Difference between revisions of "Process thought" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m
Line 2: Line 2:
 
[[Process thought]], also known as [[process philosophy]] or [[process theology]], is a system of thought with its fundamental description in [[Alfred North Whitehead]]'s ''Process and Reality'' (1929). Process thought sees all of reality as one interconnected whole; and Whitehead's background in [[biology]], [[mathematics]] and [[philosophy]] enabled him to develop a unified worldview in which religion and science are harmonized.
 
[[Process thought]], also known as [[process philosophy]] or [[process theology]], is a system of thought with its fundamental description in [[Alfred North Whitehead]]'s ''Process and Reality'' (1929). Process thought sees all of reality as one interconnected whole; and Whitehead's background in [[biology]], [[mathematics]] and [[philosophy]] enabled him to develop a unified worldview in which religion and science are harmonized.
  
For Whitehead an "actual entity" is a "unit of concresence," i.e., the coming together of all that precedes an entity to make it what it is at that particular instant. Then fades into the past, as it become the basis for the next actual entity in its immediate future.<ref>Alfred North Whitehead, ''Process and Reality,'' pp. 18-30.</ref> In our [[consciousness]] we know each instant as a unified "drop of experience." This consciousness is more primary than the physical entities in which the experience resides (e.g., our brains). Consciousness exists in all life at different levels, and is pushing the [[universe]] forward toward ever higher expressions of creativity and awareness. [[God]], who is the foundation of all consciousness, "prehends" all existence with perfect knowledge and perfect love<ref>John B.Cobb, Jr., ''Process Theology as Political Theology,'' p. 57.</ref>and pushes each actual entity forward through persuasion (not  coercion).  
+
For Whitehead an "actual entity" is a "unit of concresence," i.e., the coming together of all that precedes an entity to make it what it is at that particular instant. Then fades into the past, as it become the basis for the next actual entity in its immediate future.<ref>Alfred North Whitehead, ''Process and Reality,'' pp. 18-30.</ref> We know each instant as a unified "drop of experience." This experience is more primary than the physical entities in which the experience resides (e.g., our brains). Consciousness and subconscious experience exists in all life at different levels, and is pushing the [[universe]] forward toward ever higher expressions of creativity and awareness. [[God]], who is the foundation of all experience, "prehends" all existence with perfect knowledge and perfect love<ref>John B.Cobb, Jr., ''Process Theology as Political Theology,'' p. 57.</ref> and pushes each actual entity forward through persuasion (not  coercion).  
  
 
[[Charles Hartshorne]], an assistant to Whitehead at [[Harvard University]], continued to develop Whitehead's metaphysics at the [[University of Chicago]] where he influenced two theologians, [[John B. Cobb, Jr.]] and [[Schubert Ogden]] who developed process theology to a status with influence comparable to [[liberation theology]].
 
[[Charles Hartshorne]], an assistant to Whitehead at [[Harvard University]], continued to develop Whitehead's metaphysics at the [[University of Chicago]] where he influenced two theologians, [[John B. Cobb, Jr.]] and [[Schubert Ogden]] who developed process theology to a status with influence comparable to [[liberation theology]].
Line 8: Line 8:
 
Process theologians have found extensive common ground with [[Buddhism|Buddhist]]s and their conception of God as cosmic consciousness, not a physical substance. They have also contributed uniquely to discussions of [[evolution]] because they understand reality as an evolution of the universe, not on the basis of "survival of the fittest," but as a goad<ref>There has been some controversy over changing the term "goal" to "goad" on p. 88 of the corrected edition by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. While the authors feel it is more consistent with Whitehead's philosophy, it has been a challenge to those traditional theologians who believe God has a specific ''telos'' in mind. However, process theology affirms that God also changes and grows, striving for ever greater joy.</ref> to a future with ever-higher and more complex modes of expression and experiences of joy and "feeling."  
 
Process theologians have found extensive common ground with [[Buddhism|Buddhist]]s and their conception of God as cosmic consciousness, not a physical substance. They have also contributed uniquely to discussions of [[evolution]] because they understand reality as an evolution of the universe, not on the basis of "survival of the fittest," but as a goad<ref>There has been some controversy over changing the term "goal" to "goad" on p. 88 of the corrected edition by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. While the authors feel it is more consistent with Whitehead's philosophy, it has been a challenge to those traditional theologians who believe God has a specific ''telos'' in mind. However, process theology affirms that God also changes and grows, striving for ever greater joy.</ref> to a future with ever-higher and more complex modes of expression and experiences of joy and "feeling."  
  
== History ==
+
==Earlier forms of process thought==
Various forms of thought that emphasize process exist in history and in other cultures. While these are not specifically related to the school of thought descended from Whitehead, they contain various efforts to explain life in terms of change, growth, and flux. Elements of a process philosophy begin in Western thought with [[Heraclitus]]' fragments in which he posits the [[noumenon]] (not to be confused with Kant's "Ding an sich"), the ground of becoming, as ''agon'' or "strife of opposites" as the underlying basis of all reality defined by change.
+
Various forms of thought that emphasize process exist in history and in other cultures. While these are not specifically related to the school of thought developed by Whitehead, they contain various efforts to explain life in terms of change, growth, and flux. Elements of a process philosophy begin in Western thought with [[Heraclitus]]' fragments in which he posits the [[noumenon]] (not to be confused with Kant's "Ding an sich"), the ground of becoming, as ''agon'' or "strife of opposites" as the underlying basis of all reality defined by change.
  
Much later, [[Aristotle]]'s concept of [[moderation]], which parallels the concept in [[Buddhism]] (the two are almost contemporaries) establishes goodness or value as a function of a process in which extremes are avoided. The process, not the outcomes or ideals balanced to achieve the process, is the ultimate good. The [[Noble Eightfold Path]] may be the clearest expression of this principle in any [[religion]] before modern times. More [[monastic]] traditions in both East and West tended to emphasize the process of [[enlightenment]], often interpreted quite literally as leaving the (heavy) body behind, especially among [[Roman Catholic]] monks. Historically, however, the Eastern traditions were more forgiving of temporary failures of will as long as they were in fact temporary. Many Buddhist and [[Taoist]] stories emphasize the value of quickly returning to one's disciplined state after a breach, and even forgetting it had occurred. [[Yoga]]-related disciplines also avoid any explicit goal-setting or measures of success. Eastern traditions almost universally invoke the concept of '''balance''' which implies multiple and contradictory pressures in, as Heraclitus suggested, ongoing "strife".
+
Much later, [[Aristotle]]'s concept of [[moderation]], which parallels the concept in [[Buddhism]] (the two are almost contemporaries) establishes goodness or value as a function of a process in which extremes are avoided. The process, not the outcome, is the ultimate good. The [[Noble Eightfold Path]] may be the clearest expression of this principle in any [[religion]] before modern times. More [[monastic]] traditions in both East and West tended to emphasize the process of [[enlightenment]], often interpreted quite literally as leaving the (heavy) body behind, especially among [[Roman Catholic]] monks. Historically, however, the Eastern traditions were more forgiving of temporary failures of will as long as they were in fact temporary. Many Buddhist and [[Taoist]] stories emphasize the value of quickly returning to one's disciplined state after a breach, and even forgetting it had occurred. [[Yoga]]-related disciplines also avoid any explicit goal-setting or measures of success. Eastern traditions almost universally invoke the concept of '''balance''' which implies multiple and contradictory pressures in, as Heraclitus suggested, ongoing "strife."
  
 
Process philosophy was not totally neglected during [[The Enlightenment]]. [[René Descartes]], for instance, proposed that the mind and body were actually connected and unified by a single process, the [[imagination]]. This idea was often discarded or devalued by Descartes' followers and critics who attributed to him (incorrectly) advocating a [[mind-body dualism]]. Very similarly, the [[law of the excluded middle]] was raised to ontological status by those of [[Aristotle]]'s followers, notably those practicing medieval [[scholasticism]], who wished to ignore some of  his telling observations about moderation (the very ones that [[Francis Bacon]] celebrated) and [[rhetoric]] (which Aristotle praised, seemingly foreshadowing Descartes' imagination).   
 
Process philosophy was not totally neglected during [[The Enlightenment]]. [[René Descartes]], for instance, proposed that the mind and body were actually connected and unified by a single process, the [[imagination]]. This idea was often discarded or devalued by Descartes' followers and critics who attributed to him (incorrectly) advocating a [[mind-body dualism]]. Very similarly, the [[law of the excluded middle]] was raised to ontological status by those of [[Aristotle]]'s followers, notably those practicing medieval [[scholasticism]], who wished to ignore some of  his telling observations about moderation (the very ones that [[Francis Bacon]] celebrated) and [[rhetoric]] (which Aristotle praised, seemingly foreshadowing Descartes' imagination).   
Line 21: Line 21:
 
Of other philosophers, more dominant at that time, [[Immanuel Kant]] noted that either experience made objects possible, or objects made experience possible. He didn't consider that processes might make both possible. [[Gottfried Leibniz]]'s [[monad]]s were not related to all other occasions of experience that preceded them. [[Reductionism]] was in vogue—to reduce processes (say into tasks or events) was more difficult than reducing objects. In the [[management science]] of [[Frederick Taylor]] however there was emerging a view of infinitely reducible work processes and an ontology limited to "practical" tasks - later to come into bloom with [[total quality management]] and the "[[six sigma]]" goal.
 
Of other philosophers, more dominant at that time, [[Immanuel Kant]] noted that either experience made objects possible, or objects made experience possible. He didn't consider that processes might make both possible. [[Gottfried Leibniz]]'s [[monad]]s were not related to all other occasions of experience that preceded them. [[Reductionism]] was in vogue—to reduce processes (say into tasks or events) was more difficult than reducing objects. In the [[management science]] of [[Frederick Taylor]] however there was emerging a view of infinitely reducible work processes and an ontology limited to "practical" tasks - later to come into bloom with [[total quality management]] and the "[[six sigma]]" goal.
  
In 1905, the theory of [[general relativity]] curtailed exploration of pure process views and made the case for a specific and expanding [[universe]] that existed as an objective object of our human perception and cognition. This view was attractive if only for simplicity. The curiously fixed [[speed of light]] provided the basis on which a number or limit, rather than a process, could be said to be defining reality itself, at least as perceivable by beings similar to ourselves. At the same time, a [[philosophy of mathematics]] was developing that could be specified as a set of [[axiom]]s, again, a fixed not process-oriented description.   
+
===Influences on Whitehead===
 +
Whitehead's background was a very unusual one for a speculative [[metaphysics|metaphysician]]. Educated as a mathematician, he became, through his coauthorship and 1913 publication of ''[[Principia Mathematica]]''' with [[Bertrand Russell]], a major logician. Later he wrote extensively on physics and its philosophy, proposing a theory of relativity rivaling [[Einstein]]'s - ''see [[Theory of relativity|relativity]].'' He was conversant with the [[quantum mechanics]] that emerged in the 1920s. Whitehead did not begin teaching and writing on process and metaphysics until he moved to [[Harvard University|Harvard]] at 63 years of age.
 +
 
 +
In 1905, the theory of [[general relativity]] had curtailed exploration of pure process views and made the case for a specific and expanding [[universe]] that existed as an objective object of our human perception and cognition. This view was attractive if only for simplicity. The curiously fixed [[speed of light]] provided the basis on which a number or limit, rather than a process, could be said to be defining reality itself, at least as perceivable by beings similar to ourselves. At the same time, a [[philosophy of mathematics]] was developing that could be specified as a set of [[axiom]]s, again, a fixed not process-oriented description.   
  
 
These hopes proved vain, although it remained for [[Bertrand Russell|Russell]] and [[Alfred North Whitehead|Whitehead]] to prove that so in 1913, after which Whitehead elaborated what had been learned from attempts to escape process as the basis of ontology. This resulted in the most famous work of process philosophy ''[[Process and Reality]].''
 
These hopes proved vain, although it remained for [[Bertrand Russell|Russell]] and [[Alfred North Whitehead|Whitehead]] to prove that so in 1913, after which Whitehead elaborated what had been learned from attempts to escape process as the basis of ontology. This resulted in the most famous work of process philosophy ''[[Process and Reality]].''
Line 27: Line 30:
 
Hegel's [[dialectic]]al thought is said by some to have influenced Whitehead. In both philosophers, the "absolute" is a movement in and through determinates, not the essence of the determinates, which are fixed concepts or "things." However, [[Hegel]] proposed an ontology of the relationship between opposites that form the basis for a synthesis which is the new state of reality. The method was a "struggle" of opposites—picked up by Marx as justification for the struggle of workers against capitalists to create a higher form of society. This might fit, to some extent, with Darwin's notion of "survival of the fittest." Hegel nonetheless, failed to make process an absolute when he called the [[Nation-state|State]] as a ''telos''—the end-state of the "march of the Absolute through history."   
 
Hegel's [[dialectic]]al thought is said by some to have influenced Whitehead. In both philosophers, the "absolute" is a movement in and through determinates, not the essence of the determinates, which are fixed concepts or "things." However, [[Hegel]] proposed an ontology of the relationship between opposites that form the basis for a synthesis which is the new state of reality. The method was a "struggle" of opposites—picked up by Marx as justification for the struggle of workers against capitalists to create a higher form of society. This might fit, to some extent, with Darwin's notion of "survival of the fittest." Hegel nonetheless, failed to make process an absolute when he called the [[Nation-state|State]] as a ''telos''—the end-state of the "march of the Absolute through history."   
  
Whitehead, on the other hand, saw experience as a complex unity of all that "ingressed" into a unit of experience. A dialectic between two poles, might be a simple way of employing logic by an observer, but it does not properly represent the wholeness of experience. Further there is no end-state, there is only ongoing process. Also, for Whitehead, "survival of the fittest" is not the reason for increased complexity of species, but increased complexity develops because it provides the basis for increased richness in feeling, in other words joy. It is the thirst for increased richness of feeling that stimulates creativity that lays at the basis of [[evolution]], not some struggle between two opposites.
+
Whitehead, on the other hand, saw experience as a complex unity of all that "ingressed" into a unit of experience. A dialectic between two poles, might be a simple way of employing logic by an observer, but it does not properly represent the wholeness of experience. Further there is no end-state, there is only ongoing process. For Whitehead, "survival of the fittest" is not the reason for increased complexity of species, but increased complexity develops because it provides the basis for increased richness in feeling. It is the thirst for increased richness of feeling and joy that stimulates creativity and lays at the basis of [[evolution]], not a struggle between two opposites.
 +
 
 +
Whitehead was also influenced by the French philosopher [[Henri Bergson|Henri-Louis Bergson]] (1859-1941), who was awarded the [[Nobel Prize for Literature]] in 1927.
  
 
== Whitehead's ''Process and Reality''==
 
== Whitehead's ''Process and Reality''==
 
In his major work on process philosophy, ''Process and Reality,'' Whitehead stated that the entire European philosophical tradition consists of "a series of footnotes to [[Plato]]."<ref>''Process and Reality,'' p. 39.</ref> In Plato and [[Aristotle]] resided elements that could have developed into a "philosophy or organism" (see above), in which the temporal and the timeless, the actual and the potential, the eternal and the concrete coexisted. However, Western philosophy has more often excluded the organic nature of reality, and modern philosophy has focused material substances as the basis of reality. The thoughtworld of the west became a bridgeless chasm between fact and value, between [[science]] and [[religion]]. Whitehead, as a [[mathematics|mathematician]], could see how what we often view as abstractions from reality can instead be the foundation of reality.  
 
In his major work on process philosophy, ''Process and Reality,'' Whitehead stated that the entire European philosophical tradition consists of "a series of footnotes to [[Plato]]."<ref>''Process and Reality,'' p. 39.</ref> In Plato and [[Aristotle]] resided elements that could have developed into a "philosophy or organism" (see above), in which the temporal and the timeless, the actual and the potential, the eternal and the concrete coexisted. However, Western philosophy has more often excluded the organic nature of reality, and modern philosophy has focused material substances as the basis of reality. The thoughtworld of the west became a bridgeless chasm between fact and value, between [[science]] and [[religion]]. Whitehead, as a [[mathematics|mathematician]], could see how what we often view as abstractions from reality can instead be the foundation of reality.  
 
Whitehead's background was a very unusual one for a speculative [[metaphysics|metaphysician]]. Educated as a mathematician, he became, through his coauthorship and 1913 publication of ''[[Principia Mathematica]]''' with [[Bertrand Russell]], a major logician. Later he wrote extensively on physics and its philosophy, proposing a theory of relativity rivaling [[Einstein]]'s - ''see [[Theory of relativity|relativity]].'' He was conversant with the [[quantum mechanics]] that emerged in the 1920s. Whitehead did not begin teaching and writing on process and metaphysics until he moved to [[Harvard University|Harvard]] at 63 years of age.
 
  
 
The process metaphysics elaborated in ''Process and Reality'' proposes that the fundamental elements of the universe are ''actual entities'' which exist as the coming together, or "nexus" of a complex string of previous entities into an new occasion, or event. What people commonly think of as concrete [[object]]s are actually transient successions of events where entities exist momentarily. This process is guided by a primordial "occasions of experience" present in each actual entity. Occasions of experience can be complex, like the experience of individual human beings, or smaller occasions of experience in tadpoles or plants.  
 
The process metaphysics elaborated in ''Process and Reality'' proposes that the fundamental elements of the universe are ''actual entities'' which exist as the coming together, or "nexus" of a complex string of previous entities into an new occasion, or event. What people commonly think of as concrete [[object]]s are actually transient successions of events where entities exist momentarily. This process is guided by a primordial "occasions of experience" present in each actual entity. Occasions of experience can be complex, like the experience of individual human beings, or smaller occasions of experience in tadpoles or plants.  
Line 40: Line 43:
 
Whitehead's philosophy resembles in some respects the monads of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]]. However, unlike Leibniz's monads, Whitehead's occasions of experience are interrelated with every other occasion of experience that precedes it in time. Inherent in Whitehead's philosophy is the notion of time; all experiences are influenced by prior experiences, and will influence all future experiences. This process of influencing is never deterministic; God did not set a machine in motion and leave.  
 
Whitehead's philosophy resembles in some respects the monads of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]]. However, unlike Leibniz's monads, Whitehead's occasions of experience are interrelated with every other occasion of experience that precedes it in time. Inherent in Whitehead's philosophy is the notion of time; all experiences are influenced by prior experiences, and will influence all future experiences. This process of influencing is never deterministic; God did not set a machine in motion and leave.  
  
In every occasion of experience there exists a prehending of other experiences, and then a response to them. This is the ''process'' in ''process philosophy''. Because no process is ever deterministic, free will and creativity are essential to and inherent in the universe. Each "prehension" is the basis for a subjective harmony and a valuation which includes a subjective aim at greater intensity of feeling in a future event. This is the basis for novelty and the organic development of all experience.
+
In every occasion of experience there exists a prehending of other experiences, and then a response to them. This is the ''process'' in ''process philosophy''. Because no process is ever deterministic, free will and creativity are essential to and inherent in the universe. Each "prehension" is the basis for a subjective harmony and a valuation which includes a subjective aim at greater intensity of [[feeling]] in a future event. This is the basis for novelty and the organic development of all experience.
  
God, for Whitehead<ref>''Process and Reality,'' p. 31ff.</ref> is present in all actual entities via ingression of "eternal objects." While God is the primordial creature, He is not limited to His primordial nature. God derives a "consequent nature" from his "physical prehension of derivative actual entities." God is present in all occasions; thus Whitehead promotes a form of [[panentheism]]. Further God experiences growth and change; God himself is in process.
+
[[God]], for Whitehead<ref>''Process and Reality,'' p. 31ff.</ref> is present in all actual entities via ingression of "eternal objects." While God is the primordial creature, He is not limited to His primordial nature. God derives a "consequent nature" from his "physical prehension of derivative actual entities." God is present in all occasions; thus Whitehead promotes a form of [[panentheism]]. Further, God experiences growth and change; God himself is in process.
  
Since, Whitehead argues, free will is inherent to the nature of the universe, God is not a powerful master that commands us to serve him. Rather, God offers goads us toward higher forms of experience, with greater intensity of feeling and joy. God participates in the evolution of the universe by offering possibilities, which may be accepted or rejected. Whitehead's thinking here has influenced [[process theology]], whose prominent advocates include [[Charles Hartshorne]], [[John B. Cobb, Jr.]], and [[Hans Jonas]].  
+
Since, Whitehead argues, free will is inherent to the nature of the universe, God is not a powerful master that commands us to serve him. Rather, God offers goads us toward higher forms of experience, with greater intensity of feeling and joy. God participates in the evolution of the universe by offering possibilities, which may be accepted or rejected.  
  
Whitehead enumerated three essential natures of God. The primordial nature of God consists of all potentialities of existence for actual occasions, which Whitehead called eternal objects. God can offer possibilities by ordering the relevance of eternal objects. The consequent nature of God prehends everything that happens in reality. As such, God experiences all of reality in a sentient manner. The last nature is the superjective. This is the way in which God’s synthesis becomes a sense-datum for other actual entities. In this sense, God is prehended or felt by other existing actual entities. In Christian terms, this prehension of God may be through the spiritual senses.
+
Whitehead enumerated three essential natures of God. The primordial nature of God consists of all potentialities of existence for actual occasions, which Whitehead called eternal objects. God can offer possibilities by ordering the relevance of eternal objects. The consequent nature of God prehends everything that happens in reality. As such, God experiences all of reality in a sentient manner. The last nature is the superjective. This is the way in which God’s synthesis becomes a sense-datum for other actual entities. In this sense, God is prehended or felt by other existing actual entities. In Christian terms, this prehension of God may be through the spiritual senses.
  
 
== Process philosophy since Whitehead ==
 
== Process philosophy since Whitehead ==
  
Whitehead's influence was not restricted to philosophers, physicists and mathematicians.  He was influenced by the French philosopher [[Henri Bergson|Henri-Louis Bergson]] (1859-1941), who was awarded the [[Nobel Prize for Literature]] in 1927. Process philosophy is also believed to have influenced some 20th century [[modernists]], such as [[D.H. Lawrence]], [[William Faulkner]] and [[Charles Olson]].{{Fact|date=February 2007}}
+
Whitehead's influence was not restricted to philosophers, physicists and mathematicians.  
 
 
Several fields of science and especially [[medicine]] seem to make liberal use of ideas in process philosophy, notably the theory of [[Pain and nociception|pain]] and [[healing]] of the late 20th century.  The [[philosophy of medicine]] began to deviate somewhat from [[scientific method]] and an emphasis on repeatable results very late 20th century by embracing [[population thinking]], and a more pragmatic approach to issues in [[public health]], [[environmental health]] and especially [[mental health]].  In this latter field, [[R. D. Laing]], [[Thomas Szasz]] and [[Michel Foucault]] were instrumental in moving medicine away from emphasis on "cures" and towards concepts of individuals in balance with their society, both of which are changing, and against which no benchmarks or finished "cures" were very likely to be measurable.
 
  
In [[psychology]] the subject of imagination was again explored more extensively since Whitehead, and the question of feasibility or "eternal objects" of thought became central to the [[impaired theory of mind]] explorations that framed postmodern [[cognitive science]].  A biological understanding of the most eternal object, that being the emerging of similar but independent cognitive apparatus, led to an obsession with the process "[[embodiment]]", that being, the emergence of these [[cognition]]s.  Like Whitehead's God, especially as elaborated in [[J. J. Gibson]]'s [[perceptual psychology]] emphasizing [[affordance]]s, by ordering the relevance of eternal objects (especially the cognitions of other such actors), the world becomes. Or, it becomes simple enough for human beings to begin to make choices, and to prehend what happens as a resultThese experiences may be summed in some sense but can only approximately be shared, even among very similar cognitions with identical DNA.  An early explorer of this view was [[Alan Turing]] who sought to prove the limits of expressive complexity of human genes in the late 1940s, to put bounds on the complexity of human [[intelligence (trait)|intelligence]] and so assess the feasibility of [[artificial intelligence]] emerging.
+
Several fields of science and especially [[medicine]] seem to make liberal use of ideas in process philosophy, notably the theory of [[Pain and nociception|pain]] and [[healing]] of the late 20th century. The [[philosophy of medicine]] began to deviate somewhat from [[scientific method]] and an emphasis on repeatable results very late 20th century by embracing [[population thinking]], and a more pragmatic approach to issues in [[public health]], [[environmental health]] and especially [[mental health]].  In this latter field, [[R. D. Laing]], [[Thomas Szasz]] and [[Michel Foucault]] were instrumental in moving medicine away from emphasis on "cures" and towards concepts of individuals in balance with their society, both of which are changing, and against which no benchmarks or finished "cures" were very likely to be measurable.
  
In the [[philosophy of mathematics]], some of Whitehead's ideas re-emerged in combination with [[cognitivism]] as the [[cognitive science of mathematics]] and [[embodied mind]] theses.
+
In [[psychology]] the subject of imagination was explored extensively since Whitehead, and the question of feasibility or "eternal objects" of thought became central to the [[impaired theory of mind]] explorations that framed postmodern [[cognitive science]]. A biological understanding of the most eternal object, that being the emerging of similar but independent cognitive apparatus, led to an obsession with the process "[[embodiment]]," that being, the emergence of these [[cognition]]s. Like Whitehead's [[God]], especially as elaborated in [[J. J. Gibson]]'s [[perceptual psychology]] emphasizing [[affordance]]s, by ordering the relevance of eternal objects (especially the cognitions of other such actors), the world becomes. Or, it becomes simple enough for human beings to begin to make choices, and to prehend what happens as a result. These experiences may be summed in some sense but can only approximately be shared, even among very similar cognitions of persons with identical DNA. An early explorer of this view was [[Alan Turing]] who sought to prove the limits of expressive complexity of human genes in the late 1940s, to put bounds on the complexity of human [[intelligence (trait)|intelligence]] and so assess the feasibility of [[artificial intelligence]] emerging.
  
Somewhat earlier, exploration of [[mathematical practice]] and [[quasi-empiricism in mathematics]] from the 1950s to 1980s had sought alternatives to [[metamathematics]] in social behaviours around [[mathematics]] itself:  for instance, [[Paul Erdos]]' simultaneous belief in [[Platonism]] and a single "big book" in which all proofs existed, combined with his personal obsessive need or decision to collaborate with the widest possible number of other mathematicians.  The process, rather than the outcomes, seemed to drive his explicit behaviour and odd use of language, e.g. he called God the "Supreme Fascist", echoing the role Whitehead assigned, as if the synthesis of Erdos and collaborators in seeking proofs, creating sense-datum for other mathematicians, was itself the expression of a divine will. Certainly, Erdos behaved as if nothing else in the world mattered, including money or love, as emphasized in his biography ''[[The Man Who Loved Only Numbers]]''.
+
In the [[philosophy of mathematics]], some of Whitehead's ideas re-emerged in combination with [[cognitivism]] as the [[cognitive science of mathematics]] and [[embodied mind]] theses.
  
 
==Process Theology==
 
==Process Theology==
  
'''Process theology''' (also known as '''neoclassical theology''') is a school of thought influenced by the metaphysical [[process philosophy]] of [[Alfred North Whitehead]] (1861–1947). Process theology is unrelated to the [[Process Church]].  
+
Because Whitehead's philosophy attributed the foundational role to [[God]], he influenced the field of theology most prominently. ''Process theology'' was developed by prominent advocates including [[Charles Hartshorne]], [[John B. Cobb, Jr.]], [[Hans Jonas]], [[Schubert Ogden]], and [[David Ray Griffin]]. These theologians teach that Whitehead's God could overcome problems generated by defining God with the static conceptions prevalent in Western culture, and overcome the apparent dualism of science and religion.
  
 
The concepts of process theology include:
 
The concepts of process theology include:
* [[God]] is not [[omnipotent]] in the sense of being [[coercive]]. The divine has a power of persuasion rather than force. Process theologians have often seen the classical doctrine of omnipotence as involving coercion, and themselves claim something more restricted than the classical doctrine.  "Persuasion" in the causal sense means that God does not exert unilateral control.
+
* [[God]] is not [[omnipotent]] in the sense of being [[coercive]]. The divine has a power of [[persuasion]] rather than force. Process theologians have often seen the classical doctrine of omnipotence as involving coercion, and themselves claim something more restricted than the classical doctrine.  "Persuasion" in the causal sense means that God does not exert unilateral control.
 
* Reality is not made up of material substances that endure through time, but serially-ordered events, which are experiential in nature.  These events have both a physical and mental aspect. All experience (male, female, atomic, and botanical) is important and contributes to the ongoing and interrelated process of reality.
 
* Reality is not made up of material substances that endure through time, but serially-ordered events, which are experiential in nature.  These events have both a physical and mental aspect. All experience (male, female, atomic, and botanical) is important and contributes to the ongoing and interrelated process of reality.
* The universe is characterized by process and change carried out by the agents of [[free will]]. [[Self-determination]] characterizes everything in the [[universe]], not just human beings. God cannot totally control any series of events or any individual, but God influences the creaturely exercise of this universal free will by offering possibilities. To say it another way, God has a will in everything, but not everything that occurs is God's will.
+
* The universe is characterized by process and change carried out by the agents of [[free will]]. [[Self-determination]] characterizes everything in the [[universe]], not just human beings. God cannot totally control any series of events or any individual, but God influences the exercise of universal free will by offering possibilities. In other words, God has a will in everything, but not everything that occurs is God's will.
* God contains the universe but is not identical with it ([[panentheism]], not [[pantheism]]). Some also call this "theocosmocentrism" to emphasize that God has always been related to some world or another.
+
* God contains the universe but is not identical with it ([[panentheism]], not [[pantheism]]). Some also call this "theocosmocentrism" to emphasize that God has always been related to some world or another.
 
* Because God interacts with the changing universe, God is changeable (that is to say, God is affected by the actions that take place in the universe) over the course of time.  However, the abstract elements of God ([[Goodness and value theory|goodness]], [[wisdom]], etc.) remain eternally solid.
 
* Because God interacts with the changing universe, God is changeable (that is to say, God is affected by the actions that take place in the universe) over the course of time.  However, the abstract elements of God ([[Goodness and value theory|goodness]], [[wisdom]], etc.) remain eternally solid.
* [[Charles Hartshorne]] believes that people do not experience '''subjective''' (or personal) [[immortality]], but they do have '''objective''' immortality because their experiences live on forever in God, who contains all that was. Others believe that people do have subjective experience after bodily death.
+
* [[Charles Hartshorne]] believes that people do not experience '''subjective''' (or personal) [[immortality]], but they do have '''objective''' immortality because their experiences live on forever in God, who contains all that is and was. Others believe that people do have subjective experience after bodily death.
 
* [[Dipolar theism]], is the idea that God has both a changing aspect (God's existence as a Living God) and an unchanging aspect (God's eternal essence).
 
* [[Dipolar theism]], is the idea that God has both a changing aspect (God's existence as a Living God) and an unchanging aspect (God's eternal essence).
  
The original ideas of process thought are found in the philosophy of Alfred North Whitehead.  Various theological and philosophical aspects have been expanded and developed by Charles Hartshorne (1897–2000), [[John B. Cobb]], and [[David Ray Griffin]].
+
Process theology influenced a number of [[Judaism|Jewish]] theologians including [[Australian]] philosopher Samuel Alexander (1859-1938), and [[Rabbi]]s Max Kaddushin, Milton Steinberg and Levi A. Olan, Harry Slominsky and to a lesser degree, [[Abraham Joshua Heschel]]. Today some rabbis who advocate some form of process theology include Donald B. Rossoff, [[William E. Kaufman]], [[Harold Kushner]], [[Anton Laytner]], [[Gilbert S. Rosenthal]], [[Lawrence Troster]] and [[Nahum Ward]].
 
 
Process theology soon influenced a number of [[Judaism|Jewish]] theologians including [[Australian]] philosopher Samuel Alexander (1859-1938), and [[Rabbi]]s Max Kaddushin, Milton Steinberg and Levi A. Olan, Harry Slominsky and to a lesser degree, [[Abraham Joshua Heschel]]. Today some rabbis who advocate some form of process theology include Donald B. Rossoff, [[William E. Kaufman]], [[Harold Kushner]], [[Anton Laytner]], [[Gilbert S. Rosenthal]], [[Lawrence Troster]] and [[Nahum Ward]].
 
 
 
Alan Anderson and [[Deb Whitehouse]] have attempted to integrate process theology with the [[New Thought Movement|New Thought]] variant of [[Christianity]].
 
  
[[Thomas Jay Oord]] integrates process theology with evangelical, openness, and Wesleyan theologies.  Oord argues that it is part of God's essence as relational to provide freedom to others.  This loving act means that God cannot withdraw or override the freedom of others, but this inability is part of who God is and not imposed by outside forces or conditions.
 
  
==Process theologians==
 
{|width=100%
 
|-valign=top
 
|width=33%|
 
*[[Charles Birch]]
 
*[[John B. Cobb]]
 
*[[Paul S. Fiddes]]
 
*[[Lewis S. Ford]]
 
*[[Stephen T. Franklin]]
 
|width=33%|
 
*[[David Ray Griffin]]
 
*[[Charles Hartshorne]]
 
*[[Nancy R. Howell]]
 
*[[William E. Kaufman]]
 
*[[Harold Kushner]]
 
|width=33%|
 
*[[Thomas Jay Oord]]
 
*[[Marjorie Hewitt Suchocki]]
 
*[[Alfred North Whitehead]]
 
*[[Daniel Day Williams]]
 
|}
 
  
 
==Notes==
 
==Notes==
Line 134: Line 109:
  
 
== External links ==
 
== External links ==
*[http://www.processnetwork.org International Process Network]
+
*[http://www.processnetwork.org International Process Network]. Retrieved March 29, 2007.
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/process-philosophy/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/process-philosophy/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry]. Retrieved March 29, 2007.
* [http://www.ctr4process.org The Center for Process Studies]
+
* [http://www.ctr4process.org The Center for Process Studies]. Retrieved March 29, 2007.
* [http://www.processandfaith.org Process and Faith]
+
* [http://www.processandfaith.org Process and Faith]. Retrieved March 29, 2007.
* [http://groups.msn.com/judaismfaqs/processtheologybetweensupernaturalismandnaturalism.msnw Process theology and Judaism]
+
* [http://neweverymoment.com Process theology and the New Thought movement]. Retrieved March 29, 2007.
* [http://neweverymoment.com Process theology and the New Thought movement]
 
* [http://newmysticjourney.org  Center for the Study of Cosmic Spirituality]
 
  
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]

Revision as of 19:54, 29 March 2007

Process thought, also known as process philosophy or process theology, is a system of thought with its fundamental description in Alfred North Whitehead's Process and Reality (1929). Process thought sees all of reality as one interconnected whole; and Whitehead's background in biology, mathematics and philosophy enabled him to develop a unified worldview in which religion and science are harmonized.

For Whitehead an "actual entity" is a "unit of concresence," i.e., the coming together of all that precedes an entity to make it what it is at that particular instant. Then fades into the past, as it become the basis for the next actual entity in its immediate future.[1] We know each instant as a unified "drop of experience." This experience is more primary than the physical entities in which the experience resides (e.g., our brains). Consciousness and subconscious experience exists in all life at different levels, and is pushing the universe forward toward ever higher expressions of creativity and awareness. God, who is the foundation of all experience, "prehends" all existence with perfect knowledge and perfect love[2] and pushes each actual entity forward through persuasion (not coercion).

Charles Hartshorne, an assistant to Whitehead at Harvard University, continued to develop Whitehead's metaphysics at the University of Chicago where he influenced two theologians, John B. Cobb, Jr. and Schubert Ogden who developed process theology to a status with influence comparable to liberation theology.

Process theologians have found extensive common ground with Buddhists and their conception of God as cosmic consciousness, not a physical substance. They have also contributed uniquely to discussions of evolution because they understand reality as an evolution of the universe, not on the basis of "survival of the fittest," but as a goad[3] to a future with ever-higher and more complex modes of expression and experiences of joy and "feeling."

Earlier forms of process thought

Various forms of thought that emphasize process exist in history and in other cultures. While these are not specifically related to the school of thought developed by Whitehead, they contain various efforts to explain life in terms of change, growth, and flux. Elements of a process philosophy begin in Western thought with Heraclitus' fragments in which he posits the noumenon (not to be confused with Kant's "Ding an sich"), the ground of becoming, as agon or "strife of opposites" as the underlying basis of all reality defined by change.

Much later, Aristotle's concept of moderation, which parallels the concept in Buddhism (the two are almost contemporaries) establishes goodness or value as a function of a process in which extremes are avoided. The process, not the outcome, is the ultimate good. The Noble Eightfold Path may be the clearest expression of this principle in any religion before modern times. More monastic traditions in both East and West tended to emphasize the process of enlightenment, often interpreted quite literally as leaving the (heavy) body behind, especially among Roman Catholic monks. Historically, however, the Eastern traditions were more forgiving of temporary failures of will as long as they were in fact temporary. Many Buddhist and Taoist stories emphasize the value of quickly returning to one's disciplined state after a breach, and even forgetting it had occurred. Yoga-related disciplines also avoid any explicit goal-setting or measures of success. Eastern traditions almost universally invoke the concept of balance which implies multiple and contradictory pressures in, as Heraclitus suggested, ongoing "strife."

Process philosophy was not totally neglected during The Enlightenment. René Descartes, for instance, proposed that the mind and body were actually connected and unified by a single process, the imagination. This idea was often discarded or devalued by Descartes' followers and critics who attributed to him (incorrectly) advocating a mind-body dualism. Very similarly, the law of the excluded middle was raised to ontological status by those of Aristotle's followers, notably those practicing medieval scholasticism, who wished to ignore some of his telling observations about moderation (the very ones that Francis Bacon celebrated) and rhetoric (which Aristotle praised, seemingly foreshadowing Descartes' imagination).

A number of other key Enlightenment figures, including those instrumental in the scientific method (especially Isaac Newton, obsessed with dreams and famously inspired by daily events, and Galileo Galilei, pioneer of diagnostic dialogue) made note of their working processes in terms that suggest change is what they seek to quantify because it is the most fundamental basis on which perception and thus reality proceeds. George Berkeley criticized Newton specifically for straying from this view and holding forth that certain objects existed, as opposed to perception suggesting they did.

By the 19th century, these views were coalescing and combining with newer sciences, most notably electromagnetism in physics and theories of harmony in music. John Keely held, in an early version of the Wave-particle duality, that all particles were outcomes of a change, one often analogized to the whitecaps upon a wave on the rolling sea: they are not themselves reasonably characterized as objects, only consequences of a change.

Of other philosophers, more dominant at that time, Immanuel Kant noted that either experience made objects possible, or objects made experience possible. He didn't consider that processes might make both possible. Gottfried Leibniz's monads were not related to all other occasions of experience that preceded them. Reductionism was in vogue—to reduce processes (say into tasks or events) was more difficult than reducing objects. In the management science of Frederick Taylor however there was emerging a view of infinitely reducible work processes and an ontology limited to "practical" tasks - later to come into bloom with total quality management and the "six sigma" goal.

Influences on Whitehead

Whitehead's background was a very unusual one for a speculative metaphysician. Educated as a mathematician, he became, through his coauthorship and 1913 publication of Principia Mathematica' with Bertrand Russell, a major logician. Later he wrote extensively on physics and its philosophy, proposing a theory of relativity rivaling Einstein's - see relativity. He was conversant with the quantum mechanics that emerged in the 1920s. Whitehead did not begin teaching and writing on process and metaphysics until he moved to Harvard at 63 years of age.

In 1905, the theory of general relativity had curtailed exploration of pure process views and made the case for a specific and expanding universe that existed as an objective object of our human perception and cognition. This view was attractive if only for simplicity. The curiously fixed speed of light provided the basis on which a number or limit, rather than a process, could be said to be defining reality itself, at least as perceivable by beings similar to ourselves. At the same time, a philosophy of mathematics was developing that could be specified as a set of axioms, again, a fixed not process-oriented description.

These hopes proved vain, although it remained for Russell and Whitehead to prove that so in 1913, after which Whitehead elaborated what had been learned from attempts to escape process as the basis of ontology. This resulted in the most famous work of process philosophy Process and Reality.

Hegel's dialectical thought is said by some to have influenced Whitehead. In both philosophers, the "absolute" is a movement in and through determinates, not the essence of the determinates, which are fixed concepts or "things." However, Hegel proposed an ontology of the relationship between opposites that form the basis for a synthesis which is the new state of reality. The method was a "struggle" of opposites—picked up by Marx as justification for the struggle of workers against capitalists to create a higher form of society. This might fit, to some extent, with Darwin's notion of "survival of the fittest." Hegel nonetheless, failed to make process an absolute when he called the State as a telos—the end-state of the "march of the Absolute through history."

Whitehead, on the other hand, saw experience as a complex unity of all that "ingressed" into a unit of experience. A dialectic between two poles, might be a simple way of employing logic by an observer, but it does not properly represent the wholeness of experience. Further there is no end-state, there is only ongoing process. For Whitehead, "survival of the fittest" is not the reason for increased complexity of species, but increased complexity develops because it provides the basis for increased richness in feeling. It is the thirst for increased richness of feeling and joy that stimulates creativity and lays at the basis of evolution, not a struggle between two opposites.

Whitehead was also influenced by the French philosopher Henri-Louis Bergson (1859-1941), who was awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature in 1927.

Whitehead's Process and Reality

In his major work on process philosophy, Process and Reality, Whitehead stated that the entire European philosophical tradition consists of "a series of footnotes to Plato."[4] In Plato and Aristotle resided elements that could have developed into a "philosophy or organism" (see above), in which the temporal and the timeless, the actual and the potential, the eternal and the concrete coexisted. However, Western philosophy has more often excluded the organic nature of reality, and modern philosophy has focused material substances as the basis of reality. The thoughtworld of the west became a bridgeless chasm between fact and value, between science and religion. Whitehead, as a mathematician, could see how what we often view as abstractions from reality can instead be the foundation of reality.

The process metaphysics elaborated in Process and Reality proposes that the fundamental elements of the universe are actual entities which exist as the coming together, or "nexus" of a complex string of previous entities into an new occasion, or event. What people commonly think of as concrete objects are actually transient successions of events where entities exist momentarily. This process is guided by a primordial "occasions of experience" present in each actual entity. Occasions of experience can be complex, like the experience of individual human beings, or smaller occasions of experience in tadpoles or plants.

The relationship to other entities is felt as a "prehension," a term similar to what we think of as subconscious awareness. According to Whitehead, everything in the universe is characterized by experience (which is not to be confused with consciousness); there is no mind-body duality under this system, because "mind" simply relates to a very advanced kind of experiencing. Whitehead's philosophy is a form of panpsychism.

Whitehead's philosophy resembles in some respects the monads of Leibniz. However, unlike Leibniz's monads, Whitehead's occasions of experience are interrelated with every other occasion of experience that precedes it in time. Inherent in Whitehead's philosophy is the notion of time; all experiences are influenced by prior experiences, and will influence all future experiences. This process of influencing is never deterministic; God did not set a machine in motion and leave.

In every occasion of experience there exists a prehending of other experiences, and then a response to them. This is the process in process philosophy. Because no process is ever deterministic, free will and creativity are essential to and inherent in the universe. Each "prehension" is the basis for a subjective harmony and a valuation which includes a subjective aim at greater intensity of feeling in a future event. This is the basis for novelty and the organic development of all experience.

God, for Whitehead[5] is present in all actual entities via ingression of "eternal objects." While God is the primordial creature, He is not limited to His primordial nature. God derives a "consequent nature" from his "physical prehension of derivative actual entities." God is present in all occasions; thus Whitehead promotes a form of panentheism. Further, God experiences growth and change; God himself is in process.

Since, Whitehead argues, free will is inherent to the nature of the universe, God is not a powerful master that commands us to serve him. Rather, God offers goads us toward higher forms of experience, with greater intensity of feeling and joy. God participates in the evolution of the universe by offering possibilities, which may be accepted or rejected.

Whitehead enumerated three essential natures of God. The primordial nature of God consists of all potentialities of existence for actual occasions, which Whitehead called eternal objects. God can offer possibilities by ordering the relevance of eternal objects. The consequent nature of God prehends everything that happens in reality. As such, God experiences all of reality in a sentient manner. The last nature is the superjective. This is the way in which God’s synthesis becomes a sense-datum for other actual entities. In this sense, God is prehended or felt by other existing actual entities. In Christian terms, this prehension of God may be through the spiritual senses.

Process philosophy since Whitehead

Whitehead's influence was not restricted to philosophers, physicists and mathematicians.

Several fields of science and especially medicine seem to make liberal use of ideas in process philosophy, notably the theory of pain and healing of the late 20th century. The philosophy of medicine began to deviate somewhat from scientific method and an emphasis on repeatable results very late 20th century by embracing population thinking, and a more pragmatic approach to issues in public health, environmental health and especially mental health. In this latter field, R. D. Laing, Thomas Szasz and Michel Foucault were instrumental in moving medicine away from emphasis on "cures" and towards concepts of individuals in balance with their society, both of which are changing, and against which no benchmarks or finished "cures" were very likely to be measurable.

In psychology the subject of imagination was explored extensively since Whitehead, and the question of feasibility or "eternal objects" of thought became central to the impaired theory of mind explorations that framed postmodern cognitive science. A biological understanding of the most eternal object, that being the emerging of similar but independent cognitive apparatus, led to an obsession with the process "embodiment," that being, the emergence of these cognitions. Like Whitehead's God, especially as elaborated in J. J. Gibson's perceptual psychology emphasizing affordances, by ordering the relevance of eternal objects (especially the cognitions of other such actors), the world becomes. Or, it becomes simple enough for human beings to begin to make choices, and to prehend what happens as a result. These experiences may be summed in some sense but can only approximately be shared, even among very similar cognitions of persons with identical DNA. An early explorer of this view was Alan Turing who sought to prove the limits of expressive complexity of human genes in the late 1940s, to put bounds on the complexity of human intelligence and so assess the feasibility of artificial intelligence emerging.

In the philosophy of mathematics, some of Whitehead's ideas re-emerged in combination with cognitivism as the cognitive science of mathematics and embodied mind theses.

Process Theology

Because Whitehead's philosophy attributed the foundational role to God, he influenced the field of theology most prominently. Process theology was developed by prominent advocates including Charles Hartshorne, John B. Cobb, Jr., Hans Jonas, Schubert Ogden, and David Ray Griffin. These theologians teach that Whitehead's God could overcome problems generated by defining God with the static conceptions prevalent in Western culture, and overcome the apparent dualism of science and religion.

The concepts of process theology include:

  • God is not omnipotent in the sense of being coercive. The divine has a power of persuasion rather than force. Process theologians have often seen the classical doctrine of omnipotence as involving coercion, and themselves claim something more restricted than the classical doctrine. "Persuasion" in the causal sense means that God does not exert unilateral control.
  • Reality is not made up of material substances that endure through time, but serially-ordered events, which are experiential in nature. These events have both a physical and mental aspect. All experience (male, female, atomic, and botanical) is important and contributes to the ongoing and interrelated process of reality.
  • The universe is characterized by process and change carried out by the agents of free will. Self-determination characterizes everything in the universe, not just human beings. God cannot totally control any series of events or any individual, but God influences the exercise of universal free will by offering possibilities. In other words, God has a will in everything, but not everything that occurs is God's will.
  • God contains the universe but is not identical with it (panentheism, not pantheism). Some also call this "theocosmocentrism" to emphasize that God has always been related to some world or another.
  • Because God interacts with the changing universe, God is changeable (that is to say, God is affected by the actions that take place in the universe) over the course of time. However, the abstract elements of God (goodness, wisdom, etc.) remain eternally solid.
  • Charles Hartshorne believes that people do not experience subjective (or personal) immortality, but they do have objective immortality because their experiences live on forever in God, who contains all that is and was. Others believe that people do have subjective experience after bodily death.
  • Dipolar theism, is the idea that God has both a changing aspect (God's existence as a Living God) and an unchanging aspect (God's eternal essence).

Process theology influenced a number of Jewish theologians including Australian philosopher Samuel Alexander (1859-1938), and Rabbis Max Kaddushin, Milton Steinberg and Levi A. Olan, Harry Slominsky and to a lesser degree, Abraham Joshua Heschel. Today some rabbis who advocate some form of process theology include Donald B. Rossoff, William E. Kaufman, Harold Kushner, Anton Laytner, Gilbert S. Rosenthal, Lawrence Troster and Nahum Ward.


Notes

  1. Alfred North Whitehead, Process and Reality, pp. 18-30.
  2. John B.Cobb, Jr., Process Theology as Political Theology, p. 57.
  3. There has been some controversy over changing the term "goal" to "goad" on p. 88 of the corrected edition by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne. While the authors feel it is more consistent with Whitehead's philosophy, it has been a challenge to those traditional theologians who believe God has a specific telos in mind. However, process theology affirms that God also changes and grows, striving for ever greater joy.
  4. Process and Reality, p. 39.
  5. Process and Reality, p. 31ff.

Bibliography

  • Cobb, John B., Jr., A Christian Natural Theology, Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1965. ISBN 0664242286
  • Cobb, John B., Jr., Doubting Thomas, 1990. ISBN 082451033X
  • Cobb, John B., Jr., God and the World, Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1969. ISBN 0664248608
  • Cobb, John B., Jr., Process Theology and Political Theology, Philadelphia: Westminster Press, 1982. ISBN 0664244173
  • Cobb, John B., Jr. and David Ray Griffin, Process Theology: An Introductory Exposition, Philadelphia, Westminster Press, 1976. ISBN 0664247431
  • Cobb, John B., Jr. and W. Widick Schroeder, eds., Process Philosophy and Social Thought, Chicago: Center for the Scientific Study of Religion, 1981. ISBN 091334818X
  • Fiddes, Paul S., The Creative Suffering of God, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992.
  • Fiddes, Paul S., 'Process Theology', in A. E. McGrath, ed., The Blackwell Encyclopedia of Modern Christian Thought, Oxford: Blackwell, 1993, pp. 472–6.
  • Hartshorne, Charles, Omnipotence and Other Theological Mistakes, State University of New York Press, 1984. ISBN 0873957717
  • Kaufman, William E., A Question of Faith: An Atheist and a Rabbi Debate the Existence of God, 1994. ISBN 1568210892
  • Kaufman, William E., The Case for God, 1991. ISBN 0827204582
  • Kushner, Harold, When Bad Things Happen to Good People, 1981. ISBN 1400034728

Leclerc, Ivor, Whitehead's Metaphysics: And Introductory Exposition, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1975, ISBN 0253201810

  • Lubarsky, Sandra B. and David Ray Griffin, Jewish Theology and Process Thought, 1995. ISBN 0791428109
  • Mesle, C. Robert, Process Theology: A Basic Introduction (1993, ISBN 0-8272-2945-3) is an introduction to process theology written for the layperson.
  • Ogden, Schubert M., The Reality of God and Other Essays, SMU Press, 1992. ISBN 087074318X
  • Stone, Bryan P. and Thomas Jay Oord, Thy Nature and Thy Name is Love: Wesleyan and Process Theologies in Dialogue, Nashville: Kingswood, 2001. ISBN 0687052203
  • Suchocki, Marjorie Hewitt, God Christ Church: A Practical Guide to Process Theology 1989. ISBN 0824509706
  • Whitehead, Alfred North, Adventures of Ideas, New York, Macmillan, 1933.
  • Whitehead, Alfred North, Process and Reality, Corrected edition edited by David Ray Griffin and Donald W. Sherburne, New York: Free Press, 1978. ISBN 0029345707
  • Whitehead, Alfred North, Science and the Modern World, New York, Macmillan, 1925.
  • Whitehead, Alfred North, Symbolism: Its Meaning and Effect, New York, Macmillan, 1959. ISBN 0399502319
  • Whitehead, Alfred North, The Aims of Education and other Essays, New York: Macmillan, 1929.


External links


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.