analysis of inductive proof, in contrast to Aristotle's syllogisms, which are deductive. Mill describes the five basic principles of induction which have come to be known as [[Mill's Methods]] - the method of agreement, the method of difference, the joint or double method of agreement and difference, the method of residues, and that of concomitant variations. The common feature of these methods, the one real method of scientific inquiry, is that of elimination. All the other methods are thus subordinate to the method of difference. It was  also Mill's attempt to postulate a [[epistemology|theory of knowledge]], in the same vein as [[John Locke]].
+
==Logic==
 +
Mill's ''magnum opus'' was his ''A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive,'' which went through several revisions and editions. [[William Whewell]]'s ''History of the Inductive Sciences'' (1837) was a chief influence. The reputation of this work is largely due to his analysis of inductive proof, in contrast to Aristotle's syllogisms, which are deductive. Mill describes the five basic principles of [[induction]] which have come to be known as Mill's Methods: the method of agreement, the method of difference, the joint or double method of agreement and difference, the method of residues, and that of concomitant variations. The common feature of these methods, the one real method of scientific inquiry, is that of elimination. All the other methods are thus subordinate to the method of difference. Mill also attempted to postulate a [[epistemology|theory of knowledge]], in the same vein as [[John Locke]].
  
He was also the first to use the term [[dystopia]].<ref name="Mill">John Stuart Mill uses the term dystopia in a parliamentary speech, possibly the first recorded use of the term. [http://hem.passagen.se/replikant/dystopia_timeline.htm Exploring Dystopia], last accessed on 19th March 2006, see also [http://books.google.com/books?ie=UTF-8&vid=ISBN157181440X&id=3ye0vWc85eYC&pg=PA230&lpg=PA230&dq=John+Stuart+Mill+dystopia+1868&sig=YesYZ8kSJZhhi2NdHdOQdZ0nDTk]</ref>
+
Mill was the first to use the term “dystopia” (as opposed to "utopia") in one of his parliamentary speeches. <ref name="Mill">John Stuart Mill uses the term dystopia in a parliamentary speech, possibly the first recorded use of the term. </ref><ref>"Exploring dystopia: a timeline." [http://hem.passagen.se/replikant/dystopia_timeline.htm Exploring Dystopia]Retrieved April 20, 2008.</ref><ref>JORN RUSEN, MICHAEL FEHR AND THOMAS W. RIEGER, (eds.) ''Thinking Utopia: Steps into Other Worlds (Making Sense of History).'' (London: Berghahn Books, 2006. ISBN 1845453042)</ref>
  
==Writings==
+
==List of works==
 
Major works are in bold type.
 
Major works are in bold type.
  
*([[1843]]) ''[[A System of Logic]]''
+
*(1843) ''A System of Logic''
*([[1844]]) ''[[Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy]]''
+
*(1844) ''Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy''
*([[1848]]) '''''[[Principles of Political Economy]]'''''
+
*(1848) '''''Principles of Political Economy'''''
*([[1859]]) '''''[[On Liberty]]'''''
+
*(1859) '''''On Liberty'''''
*([[1861]]) ''[[Considerations on Representative Government]]''
+
*(1861) ''Considerations on Representative Government''
*([[1863]]) '''''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]]'''''  
+
*(1863) '''''Utilitarianism'''''  
*([[1865]]) ''[[Examinations of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy]]''
+
*(1865) ''Examinations of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy''
*([[1865]]) ''[[Auguste Comte and Positivism]]''
+
*(1865) ''Auguste Comte and Positivism''
*([[1867]]) ''Inaugural Address at St. Andrews'' - Rectorial Inaugural Address at the [[University of St. Andrews]], concerning the value of culture.
+
*(1867) ''Inaugural Address at St. Andrews'' - Rectorial Inaugural Address at the University of St. Andrews, concerning the value of culture.
*([[1869]]) ''[[The Subjection of Women]]''
+
*(1869) ''The Subjection of Women''
*([[1873]]) ''[[Autobiography (John Stuart Mill)|Autobiography]]''
+
*(1873) ''Autobiography''
*([[1874]]) ''[[Three Essays on Religion]]''
+
*(1874) ''Three Essays on Religion''
  
 
==See also==
 
==See also==
 
*[[Liberalism]]
 
*[[Liberalism]]
 
*[[Utilitarianism]]
 
*[[Utilitarianism]]
*[[Contributions to liberal theory]]
 
  
==References==
+
==Notes==
;Inline:
 
 
<references/>
 
<references/>
;General:
+
 
*David O. Brink, "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," in ''Philosophy and Public Affairs'' 21 (1992), 67-103.
+
== References ==
*Sterling Harwood, "Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism," in Louis P. Pojman, ed., Moral Philosophy: A Reader (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1998), and in Sterling Harwood, ed., Business as Ethical and Business as Usual (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1996), Chapter 7, and in [http://www.sterlingharwood.com]www.sterlingharwood.com.
+
 
*Robinson, Dave & Groves, Judy (2003). ''Introducing Political Philosophy''. Icon Books. ISBN 1-84046-450-X.
+
*Brink, David O., "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," in ''Philosophy and Public Affairs'' 21 (1992): 67-103.
*[[Samuel Hollander]] - The Economics of John Stuart Mill (University of Toronto Press, 1985)
+
*Capaldi, Nicholas. ''John Stuart Mill: A Biography.'' Cambridge University Press, 2004, ISBN 0521620244
*Mill, John Stuart, [[A System of Logic]], University Press of the Pacific, Honolulu, 2002, ISBN 1-4102-0252-6
+
*Ekelund, Robert B. Jr. and Robert F. Hébert. ''A history of economic theory and method,'' 4th ed. [Long Grove, Illinois]: Waveland Press, 1997. ISBN 1577663810
 +
*Harwood, Sterling. "Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism," in ''Moral Philosophy: A Reader'' (Louis P. Pojman, ed.,), Indianapolis, IN, Hackett Publishing Co., 1998, and in Harwood, Sterling, ed., ''Business as Ethical and Business as Usual.'' Wadsworth Publishing, 1996, Chapter 7. ISBN 978-0534542511 and online [http://www.sterlingharwood.com]''www.sterlingharwood.com''.  
 +
*Hollander, Samuel. ''The Economics of John Stuart Mill.'' University of Toronto Press, 1985. ISBN 978-0802056719
 +
*Mill, John Stuart. ''A System of Logic.'' Honolulu: University Press of the Pacific, 2002. ISBN 1410202526
 +
*Robinson, Dave, and Judy Groves. ''Introducing Political Philosophy.'' London: Icon Books, 2003. ISBN 184046450X.
 +
*West, Henry R., ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism.'' Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
{{Wikisource author}}
+
All links retrieved August 3, 2022.
{{Wikiquote}}
+
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/bios/Mill.html John Stuart Mill] in the ''Concise Encyclopedia of Economics''  
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/bios/Mill.html John Stuart Mill] in the ''Concise Encyclopedia of Economics'' on [[Econlib]]
+
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/ John Stuart Mill] in the ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/ John Stuart Mill] in the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
+
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/m/milljs.htm John Stuart Mill] in the ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy''
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/m/milljs.htm John Stuart Mill] in the [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
 
 
* {{gutenberg author|id=John_Stuart_Mill|name=John Stuart Mill}}
 
* {{gutenberg author|id=John_Stuart_Mill|name=John Stuart Mill}}
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlLbty.html ''On Liberty''], by John Stuart Mill. Definitive edition, free on [[Econlib]]
+
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlLbty.html ''On Liberty''], by John Stuart Mill.  
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlP.html ''Principles of Political Economy''], by John Stuart Mill. Definitive edition, free on [[Econlib]]
+
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlP.html ''Principles of Political Economy''], by John Stuart Mill.
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlUQP.html ''Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy''], by John Stuart Mill. Definitive edition, free on [[Econlib]]
+
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlUQP.html ''Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy''], by John Stuart Mill.  
* [http://oll.libertyfund.org/Intros/MillJS.php Works of John Stuart Mill] in The Online Library of Liberty
 
 
* [http://utilitarian.net/jsmill John Stuart Mill]. Extensive collection of links to writings by and about J.S. Mill.
 
* [http://utilitarian.net/jsmill John Stuart Mill]. Extensive collection of links to writings by and about J.S. Mill.
 
* [http://atheisme.free.fr/Biographies/Mill_e.htm Biography, works and quotes of John Stuart Mill]
 
* [http://atheisme.free.fr/Biographies/Mill_e.htm Biography, works and quotes of John Stuart Mill]
* [http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/ More easily readable versions of On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and Three Essays on Religion]
 
*[http://www.utilitarianism.com/millauto/ Autobiography of John Stuart Mill]
 
* MetaLibri Digital Library:
 
**'''[http://metalibri.incubadora.fapesp.br/portal/authors/m/john-stuart-mill/utilitarianism/ Utilitarianism]'''
 
*[http://www.la-articles.org.uk/Did%20Mill%20ever%20prefer%20socialism%20to%20liberalism.doc ''How far did JS Mill let liberalism down? Did he prefer Socialism to Liberalism?''] by David McDonagh
 
*[http://catallarchy.net/blog/archives/2006/05/19/welcome-to-catallarchys-mill-fest-the-bicentennial-edition/ Mill-fest: The Bicentennial Edition''] by the blog Catallarchy
 
  
[[Category:19th century philosophers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English agnostics|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Political philosophers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Utilitarians|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English economists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Classical economists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English philosophers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Philosophers of language|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English political writers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Political theorists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Feminist writers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Voting theorists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:People from London|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:People commemorated by blue plaques|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Anglo-Scots|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:1806 births|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:1873 deaths|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
  
[[bs:John Stuart Mill]]
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
[[bg:Джон Стюарт Мил]]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
[[ca:John Stuart Mill]]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
[[cs:John Stuart Mill]]
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
[[da:John Stuart Mill]]
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]  
[[de:John Stuart Mill]]
+
 
[[et:John Stuart Mill]]
+
[[Category:Philosophers]]
[[el:Τζον Στιούαρτ Μιλλ]]
+
[[Category:Economists]]
[[es:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[eo:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[fa:استوارت میل]]
 
[[fr:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[gl:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[ko:존 스튜어트 밀]]
 
[[io:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[is:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[it:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[he:ג'ון סטיוארט מיל]]
 
[[hu:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[nl:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[ja:ジョン・スチュアート・ミル]]
 
[[no:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[oc:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[pl:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[pt:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[ro:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[ru:Милль, Джон Стюарт]]
 
[[simple:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[sk:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[fi:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[sv:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[vi:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[tr:John Stuart Mill]]
 
[[zh:约翰·斯图尔特·密尔]]
 
  
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
  
 +
{{Classical economists}}
 
{{Credit|94402732}}
 
{{Credit|94402732}}

Latest revision as of 07:56, 3 August 2022

Western Philosophy
Nineteenth-century philosophy
JohnStuartMill.JPG
Name: John Stuart Mill
Birth: May 20, 1806 (Pentonville, London, England)
Death: May 8, 1873 (Avignon, France)
School/tradition: Empiricism, Utilitarianism
Main interests
Political philosophy, Ethics, Economics, Inductive Logic
Notable ideas
public/private sphere, hierarchy of pleasures in Utilitarianism, liberalism, early liberal feminism, first system of inductive logic
Influences Influenced
Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, Hobbes, Locke, Bentham, Smith, Ricardo, Tocqueville, James Mill, Saint-Simon (Utopian Socialists)[1] Many philosophers after him, including John Rawls, Robert Nozick, Bertrand Russell, Karl Popper, Ronald Dworkin, H.L.A. Hart, Peter Singer

John Stuart Mill (May 20, 1806 - May 8, 1873), an English philosopher and political economist, was an influential liberal thinker of the nineteenth century. John Stuart Mill refined and developed utilitarianism, which was originally formulated by Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832), his godfather and a close friend of his father James Mill. John Stewart Mill worked for most of his life in the examiner’s office of the British East India Company, while producing a number of books and essays, many of which were published in Westminster Review, The Examiner, Tait’s Magazine, The London Review, The Jurist, and The Monthly Repository. He remains of lasting interest as an ethicist, a social political thinker, and a logician.

Mill formulated the “greatest happiness principle,” which held that one must always act so as to produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people, and distinguished among the quality of different types of happiness. As a logician, in A System of Logic, Mill describes the five basic principles of induction which have come to be known as "Mill's Methods." Among his most well-known and significant works are A System of Logic, Principles of Political Economy, On Liberty, Utilitarianism, The Subjection of Women, Three Essays on Religion, and his Autobiography. Mill's On Liberty emphasized that freedom was not determined by majority rule alone. A free society had the responsibility to protect and guarantee the right of the minority to hold and propagate its views and thus possibly eventually become the majority view within society.

Life

John Stuart Mill was born May 20, 1806 in Pentonville, London, the oldest son of the Scottish philosopher and historian James Mill. John Stuart Mill was given an extremely rigorous upbringing, and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings. He was educated exclusively by his father, a strict disciplinarian, with the advice of Jeremy Bentham and Francis Place. His father, a follower of Bentham and an adherent of associationism, wanted to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of utilitarianism and its implementation after he and Bentham were dead. John Stuart's feats as a child were exceptional; at the age of three he was taught the Greek alphabet and long lists of Greek words with their English equivalents. By the age of eight he had read Aesop's Fables, Xenophon's Anabasis, and the whole of Herodotus, and was acquainted with Lucian, Diogenes Laërtius, Isocrates and six dialogues of Plato (see his Autobiography). He had also read a great deal of history in English and had been taught arithmetic.

A contemporary record of Mill's studies from ages eight to thirteen, published in Bain's sketch of his life, suggests that his autobiography understated the amount of work he did as a child. At the age of eight he began learning Latin, Euclid, and algebra, and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family. His main reading was still history, but he went through all the Latin and Greek authors commonly read in the schools and universities at the time. He was not taught to compose either in Latin or in Greek, and he was never an exact scholar; he was required to read for the subject matter, and by the age of ten he could read Plato and Demosthenes with ease. His father's History of India was published in 1818; immediately afterwards, at about the age of 12, John began a thorough study of scholastic logic, at the same time reading Aristotle's logical treatises in the original language. In the following year he was introduced to political economy and studied Adam Smith and David Ricardo with his father, ultimately completing their classical economic view of factors of production. Mill’s childhood was not unhappy, but he suffered from the lack of natural, unforced development and his mental health and state of mind were affected.

In France

Mill spent the period from May 1820 until July 1821 in France with the family of Sir Samuel Bentham, the brother of the English Utilitarian philosopher Jeremy Bentham. Extracts from his diary at that time show that he studied chemistry, botany, and advanced mathematics; methodically read and wrote; and made notes on the scenery and the customs of the French people, while becoming fluent in French. On his return to England in 1821, Mill refused to study at Oxford University or Cambridge University, because he refused to take Anglican orders, a requirement at that time.[2] Instead he studied psychology and began to read Roman law with John Austin; his father was preparing him for a career in law. In 1823, however, at the age of eighteen, he entered the examiner’s office of the India House. In 1828 he was promoted to assistant examiner, and after his father’s death in 1836, he was put in charge of the British East India Company’s relations with the Indian states. He carried this responsibility for 20 years, and in 1856 became chief of the examiner’s office.

Mill was an outspoken critic of the flaws which he perceived in Parliament and in the British legal system. He became a contributor to the Westminster Review, founded in April, 1824, as the organ of the philosophical radicals. In 1825 he began work on Bentham’s Rationale of Judicial Evidence (1827). He enjoyed discussions with the intellectuals who visited his father’s house, and participated in a reading society which began meeting at the home of the English historian George Grote in 1825. The same year he joined the London Debating Society, where he began to question the values with which he had been brought up. His father had had little use for poetry, friendship and private emotions; John Stuart Mill began to change his views and to have a more moderate and practical approach to political ideals and the meaning of human happiness. He came to believe that the purpose of a political philosophy was not to define ideal political institutions and or the ideal structure of society, but to define ideal political principles which could be used to construct institutions appropriate to the many different circumstances of the real world.

At the age of 21 Mill suffered a nervous breakdown; as he explained in chapter V of his Autobiography, this was caused by the great physical and mental arduousness of his studies which had suppressed any feelings he might have developed normally in childhood. This depression eventually began to dissipate, and he began to find solace in the poetry of William Wordsworth. His capacity for emotion resurfaced, Mill remarking that the "cloud gradually drew off." Letters published by Mill in The Examiner during the autumn of 1830, just after he met some young political liberals in Paris, indicated that he had regained some optimism. In 1831 The Examiner published a series of articles by Mill on The Spirit of the Age, and during 1832 and 1833 he contributed essays to Tait’s Magazine, The Jurist, and The Monthly Repository. In 1835 he was made editor of The London Review when it was founded by Sir William Molesworth, and he continued as editor when it was combined with The Westminster into The London and Westminster Review, until 1840. After 1840, he published several articles in the Edinburgh Review.

In 1843, John Stuart Mill published the first edition of A System of Logic, an attempt to formulate the methods of scientific investigation and to amalgate old and new forms of logic. Mill himself distinguished three stages in his development as a political economist. In Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy, five essays proposing solutions to problems of economics published in 1844, he appeared to follow David Ricardo, striving for precision and exploring future consequences. His Principles of Political Economy, published in two volumes in 1848, 1849, and 1852, showed more originality and independent thought, proposing the creation of peasant proprietorships as a solution for the poverty and social disorder in Ireland.

Social concern

In his third stage, he became increasingly interested in social problems rather than political problems, no longer regarding property ownership as sacred and recognizing that the changing structure of society required new methods of economic organization in order to ensure a tolerable life for the working classes. He claimed that he was influenced in this direction by his wife, Harriet Taylor Mill, whom he married in 1851 after a friendship of 21 years. Brilliant in her own right, Taylor was a significant influence on Mill's work and ideas during both their friendship and marriage. She reinforced Mill's advocacy of women's rights. He cited her influence in his final revision of On Liberty, which was published shortly after her death, and she appeared to be obliquely referenced in The Subjection of Women.

Harriet Taylor

During the seven years of his marriage, Mill was fully occupied with his work in the British East India Company. He became head of the examiner’s office in 1856 and served until the British East India Company was dissolved and its powers transferred to the government of Britain. Mill opposed this move, and as head of the office it was his responsibility to write the defense of the British East India Company’s government of India. He was offered a position on the new governing council, but took retirement instead. Shortly afterwards, Harriet Taylor Mill died in Avignon in 1858 after developing severe lung congestion. Mill spent the rest of his life mostly at a villa in Saint-Véran, near Avignon, returning to England only for a short period in each year. He published a series of books and essays on politics and ethics, including On Liberty (1859), Thoughts on Parliamentary Reform (1859), Considerations on Representative Government (1861), and Utilitarianism (in 'Fraser's Magazine', 1861; separate publication, 1863). In 1865 he published two philosophical works, Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy and Auguste Comte and Positivism, and in 1869 he republished his father's Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind with additional illustrations and explanatory notes.

Mill remained engaged in politics. He supported the North in the United States Civil War, making it clear that the real issue behind the war was abolition of slavery. In 1865 he ran for election as the parliamentary candidate for Westminster. [3] According to his principles, he did no campaigning, but was elected. He was instrumental in shaping the 1867 Reform Bill to prevent certain corrupt practices, and argued for the reform of land tenure in Ireland (see his England and Ireland, 1868, and his Chapters and Speeches on the Irish Land Question, 1870), women’s suffrage, the reduction of the national debt, the reform of London government, and the abrogation of the Declaration of Paris (1856), concerning the carriage of property at sea during the Crimean War. He also advocated England's duty to intervene in foreign politics in support of freedom. In Considerations on Representative Government, Mill called for various reforms of Parliament and voting, especially proportional representation, the Single Transferable Vote, and the extension of suffrage. His advocacy of reform made him unpopular with “moderate Liberals” and he lost the general parliamentary election in 1868. Between the years 1865-1868 he served as Lord Rector of the University of Saint Andrews, where he gave an inaugural speech on the value of culture.

Mill retired to Avignon, but continued his writing, publishing essays on endowments, on land, on labor, and on metaphysical and psychological questions in the Fortnightly Review (compiled in the fourth volume of his Dissertations, 1875). In 1867 he had helped to found the first women's suffrage society, later the National Union of Women's Suffrage Societies, and in 1869 he published The Subjection of Women (written 1861), the classical theoretical statement of the case for woman suffrage. His last public activity was involvement with the starting of the Land Tenure Reform Association, for which he wrote in The Examiner and made a public speech a few months before his death. Mill was also an enthusiastic botanist and frequently contributed papers and short articles to the Phytologist. He was godfather to Bertrand Russell.

John Stuart Mill died at Avignon, France, on May 8, 1873 and was buried alongside his wife. His Autobiography and Three Essays on Religion (1874) were published posthumously.

A bronze statue of Mill stands on the Thames embankment in London, and G.F. Watts's copy of his original portrait of Mill hangs in the National Gallery there.

Theory of Liberty

Mill's On Liberty, a founding text of liberalism and one of the most important treatises ever written on the concept of liberty, explored the nature and limits of the power that can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual. Mill developed further than any previous philosopher the concept of the “harm principle,” which holds that each individual has the right to act as he wants, so long as these actions do not harm others. If an action is self-regarding, that is, if it only directly affects the person undertaking the action, then society has no right to intervene, even if it feels the actor is harming himself. Mill excused those who are "incapable of self-government" from this principle, such as young children or those living in “backward states of society." It is important to emphasize that Mill did not consider that giving offence to someone constituted “harm;” an action could not be restricted because it violated the conventions or morals of a given society.

On Liberty included an impassioned defense of free speech. Mill argued that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress. We can never be sure, he contended, if a silenced opinion does not contain some element of the truth. He also argued that allowing people to air false opinions is productive for two reasons. Individuals are more likely to abandon erroneous beliefs if they are engaged in an open exchange of ideas. By forcing other individuals to re-examine and re-affirm their beliefs in the process of debate, these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma. It was not enough for Mill that one simply has an unexamined belief that happens to be true; one must understand why the belief in question is the true one.

Mill's statement of the "harm principle" in Chapter 1 of On Liberty, "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not sufficient warrant," entails a number of complications. For example, Mill explicitly stated that “harms” may include acts of omission as well as acts of commission. Thus, failing to rescue a drowning child counts as a harmful act, as does failing to pay taxes, or failing to appear as a witness in court. All such harmful omissions may be regulated, according to Mill. By contrast, it does not count as harming someone if (without force or fraud) the affected individual consents to assume the risk; one may permissibly offer unsafe employment to others, provided there is no deception involved. (Mill does, however, recognize one limit to consent: society should not permit people to sell themselves into slavery). In these and other cases, it is important to keep in mind that the arguments in On Liberty are grounded on the principle of Utility, and not on appeals to natural rights. The question of what counts as a self-regarding action and what actions, whether of omission or commission, constitute harmful actions subject to regulation, is still under debate.

Mill was an early and strong supporter of women's rights. His book The Subjection of Women is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author. He felt that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times, a set of prejudices that severely impeded the progress of humanity.

Utilitarianism

The canonical statement of Mill's Utilitarianism can be found in Utilitarianism, written to defend his ethical system. The concept of the greatest good for the greatest number goes back to Aristotle; Mill's account is primarily influenced by Jeremy Bentham, and Mill's father James Mill. Mill’s famous formulation of Utilitarianism is known as the “greatest happiness principle.” It holds that one must always act so as to produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people. One of Mill's major contributions to Utilitarianism was his argument for the qualitative separation of pleasures. Bentham treated all forms of happiness as equal, whereas Mill argued that intellectual and moral pleasures are superior to more physical forms of pleasure. Mill distinguishes between "happiness" and "contentment," claiming that the former is of higher value than the latter, a belief wittily encapsulated in his statement that it is “better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.” Mill included in his definition of “utility” the pleasures of the imagination and the gratification of the higher emotions.

In On Liberty, Mill suggests that utility is to be conceived in relation to man as "a progressive being," whose rational capacities are constantly being developed and exercised as he strives to achieve a “higher mode of existence." His rejection of censorship and paternalism is intended to create the necessary social conditions for the achievement of knowledge, and the possibility for the greatest number of people to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities.

Economic Philosophy

In his early years as an economic philosopher, Mill advocated a free market economy. However, he accepted interventions in the economy, such as a tax on alcohol, if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds. He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare. [4] Mill believed that "equality of taxation" meant "equality of sacrifice" and that progressive taxation penalized those who worked harder and saved more and was therefore "a mild form of robbery." [5]

Mill's Principles of Political Economy, first published in 1848, was one of the most widely read of all books on economics in the period.[6] As Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations had during an earlier period, Mill's Principles dominated the teaching of economics. At Oxford University it was the standard text until 1919, probably because the text that replaced it had been written by Cambridge's Alfred Marshall). Mill was the last great political economist who championed the market system. The great economic thinkers who followed him eschewed value judgments in favor of developing theory while allowing others to formulate policy. Later in life, Mill favored more socialist-oriented politics which assured a certain level of well-being for all members of a society. [7]

Logic

Mill's magnum opus was his A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, which went through several revisions and editions. William Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences (1837) was a chief influence. The reputation of this work is largely due to his analysis of inductive proof, in contrast to Aristotle's syllogisms, which are deductive. Mill describes the five basic principles of induction which have come to be known as Mill's Methods: the method of agreement, the method of difference, the joint or double method of agreement and difference, the method of residues, and that of concomitant variations. The common feature of these methods, the one real method of scientific inquiry, is that of elimination. All the other methods are thus subordinate to the method of difference. Mill also attempted to postulate a theory of knowledge, in the same vein as John Locke.

Mill was the first to use the term “dystopia” (as opposed to "utopia") in one of his parliamentary speeches. [8][9][10]

List of works

Major works are in bold type.

  • (1843) A System of Logic
  • (1844) Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy
  • (1848) Principles of Political Economy
  • (1859) On Liberty
  • (1861) Considerations on Representative Government
  • (1863) Utilitarianism
  • (1865) Examinations of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy
  • (1865) Auguste Comte and Positivism
  • (1867) Inaugural Address at St. Andrews - Rectorial Inaugural Address at the University of St. Andrews, concerning the value of culture.
  • (1869) The Subjection of Women
  • (1873) Autobiography
  • (1874) Three Essays on Religion

See also

Notes

  1. Friedrich Hayek (1941). The Counter-Revolution of Science. Economica 8 (31): 281-320.
  2. Nicholas Capaldi. John Stuart Mill: A Biography. (Cambridge, 2004, ISBN 0521620244), 33.
  3. Capaldi, 321-322
  4. "The Morality of Hunting with Dogs" [1] International Fund for Animal Welfare. Retrieved April 20, 2008.
  5. Daniel Pellerin. "Taxation and Justice." [2] irefeurope.org. Retrieved April 20, 2008.
  6. Robert B. Ekelund, Jr. and Robert F. Hébert. A history of economic theory and method, 4th ed.([Long Grove, Illinois]: Waveland Press, 1997. ISBN 1577663810), 172
  7. "John Stuart Mills, Political Economy"[3]Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved September 10, 2008.
  8. John Stuart Mill uses the term dystopia in a parliamentary speech, possibly the first recorded use of the term.
  9. "Exploring dystopia: a timeline." Exploring DystopiaRetrieved April 20, 2008.
  10. JORN RUSEN, MICHAEL FEHR AND THOMAS W. RIEGER, (eds.) Thinking Utopia: Steps into Other Worlds (Making Sense of History). (London: Berghahn Books, 2006. ISBN 1845453042)

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Brink, David O., "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," in Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (1992): 67-103.
  • Capaldi, Nicholas. John Stuart Mill: A Biography. Cambridge University Press, 2004, ISBN 0521620244
  • Ekelund, Robert B. Jr. and Robert F. Hébert. A history of economic theory and method, 4th ed. [Long Grove, Illinois]: Waveland Press, 1997. ISBN 1577663810
  • Harwood, Sterling. "Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism," in Moral Philosophy: A Reader (Louis P. Pojman, ed.,), Indianapolis, IN, Hackett Publishing Co., 1998, and in Harwood, Sterling, ed., Business as Ethical and Business as Usual. Wadsworth Publishing, 1996, Chapter 7. ISBN 978-0534542511 and online [4]www.sterlingharwood.com.
  • Hollander, Samuel. The Economics of John Stuart Mill. University of Toronto Press, 1985. ISBN 978-0802056719
  • Mill, John Stuart. A System of Logic. Honolulu: University Press of the Pacific, 2002. ISBN 1410202526
  • Robinson, Dave, and Judy Groves. Introducing Political Philosophy. London: Icon Books, 2003. ISBN 184046450X.
  • West, Henry R., ed., The Blackwell Guide to Mill's Utilitarianism. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006.

External links

All links retrieved August 3, 2022.


General Philosophy Sources


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.