Bergson, Henri

From New World Encyclopedia
m (Robot: Remove date links)
 
(17 intermediate revisions by 7 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Contracted}}
+
{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{copyedited}}
:''See also [[Bergson (disambiguation)]]:''
+
{{epname|Bergson, Henri}}
----
+
'''Henri-Louis Bergson''' (October 18, 1859 – January 4, 1941) was a major French [[philosopher ]] in the first half of the twentieth century. He was widely popular during his lifetime and his lectures in Paris were attended not only by philosophers and students, but also by artists, theologians, social theorists, and even the general public. At the core of his philosophy is his theory of “duration,” which he understands to be the ultimate and irreducible reality. Although Bergson understood duration to be the unified flow of [[time]] or becoming, he fought hard against all mechanistic and naturalistic interpretations of this temporal flux. Rather, he argued that duration is the ''élan vital'' or vital force of life, which evolves not as a result of brute forces (as in [[Darwinian evolution]]) but in a spontaneous and creative way. This “creative evolution,” which is basically free, is what allows for different forms of life to emerge. Methodologically Bergson argued that the ''élan vital'' of duration cannot be apprehended by the rational intellect or conceptual understanding but instead through [[intuition]]. Only in intuition can one enter into this passing of time and so experience at the concrete level the flux of becoming as the ultimate reality.
[[Image:henri_Bergson.jpg|thumb|right|Henri Bergson]]
+
{{toc}}
'''Henri-Louis Bergson''' ([[October 18]], 1859 – [[January 4]], 1941) was a major [[France|French]] [[Philosophy|philosopher]], influential in the first half of the 20th century.
 
 
 
 
==Biography==
 
==Biography==
===Overview===
+
===Early years===
Bergson was born in the Rue Lamartine in [[Paris]], not far from the [[Palais Garnier]] (the old Paris opera house). He was descended from a [[Poles|Polish]] [[Jew]]ish family (originally Berekson) on his father's side, while his mother was from an [[England|English]] and [[Irish people|Irish]] Jewish background. His family lived in [[London]] for a few years after his birth, and he obtained an early familiarity with the [[English language]] from his mother. Before he was nine, his parents crossed the [[English Channel]] and settled in France, Henri becoming a naturalized citizen of the Republic. His sister, Mina Bergson (also known as Moina Mathers), married the English [[List of occult authors|occult author]] [[Samuel Liddell MacGregor Mathers]], a leader of the [[Hermetic Order of the Golden Dawn]], and the couple later relocated to Paris as well.
+
Bergson was born on October 18, 1859, in the ''Rue Lamartine,'' in Paris. Both his parents were Jewish, but while his father, a musician, came from a Polish background, his mother was English. His family lived in London for a few years after his birth, but before he was nine, his parents crossed the English Channel and settled in France. It was there that the young Henri became a naturalized citizen of the Republic.  
 
 
Bergson lived the quiet and uneventful life of a French professor. Its chief landmarks were the publication of his four principal works: first, in 1889, the ''[[Time and Free Will]]'' (Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience), then ''[[Matter and Memory]]'' (Matière et mémoire) in 1896, ''[[Creative Evolution]]'' (L'Evolution créatrice) in 1907 and finally ''[[The Two Sources of Morality and Religion]]'' (Les deux sources de la morale et de la religion) in 1932.
 
 
 
=== Education and career ===
 
Bergson attended the ''Lycée Fontaine'' (now known as the ''[[Lycée Condorcet]]'') in Paris from 1868 to 1878. While there he won a prize for his scientific work and another, in 1877 when he was eighteen, for the solution of a mathematical problem. His solution was published the following year in ''[[Annales de Mathématiques]].'' It was his first published work. After some hesitation as to whether his career should lie in the sphere of the sciences or that of the [[humanities]], he decided in favour of the latter, and when nineteen years of age, he entered the famous ''[[École Normale Supérieure]]''. He obtained there the degree of ''[[Licence-ès-Lettres]]'', and this was followed by that of ''[[agrégation|Agrégation de philosophie]]'' in 1881.
 
 
 
The same year he received a teaching appointment at the ''[[Lycée]]'' in [[Angers]], the ancient capital of [[Anjou]]. Two years later he settled at the ''[[Lycée Blaise-Pascal]]'' in [[Clermont-Ferrand]], capital of the [[Puy-de-Dôme]] [[département in France|département]], a town whose name is usually more of interest for motorists than for philosophers, being the home of [[Michelin]] tyres and the [[Charade Circuit]] racing track.
 
 
 
The year after his arrival at [[Clermont-Ferrand]] Bergson displayed his ability in the humanities by the publication of an excellent edition of extracts from [[Lucretius]], with a critical study of the text and the philosophy of the poet (1884), a work whose repeated editions are sufficient evidence of its useful place in the promotion of classical study among the youth of France. While teaching and lecturing in this part of his country (the [[Auvergne (province)|Auvergne]] region), Bergson found time for private study and original work. He was working on his essay ''Time and Free Will'', which was submitted, along with a short [[Latin]] thesis on [[Aristotle]], for the degree of ''[[Docteur-ès-Lettres]]'', which was awarded by the [[University of Paris]] in 1889. The work was published in the same year by [[Felix Alcan]], the Paris publisher.
 
 
 
Bergson dedicated ''Time and Free Will'' to [[Jules Lachelier]], then public education minister, who was a disciple of [[Felix Ravaisson]] and the author of a rather important philosophical work ''On the Founding of Induction'' (Du fondement de l'induction, 1871). Lachelier endeavoured "to substitute everywhere force for inertia, life for death, and liberty for fatalism." (Lachelier was born in 1832, Ravaisson in 1813. Bergson owed much to both of these teachers of the ''Ecole Normale Supérieure''. Cf. his memorial address on Ravaisson, who died in 1900.)
 
 
 
Bergson settled again in Paris, and after teaching for some months at the [[Municipal College]], known as the ''College Rollin'', he received an appointment at the [[Lycée Henri-Quatre]], where he remained for eight years. In 1896 he published his second large work, entitled ''Matter and Memory''. This rather difficult, but brilliant, work investigates the function of the brain, undertakes an analysis of [[perception]] and [[memory]], leading up to a careful consideration of the problems of the relation of body and mind. Bergson had spent years of research in preparation for each of his three large works. This is especially obvious in ''Matter and Memory'', where he showed a thorough acquaintance with the extensive pathological investigations which had been carried out during the period.
 
 
 
In 1898 Bergson became ''[[Maître de conférences]]'' at his [[Alma Mater]], ''L'Ecole Normale Supérieure'', and was later promoted to a Professorship. The year 1900 saw him installed as Professor at the [[Collège de France]], where he accepted the Chair of [[Greek Philosophy]] in succession to [[Charles L'Eveque]].
 
 
 
At the [[First International Congress of Philosophy]], held in Paris during the first five days of August, 1900, Bergson read a short, but important, paper, "Psychological Origins of the Belief in the Law of Causality" (Sur les origines psychologiques de notre croyance à la loi de causalité). In 1901 [[Felix Alcan]] published a work which had previously appeared in the [[Revue de Paris]], entitled ''[[Laughter (Bergson)|Laughter]]'' (Le rire), one of the most important of Bergson's minor productions. This essay on the meaning of comedy was based on a lecture which he had given in his early days in the Auvergne. The study of it is essential to an understanding of Bergson's views of life, and its passages dealing with the place of the artistic in life are valuable. The main thesis of the work is that [[laughter]] is a corrective evolved to make social life possible for human beings. We laugh at people who fail to adapt to the demands of society, if it seems their failure is akin to an inflexible mechanism. [[comedy|Comic]] authors have exploited this human tendency to laugh in various ways, and what is common to them is the idea that the comic consists in there being "something mechanical in something living".
 
 
 
In 1901 Bergson was elected to the [[Académie des sciences morales et politiques]], and became a member of the Institute. In 1903 he contributed to the ''Revue de metaphysique et de morale'' a very important essay entitled ''[[Introduction to Metaphysics]]'' (Introduction à la metaphysique), which is useful as a preface to the study of his three large books.
 
 
 
On the death of [[Gabriel Tarde]], the eminent sociologist, in 1904, Bergson succeeded him in the Chair of Modern Philosophy. From the 4th to the 8th of September of that year he was at [[Geneva]] attending the [[Second International Congress of Philosophy]], when he lectured on ''The Mind and Thought: A Philosophical Illusion'' (Le cerveau et la pensée: une illusion philosophique). An illness prevented his visiting [[Germany]] to attend the [[Third International Congress of Philosophy|Third Congress]] held at [[Heidelberg]].
 
 
 
His third major work, ''Creative Evolution'', appeared in 1907, and is undoubtedly the most widely known and most discussed. It constitutes one of the most profound and original contributions to the philosophical consideration of the [[theory of evolution]]. Imbart de la Tour remarked that ''Creative Evolution'' was a milestone of new direction in thought. By 1918, [[Alcan]], the publisher, had issued twenty-one editions, making an average of two editions per annum for ten years. Following the appearance of this book, Bergson's popularity increased enormously, not only in academic circles, but among the general reading public.
 
 
 
=== Relationship with James and Pragmatism ===
 
Bergson came to London in 1908 and visited [[William James]], the [[Harvard]] philosopher who was Bergson's senior by seventeen years, and who was instrumental in calling the attention of the Anglo-American public to the work of the French professor. James's impression of Bergson is given in his Letters under date of [[October 4]], 1908. "So modest and unpretending a man but such a genius intellectually! I have the strongest suspicions that the tendency which he has brought to a focus, will end by prevailing, and that the present epoch will be a sort of turning point in the history of philosophy."
 
 
 
As early as 1880 James had contributed an article in French to the periodical ''La Critique philosophique'', of Renouvier and Pillon, entitled ''[[Le Sentiment de l'Effort]]''. Four years later a couple of articles by him appeared in Mind: "What is an Emotion?" and "On some Omissions of Introspective Psychology." Of these articles the first two were quoted by Bergson in his 1889 work, ''Time and Free Will''. In the following years 1890-91 appeared the two volumes of James's monumental work, [[The Principles of Psychology]], in which he refers to a pathological phenomenon observed by Bergson. Some writers, taking merely these dates into consideration and overlooking the fact that James's investigations had been proceeding since 1870 (registered from time to time by various articles which culminated in "The Principles"), have mistakenly dated Bergson's ideas as earlier than James's.
 
 
 
It has been suggested that Bergson owes the root ideas of his first book to the 1884 article by James, "On Some Omissions of Introspective Psychology," which he neither refers to nor quotes. This article deals with the conception of thought as a [[stream of consciousness]], which [[intellect]] distorts by framing into concepts. Bergson replied to this insinuation by denying that he had any knowledge of the article by James when he wrote ''Les données immédiates de la conscience''. The two thinkers appear to have developed independently until almost the close of the century. They are further apart in their intellectual position than is frequently supposed. Both have succeeded in appealing to audiences far beyond the purely academic sphere, but only in their mutual rejection of "intellectualism" as final is there real unanimity. Although James was slightly ahead in the development and enunciation of his ideas, he confessed that he was baffled by many of Bergson's notions. James certainly neglected many of the deeper metaphysical aspects of Bergson's thought, which did not harmonize with his own, and are even in direct contradiction. In addition to this, Bergson can hardly be considered a pragmatist.  For him, "utility," far from being a test of truth, was in fact the reverse:  a synonym for error.
 
  
Nevertheless, William James hailed Bergson as an ally. Early in the century (1903) he wrote: "I have been re-reading Bergson's books, and nothing that I have read since years has so excited and stimulated my thoughts. I am sure that that philosophy has a great future, it breaks through old cadres and brings things into a solution from which new crystals can be got." The most noteworthy tributes paid by him to Bergson were those made in the [[Hibbert Lectures]] (A Pluralistic Universe), which James gave at [[Manchester College, Oxford]], shortly after meeting Bergson in London. He remarks on the encouragement he has received from Bergson's thought, and refers to the confidence he has in being "able to lean on Bergson's authority."
+
Bergson attended the ''Lycée Fontaine'' in Paris, from 1868 to 1878. In early adulthood he excelled in science and mathematics, winning prizes in both fields. In fact, he won a prize for a solution to a complex mathematical problem that had originally been presented by [[Pascal]]. The solution was published in ''Annales de Mathématiques'' and was Bergson’s first published work. Despite these early accomplishments in the hard sciences, Bergson decided to pursue a career in the humanities. At the age of nineteen he entered the famous ''École Normale Supérieure,'' where he earned the degree of ''Licence-ès-Lettres,'' and later in 1881, the ''Agrégation de philosophie''.
  
The influence of Bergson had led him "to renounce the intellectualist method and the current notion that [[logic]] is an adequate measure of what can or cannot be." It had induced him, he continued, "to give up logic, squarely and irrevocably" as a method, for he found that "reality, life, experience, concreteness, immediacy, use what word you will, exceeds our logic, overflows, and surrounds it."
+
===Professional career===
 +
In 1884, while teaching at Clermont-Ferrand, Bergson published an excellent edition of extracts from [[Lucretius]]. Also, during this period Bergson began what was to become the first of his four major works, ''Time and Free Will'' ''(Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience)''. The work was submitted, along with a short thesis on [[Aristotle’s]] interpretation of Lucretius, for the degree of ''Docteur-ès-Lettres,'' which was awarded by the University of Paris in 1889. After teaching for some months at the Municipal College in Paris, Bergson received an appointment at the ''Lycée Henri-Quatre,'' where he remained for eight years. In 1896, he published his second major work, entitled ''Matter and Memory'' ''(Matière et mémoire)''. This rather difficult but brilliant work explores some of the problems of the mind-body relation. In the work, he considered the function of the brain, particularly as it relates to the cognitive powers of perception and memory.  
  
These remarks, which appeared in James' book ''A Pluralistic Universe'' in 1909, impelled many English and American readers to an investigation of Bergson's philosophy for themselves. A certain handicap existed in that his greatest work had not then been translated into English. James, however, encouraged and assisted Dr. [[Arthur Mitchell]] in his preparation of the English translation of ''Creative Evolution''. In August of 1910 James died. It was his intention, had he lived to see the completion of the translation, to introduce it to the English reading public by a prefatory note of appreciation. In the following year the translation was completed and still greater interest in Bergson and his work was the result. By a coincidence, in that same year (1911), Bergson penned a preface of sixteen pages entitled ''Truth and Reality'' for the French translation of James's book, "Pragmatism". In it he expressed sympathetic appreciation of James's work, coupled with certain important reservations.
+
In 1901, Bergson published a relatively short essay entitled ''Laughter'' ''(Le rire)'', one of the most important of his minor productions. This essay centers upon the meaning of comedy, and it reflects some of the essential aspects of Bergson's views on life. The main thesis of the work is that laughter is a corrective evolved to make social life possible for human beings. People laugh at those who fail to adapt to the demands of society when their failure is a result of an inflexible mechanism. Comic novelists and poets, in particular, exploit this human tendency to laugh at such social misfits by revealing the way "something mechanical” exists “in something living."
  
In April (5th to 11th) Bergson attended the Fourth International Congress of Philosophy held at [[Bologna]], in [[Italy]], where he gave an address on "Philosophical Intuition". In response to invitations he visited England in May of that year, and on several subsequent occasions. These visits were well received. His speeches offered new perspectives and elucidated many passages in his three major works: ''Time and Free Will'', ''Matter and Memory'', and ''Creative Evolution''. Although necessarily brief statements, they developed and enriched the ideas in his books and clarified for English audiences the fundamental principles of his philosophy.
+
In 1903, Bergson wrote a short but important essay entitled ''Introduction to Metaphysics'' ''(Introduction à la metaphysique)'', which serves as a useful preface to the study of his larger works. Bergon’s third and perhaps most important major work, ''Creative Evolution'' (''L'Evolution créatrice'') appeared in 1907. The work was widely known and much discussed, as it offered a profound and original philosophical interpretation of the theory of [[evolution]]. Following the appearance of this book, Bergson's popularity increased enormously, not only in academic circles, but also among the general public. People in a variety of academic, literary, and artistic fields frequented his lectures at the ''Collège de France'' and even tourists would drop in to what became known as “the House of Bergson.
  
=== The lectures on Change, and Bergson's later life ===
+
=== Relationship with James and [[pragmatism]] ===
Bergson visited the [[University of Oxford]], where he delivered two lectures entitled ''The Perception of Change'' (La perception du changement), which were published in French in the same year by the [[Clarendon Press]]. As he had a delightful gift of lucid and brief exposition, when the occasion demands such treatment, these lectures on Change formed a most valuable synopsis or brief survey of the fundamental principles of his thought, and served the student or general reader alike as an excellent introduction to the study of the larger volumes. Oxford honoured its distinguished visitor by conferring upon him the degree of [[Doctor of Science]].  
+
In 1908, Bergson went to London and visited the well-known American philosopher [[William James]]. James had been instrumental in alerting the Anglo-American public to the work of the French professor. In fact, James's impression of Bergson is given in a letter dated October 4, 1908. "So modest and unpretending a man but such a genius intellectually! I have the strongest suspicions that the tendency which he has brought to a focus, will end by prevailing, and that the present epoch will be a sort of turning point in the history of philosophy."
  
Two days later he delivered the [[Huxley Lecture]] at the [[University of Birmingham]], taking for his subject ''Life and Consciousness''. This subsequently appeared in ''[[The Hibbert Journal]]'' (October, 1911), and since revised, forms the first essay in the collected volume ''Mind-Energy'' (L'Energie spirituelle). In October he was again in England, where he had an enthusiastic reception, and delivered at [[University College London]] four lectures on ''La Nature de l'Ame''.  
+
Comparisons are often made between the philosophies of Bergson and James due to the similarities in their work. For example, both thinkers rejected rationalism and materialism in favor of an interpretation of reality as transpiring in a temporal flux. Nevertheless Bergson’s metaphysics went beyond the pragmatism of James and so Bergson argued that [[utility]], far from being a test of truth, was in fact the very source of error. As [[Jean Wahl]] described, the "ultimate disagreement" between James and Bergson: "for James, the consideration of action is necessary for the definition of truth, according to Bergson, action…must be kept from our mind if we want to see the truth.
  
In 1913 he visited the [[United States|United States of America]], at the invitation of [[Columbia University]], [[New York]], and lectured in several American cities, where he was welcomed by very large audiences. In February, at Columbia University, he lectured both in French and English, taking as his subjects: ''Spirituality and Freedom'' and The Method of Philosophy. Being again in England in May of the same year, he accepted the Presidency of the [[British Society for Psychical Research]], and delivered to the Society an impressive address: ''Phantoms of Life and Psychic Research'' (Fantômes des vivants et recherche psychique).
+
=== Later life ===
 +
Bergson visited the United States in 1913, where he lectured in several American cities and was welcomed by large audiences. Shortly thereafter he was elected as a member of the ''Académie française'' and later he delivered the famous Gifford Lectures under the title of ''The Problem of Personality''. In 1927, Bergson won the [[Nobel Prize for Literature]], “in recognition of his rich and vitalizing ideas and the brilliant skill with which they have been presented.
  
Meanwhile, his popularity increased, and translations of his works began to appear in a number of languages: [[English language|English]], [[German language|German]], [[Italian language|Italian]], [[Danish language|Danish]], [[Swedish (language)|Swedish]], [[Hungarian language|Hungarian]], [[Polish language|Polish]] and [[Russian language|Russian]]. In 1914 he was honoured by his fellow-countrymen in being elected as a member of the [[Académie française]]. He was also made President of the Académie des Sciences morales et politiques, and in addition he became Officier de la [[Légion d'honneur]], and Officier de l'Instruction publique.  
+
In 1932, Bergson completed his final major work, ''The Two Sources of Morality and Religion'' ''(Les deux sources de la morale et de la religion)''. Here he extended his philosophical theories to the realms of morality, religion, and art. Although the work was respectfully received by the public and philosophical community, Bergson's influence had by this time begun to fade. He was, however, able to give force to his core beliefs near the end of his life when he renounced all the posts and honors previously received rather than accept exemption from the anti-Semitic laws imposed by the Vichy government. Bergson died on January 4, 1941. He is buried in the ''Cimetière de Garches''.
  
Bergson found disciples of many varied types, and in France movements such as [[Neo-Catholicism]] or [[Modernism]] on the one hand and [[Syndicalism]] on the other, endeavoured to absorb and to appropriate for their own immediate use and propaganda some of the central ideas of his teaching. That important continental organ of socialist and syndicalist theory, ''Le Mouvement [[Socialism|socialiste]]'', suggested that the realism of [[Karl Marx]] and [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]] is hostile to all forms of intellectualism, and that, therefore, supporters of Marxian socialism should welcome a philosophy such as that of Bergson. Other writers, in their eagerness, asserted the collaboration of the Chair of Philosophy at the College de France with the aims of the ''[[Confédération Générale du Travail]]'' and the [[Industrial Workers of the World]]. It was claimed that there is harmony between the flute of personal philosophical meditation and the trumpet of social revolution.
+
== Main philosophical ideas ==
 +
=== Duration ===
 +
Bergson’s philosophy can be viewed as challenging two fundamental positions in the history of philosophy. The first is a [[scientific materialism]] which views all reality as being controlled or determined by mechanical laws or necessities. This view was prominent in the philosophical milieu of the late nineteenth century, in which Bergson had been educated. Although Bergson agreed with certain undeniable aspects of a “philosophy of becoming” such as the biological evolutionism of Darwin, he nevertheless did not hold to the randomness of [[natural selection]] or the interpretation of all order to a brute, biological force. There was for him something more “vital” which animated the process of becoming and which raised it above mechanistic laws.
  
While social revolutionaries were endeavouring to make the most out of Bergson, many leaders of religious thought, particularly the more liberal-minded theologians of all creeds, e.g., the Modernists and Neo-Catholic Party in his own country, showed a keen interest in his writings, and many of them endeavoured to find encouragement and stimulus in his work. The [[Roman Catholic Church]], however, which still believed that finality was reached in philosophy with the work of [[Thomas Aquinas]] in the thirteenth century, and consequently had made that mediaeval philosophy her official, orthodox, and dogmatic view, took the step of banning Bergson's three books by placing them upon the [[Index Librorum Prohibitorum|Index of prohibited books]] (Decree of June 1, 1914).
+
On the other hand, Bergson also argued against a kind of [[rationalism]] which reduced all becoming to static natures or essences that are known through intellect. Such a reduction was common within the entire history of philosophy understood as [[metaphysics]]. In contrast, Bergson held to the irreducible flux of becoming. This notion of becoming for Bergson was the fundamental reality, which he called “duration.” Duration is the irreducible flux or flow of time. Although we are able to break up or isolate different pieces of this continuous flow into fragments of time or “states of consciousness,” this “knowledge” is merely derived or abstracted from the original source of duration as “concrete time.” For this reason, duration cannot be known in the normal sense of the word “knowing.” It requires a particular kind of access or descent into the self in order to experience this flux in its originality.  
  
In 1914, the Scottish Universities arranged for Bergson to deliver the famous [[Gifford Lectures]], and one course was planned for the spring and another for the autumn. The first course, consisting of eleven lectures, under the title of ''The Problem of Personality'', was delivered at the [[University of Edinburgh]] in the Spring of that year. The course of lectures planned for the autumn months had to be abandoned because of the outbreak of war. Bergson was not, however, silent during the conflict, and he gave some inspiring addresses. As early as [[November 4]], 1914, he wrote an article entitled ''Wearing and Nonwearing forces'' (La force qui s'use et celle qui ne s'use pas), which appeared in that unique and interesting periodical of the ''poilus'', ''Le Bulletin des Armées de la République Française''. A presidential address, ''The Meaning of the War'', was delivered in December, 1914, to the Académie des sciences morales et politiques.  
+
===''Élan  Vital''===
 +
But duration as the ultimate reality does merely encompass individual selves, it also envelopes or runs through all things. When people turn their attention to “outward things” which initially appear to be stable entities in themselves, they can discover that like themselves, they exist in a kind of transience or flux, never standing still but always “caught up” in this passage of time. For this reason everything changes; everything is in movement. And yet, as mentioned above, this change is neither random nor mechanistic. Rather freedom itself is a fundamental component within duration. Here we see how Bergson sought to go beyond a Darwinian conception of evolution to a creative one, hence, the title of his major work ''Creative Evolution''. The creative force of becoming Bergson calls the ''élan vital'' or vital force. It is the original dynamism or animating energy of the universe which is always in a flow of becoming and yet, at the same time, creative. Although Bergson acknowledges that the evolutionary process is limited by material forces, freedom nonetheless provides the possibility for new orders and structures to emerge or evolve within this ceaseless flux.  
  
Bergson contributed also to the publication arranged by ''[[The Daily Telegraph]]'' in honour of the King of the [[Belgium|Belgians]], King Albert's Book (Christmas, 1914). In 1915 he was succeeded in the office of President of the ''Académie des Sciences morales et politiques'' by M. [[Alexandre Ribot]], and then delivered a discourse on The Evolution of German [[Imperialism]]. Meanwhile he found time to issue at the request of the Minister of Public Instruction a delightful little summary of French Philosophy. Bergson did a large amount of travelling and lecturing in America during the war. He was there when the French Mission under M. [[Viviani]] paid a visit in April and May of 1917, following upon America's entry into the conflict. M. Viviani's book ''La Mission française en Amérique'' (1917), contains a preface by Bergson.
+
=== Critique of intellect ===
 +
Given that absolute reality is a duration or flow one is most attuned to, this flow not in one's thought (which halts or stops this irreducible flux) but in actions in which one participates in and so move along with this flow. All theoretical knowing, therefore, is founded on a more primordial or original practical attitude of the knower to what is known. The mistake of metaphysics is to assume that [[universal|universals]] or [[essence|essences]] actually exist in the real things; rather all rational analysis is a kind of “objectifying” the absolute reality of duration into “segments” or static objects to be known. By adding up a number of segments or perspectives as “propositions” about the object we represent to ourselves an image of the thing that is known. In this way, one builds up or constructs a unity out of the parts which one has gathered or perceived. This knowledge can be very useful in practical affairs but it should not be confused with the ultimate reality itself, as if one were really knowing the things in themselves. Rather this unity of parts belongs to the symbol as opposed to the ultimate reality which has no parts. This capacity of intellectual knowing Bergson attributes to analysis. In analyzing, one dissects or breaks up into parts, only in order to later construct or unify that knowledge of the object under analysis. This tendency to analyze is a result of conceptual reason which always thinks in this way, that is, by objectifying. In doing this, time as the ultimate reality is conceived of in the form of space. But for Bergson time eludes all spatial representation and so there must be a more original way of accessing this ultimate reality.
  
Early in 1918 he was officially received by the ''Académie française'', taking his seat among "The Select Forty" as successor to [[Emile Ollivier]], the author of the large and notable historical work ''L'Empire libéral''. A session was held in January in his honour at which he delivered an address on Ollivier. In the war, Bergson saw the conflict of Mind and Matter, or rather of Life and Mechanism; and thus he shows us the central idea of his own philosophy in action. To no other philosopher has it fallen, during his lifetime, to have his philosophical principles so vividly and so terribly tested.
+
=== [[Intuition]] ===
 +
Since in all rational knowledge, one understands through concepts, which “freeze” the ultimate reality of duration into static representations, there must be a way to penetrate this ultimate reality in order to “know” it. Bergson calls this means of access “intuition.” Intuition is opposed to intellect and is used as a philosophical method by which one enters into a reality in order to experience it immediately in its original manner. For Bergson, intuition is deeper than intellect and so is able to penetrate the reality and so experience it even if it can’t know it, strictly speaking, through rational analysis.  
  
As many of Bergson's contributions to French periodicals were not readily accessible, he agreed to the request of his friends that these should be collected and published in two volumes. The first of these was being planned when war broke out. The conclusion of strife was marked by the appearance of a delayed volume in 1919. It bears the title ''Spiritual Energy: Essays and Lectures'' (L'Energie spirituelle: essais et conférences). The advocate of Bergson's philosophy in England, Dr. [[Wildon Carr]], prepared an English translation under the title ''Mind-Energy''. The volume opens with the Huxley Memorial Lecture of 1911, "Life and Consciousness", in a revised and developed form under the title "Consciousness and Life". Signs of Bergson's growing interest in social ethics and in the idea of a future life of personal survival are manifested. The lecture before the Society for Psychical Research is included, as is also the one given in France, ''L'Ame et le Corps'', which contains the substance of the four London lectures on the Soul. The seventh and last article is a reprint of Bergson's famous lecture to the Congress of Philosophy at Geneva in 1904, ''The Psycho-Physiolgical Paralogism'' (Le paralogisme psycho-physiologique), which now appears as ''Le cerveau et la pensée: une illusion philosophique''. Other articles are on the False Recognition, on Dreams, and Intellectual Effort. The volume is a most welcome production and serves to bring together what Bergson wrote on the concept of mental force, and on his view of "tension" and "detension" as applied to the relation of matter and mind.
+
Although not rational analysis itself, intuition is still a kind of reflection rather than some kind of instinct, feeling, or sensible perception. The disclosure of duration occurs, therefore, through an introspection of self whereby one sees through memory the flux of time, which passes through all one's various experiences, knowledge, associations, and so forth. But given this limitation of intuition, Bergson is forced into metaphorical imagery to evoke this more original experience of time. Moreover, he holds that one can “think” in duration by reflecting upon this ultimate flow from within this very flow itself, which is what metaphorical language is able to achieve because its imagery is more basic to the original flux than is the "imagery" of conceptual representation. Furthermore, because such “knowledge” is based on this original metaphysical experience, Bergson refers to his philosophy as the “true empiricism.” Therefore, he encourages his readers to penetrate for themselves the hidden depths by which the original dynamism of duration can be experienced. Likewise, the freedom, which is inherent in duration, can also be experienced within this metaphysical intuition; thus, one encounters the ''élan vital'' which eludes the mechanical necessity of brute force and so opens the space for creative possibility.
  
In June, 1920, the [[University of Cambridge]] honoured him with the degree of [[Doctor of Letters]] ([[D.Litt]]). In order that he may be able to devote his full time to the great new work he was preparing on ethics, religion, and sociology, Bergson was relieved of the duties attached to the Chair of Modern Philosophy at the ''Collège de France''. He retained the chair, but no longer delivered lectures, his place being taken by his noted pupil [[Edouard Le Roy]]. Living with his wife and daughter in a modest house in a quiet street near the Porte d'Auteuil in Paris, Bergson won the [[Nobel Prize for Literature]] in 1927.
+
==Influence of Bergson==
 +
As mentioned, Bergson was extremely popular during his lifetime, not only with philosophers but also with artists, theologians, social theorists, and even the general public. For this reason, Bergson acquired disciples of many types, and in France, movements such as [[Neo-Catholicism]], [[Modernism]], and [[Marxism]] tried to absorb and appropriate his central ideas in their own ways and for their own purposes. Marxism, for example, suggested that the realism of [[Karl Marx]] and [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]] is hostile to all forms of intellectualism; therefore, supporters of Marxist socialism should welcome a philosophy such as Bergson’s. Moreover, many religious thinkers as well, particularly the more liberal-minded theologians, showed a keen interest in his writings, and many of them sought encouragement and stimulus in his work. Finally, artists too were greatly inspired by his work. Many of the ideas of  [[Marcel Proust]], for example, are considered to have been highly influenced by Bergson.
  
After his retirement from the ''Collège'', Bergson faded into obscurity, because he was suffering from a degenerative illness. He completed his new work, ''The Two Sources of Morality and Religion'', which extended his philosophical theories to the realms of morality, religion and art, in 1935.  It was respectfully received by the public and the philosophical community, but all by that time realized that Bergson's days as a philosophical luminary were past.  He was, however, able to reiterate his core beliefs near the end of his life, by renouncing all of the posts and honours previously awarded him, rather than accept exemption from the [[Antisemitism|antisemitic]] laws imposed by the [[Vichy France|Vichy]] government. Though wanting to convert to Catholicism, he held off instead and showed solidarity with his fellow Jews by signing the registry books.  
+
==Criticisms==
 +
From his first publications, Bergson's philosophy drew strong criticism. His favoring of intuition over intellect led to the charge that his thought was “anti-intellectual” or even “irrational.” For this reason, many philosophers of the early twentieth century criticized his intuitionism as being too “indeterminate” or “psychological,and so was a confused interpretation of the scientific impulse. Among those who explicitly criticized Bergson were [[Bertrand Russell]], [[George Santayana]], [[G. E. Moore]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], and  [[C. S. Peirce]]. Pierce, for instance, took strong exception to being aligned with Bergson. In response to a letter comparing his work with that of Bergson he wrote, "a man who seeks to further science can hardly commit a greater sin than to use the terms of his science without anxious care to use them with strict accuracy; it is not very gratifying to my feelings to be classed along with a Bergson who seems to be doing his prettiest to muddle all distinctions.
  
A Roman Catholic priest said prayers at his funeral per his request. Henri Bergson is buried in the Cimetière de Garches, [[Hauts-de-Seine]].
+
Also, according to [[Santayana]] and [[Russell]], Bergson projected false claims onto the aspirations of scientific method. Russell takes particular exception to Bergson's understanding of number in ''Time and Free-will''. According to Russell, Bergson uses an outmoded spatial metaphor ("extended images") to describe the nature of mathematics as well as logic in general. Furthermore, Bergson’s notion of  ''élan vital'' was seen to be a projection of the inner life onto the world at large. The external world, according to certain theories of probability, provides less and less indeterminism with further refinement of scientific method. For this reason, an important distinction must be maintained between our inner sense of becoming and the non-human character of the outer world.
 
 
== Criticisms ==
 
 
 
From his first publications, Bergson's philosophy attracted strong criticism.  Many writers of the early 20th century criticized his intuitionism, indeterminism, psychologism and confused interpretation of the scientific impulse.  Among those who explicitly criticized Bergson (either in published articles or letters) were [[Bertrand Russell]], [[George Santayana]], [[G. E. Moore]], [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]], [[Julien Benda]], [[T. S. Eliot]], [[Paul Valéry]] (despite some recent claims otherwise), [[Andre Gide]], Marxists philosophers such as [[Theodor W. Adorno]], [[Lucio Colletti]], and [[Georges Politzer]] (see the latter's two books on the subject: "Le Bergsonisme, une Mystification Philosophique" and "La fin d'une parade philosophique: le Bergsonisme" both of which had a tremendous impact on French [[existential]] [[phenomenology]]), American philosophers such as [[Irving Babbitt]], [[Arthur Lovejoy]], [[Josiah Royce]], [[The New Realists]] ([[Ralph B. Perry]], [[E. B. Holt]], and [[William P. Montague]]), The Critical Realists (Durant Drake, [[Roy W. Sellars]], C. A. Strong, and A. K. Rogers), [[Daniel-Henry Kahnweiler]], [[Roger Fry]], and [[Virginia Woolf]] (for the latter, see Ann Banfield, "The Phantom Table").  [[C. S. Peirce]] took strong exception to being aligned with Bergson.  In response to a letter comparing his work with that of Bergson he wrote, "a man who seeks to further science can hardly commit a greater sin than to use the terms of his science without anxious care to use them with strict accuracy; it is not very gratifying to my feelings to be classed along with a Bergson who seems to be doing his prettiest to muddle all distinctions."  Some critics have taken exception to the notion that [[Proust]] took anything of great significance from Bergson's philosophy.  As one critic remarks: "As much as he was influenced by Bergson’s ideas, Proust appears to have found the diametrically opposed 'metaphysic'...equally attractive....[Proust’s] attempt, expressed in the delaying syntax of his long sentences, to immobilize and protract the instant by subdividing it infinitely, by spreading and, so to speak, spatializing it, bespeaks the mathematical, atomic, Eleatic materialism..., precisely that 'mechanical' [[materialism]] against which Bergson argued."{{fact}} Even [[William James]]'s students resisted the assimilation of his work to that of Bergson's.  See, for example, [[Horace Kallen]]'s book on the subject.  As [[Jean Wahl]] described the "ultimate disagreement" between James and Bergson: "for James, the consideration of action is necessary for the definition of truth, according to Bergson, action...must be kept from our mind if we want to see the truth."  [[Gide]] even went so far as to say that future historians will over-estimate Bergson's influence on art and philosophy just because he was the self-appointed spokesman for "the spirit of the age." 
 
 
 
Bergson's "duration" is subjective.  As he described it, "the stable, common, and...impersonal element [of everyday language]...covers over the delicate and fugitive impressions of our individual consciousness."  In all things, this "individual consciousness" is to be given priority over the pragmatic dimension of shared experience.  As early as the 1890s, [[Santayana]] attacked Bergson's view of the New and the indeterminate: "the possibility of a new and unaccountable fact appearing at any time," he writes, "does not practically affect the method of investigation;...the only thing given up is the hope that these hypotheses may ever be adequate to the reality and cover the process of nature without leaving a remainder.  This is no great renunciation; for that consumation of science...is by no one really expected."  According to Santayana and [[Russell]], Bergson projected false claims onto the aspirations of scientific method, which Bergson needed to make in order to justify his prior moral commitment to freedom. Russell takes particular exception to Bergson's understanding of number in chapter two of "Time and Free-will.According to Russell, Bergson uses an outmoded spatial metaphor ("extended images") to describe the nature of mathematics as well as logic in general. "Bergson only succeeds in making his theory of number possible by confusing a particular collection with the number of its terms, and this again with number in general," writes Russell (see "The Philosophy of Bergson" and "A History of Western Philosophy"). Further still, the ''[[élan vital]]'' was seen to be a projection of the inner life, a moral feeling, onto the world at large. The external world, according to certain theories of probability, provides less and less indeterminism with further refinement of scientific method. In brief, the moral, psychological, and aesthethic demand for the New, the underivable and the unexplained should not be confused with our imagination of the universe at large.  A difference remains between our inner sense of becoming and the non-human character of the outer world, which, according to the ancient materialist [[Lucretius]] should not be characterized as either one of becoming or being, creation or destruction.
 
 
 
==See also==
 
*[[Élan vital]]
 
*[[Charles Peguy]]
 
*[[Process philosophy]]
 
*[[Nikos Kazantzakis]]
 
*[[Philosophy of biology]]
 
  
 
==Bibliography==
 
==Bibliography==
*''Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness'' 1889. (Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience) Dover Publications 2001: ISBN 0-486-41767-0 – Bergson's doctoral dissertation
+
*''Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness''. Dover Publications, 2001. ISBN 0-486-41767-0
*''Matter and Memory'' 1896. (Matière et mémoire) Zone Books 1990: ISBN 0-942299-05-1
+
*''Matter and Memory''. Zone Books, 1990. ISBN 0-942299-05-1
*''Laughter: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic'' 1901. (Le rire) Green Integer 1998: ISBN 1-892295-02-4, Dover Publications 2005: ISBN 0-486-44380-9
+
*''Laughter: An Essay on the Meaning of the Comic''. Green Integer, 1998. ISBN 1-892295-02-4
*''Creative Evolution'' 1907. (L'Evolution créatrice) University Press of America 1983: ISBN 0-8191-3553-4, Dover Publications 1998: ISBN 0-486-40036-0, Kessinger Publishing 2003: ISBN 0-7661-4732-0, Cosimo 2005: ISBN 1-59605-309-7
+
*''Creative Evolution''. University Press of America, 1983. ISBN 0-8191-3553-4
*''Duration and Simultaneity: Bergson and the Einsteinian Universe'' 1922. Clinamen Press Ltd. ISBN 1-903083-01-X
+
*''The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics''. Citadel Press, 1992. ISBN 0-8065-0421-8  
*''The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics'' 1923. Citadel Press 1992: ISBN 0-8065-0421-8 – a collection of essays written between 1903 and 1923, including "An Introduction to Metaphysics"
+
*''The Two Sources of Morality and Religion''. University of Notre Dame Press, 1977. ISBN 0-268-01835-9
*''The Two Sources of Morality and Religion'' 1932. {Les Deux Sources de la Morale et de la Religion) University of Notre Dame Press 1977: ISBN 0-268-01835-9
 
  
 +
==References==
 +
* Ansell Pearson, K. ''Philosophy and the Adventure of the Virtual: Bergson and the Time of Life.'' Routledge, 2002.
 +
* Deleuze, G. ''Bergsonism.'' Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, trans. Zone Books, 1991.
 +
* Lawlor, L. ''The Challenge of Bergsonism: Phenomenology, Ontology, Ethics.'' Continuum Press, 2003.
 +
* Maritain, J. ''Bergsonian Philosophy and Thomism.'' Mabelle L. Andison, trans. Philosophical Library, 1955.
 +
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
{{Wikisource author}}
+
All links retrieved December 15, 2017.
*{{gutenberg author|id=Henri_Bergson|name=Henri Bergson}}
 
*[http://classiques.uqac.ca/classiques/bergson_henri/evolution_creatrice/evolution_creatrice.html L'Evolution créatrice] (in the original French, 1907)
 
*[http://spartan.ac.brocku.ca/~lward/Bergson/Bergson_1911a/Bergson_1911_toc.html English translation of ''Creative Evolution'' (1911)]
 
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/bergson/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry]
 
*[http://www.nautis.com/ Nautis Project]
 
<!--*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON8/The lectures on change, and Bergson's later life]—>
 
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON7/ Relationship with James]
 
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON6/ Education and career]
 
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON5/ Henri Bergson (1859 - 1941]
 
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON4/ LIFE AND WORKS of HENRI BERGSON]
 
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON3/ Francia, 1859-1941]
 
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON2/ Henri Bergson]
 
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON/  Henri Bergson (1859-1941)]
 
*[http://www.timoroso.com/philosophy/writings/sketches/2006-04-09-henri-bergsons-theory-of-laughter Henri Bergson's theory of laughter]. A brief summary.
 
  
{{start box}}
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/bergson/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry].
{{succession box|
+
*{{gutenberg author|id=Henri_Bergson|name=Henri Bergson}}.
  title= [[List of members of the Académie française#Seat 7|Seat 7]], [[Académie française]] | years=1914-1941 |
+
*[http://classiques.uqac.ca/classiques/bergson_henri/evolution_creatrice/evolution_creatrice.html L'Evolution créatrice] (in the original French, 1907).
  before  = [[Émile Ollivier]]|
+
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON7/ Relationship with James].
  after = [[Édouard le Roy]]
+
*[http://www.awardt.com/see/BERGSON6/ Education and career].
}}
+
 
{{end box}}
+
===General philosophy sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]  
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]  
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]  
  
 
{{Nobel Prize in Literature Laureates 1926-1950}}
 
{{Nobel Prize in Literature Laureates 1926-1950}}
  
[[Category:1859 births|Bergson, Henri]]
+
[[Category:philosophers]]
[[Category:1941 deaths|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:People from Paris|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:20th century philosophers|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:Alumni of the École Normale Supérieure|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:Continental philosophers|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:Members of the Académie française|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:Nobel Prize in Literature winners|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:Jewish French history|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:Philosophers of mind|Bergson, Henri]]
 
[[Category:French Nobel Prize winners|Bergson, Henri]]
 
 
 
[[ar:هنري برغسون]]
 
[[bs:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[cs:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[da:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[de:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[es:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[fr:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[gd:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[ko:앙리 베르그송]]
 
[[hr:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[io:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[it:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[he:אנרי ברגסון]]
 
[[sw:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[lt:Anri Bergsonas]]
 
[[hu:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[nl:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[ja:アンリ・ベルクソン]]
 
[[no:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[pl:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[pt:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[ro:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[ru:Бергсон, Анри]]
 
[[sk:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[sl:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[sr:Анри Бергсон]]
 
[[fi:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[sv:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[tr:Henri Bergson]]
 
[[ur:ہنری برگساں]]
 
[[zh:亨利·柏格森]]
 
 
 
  
 
{{Credit|76918742}}
 
{{Credit|76918742}}

Latest revision as of 17:58, 7 September 2019

Henri-Louis Bergson (October 18, 1859 – January 4, 1941) was a major French philosopher in the first half of the twentieth century. He was widely popular during his lifetime and his lectures in Paris were attended not only by philosophers and students, but also by artists, theologians, social theorists, and even the general public. At the core of his philosophy is his theory of “duration,” which he understands to be the ultimate and irreducible reality. Although Bergson understood duration to be the unified flow of time or becoming, he fought hard against all mechanistic and naturalistic interpretations of this temporal flux. Rather, he argued that duration is the élan vital or vital force of life, which evolves not as a result of brute forces (as in Darwinian evolution) but in a spontaneous and creative way. This “creative evolution,” which is basically free, is what allows for different forms of life to emerge. Methodologically Bergson argued that the élan vital of duration cannot be apprehended by the rational intellect or conceptual understanding but instead through intuition. Only in intuition can one enter into this passing of time and so experience at the concrete level the flux of becoming as the ultimate reality.

Biography

Early years

Bergson was born on October 18, 1859, in the Rue Lamartine, in Paris. Both his parents were Jewish, but while his father, a musician, came from a Polish background, his mother was English. His family lived in London for a few years after his birth, but before he was nine, his parents crossed the English Channel and settled in France. It was there that the young Henri became a naturalized citizen of the Republic.

Bergson attended the Lycée Fontaine in Paris, from 1868 to 1878. In early adulthood he excelled in science and mathematics, winning prizes in both fields. In fact, he won a prize for a solution to a complex mathematical problem that had originally been presented by Pascal. The solution was published in Annales de Mathématiques and was Bergson’s first published work. Despite these early accomplishments in the hard sciences, Bergson decided to pursue a career in the humanities. At the age of nineteen he entered the famous École Normale Supérieure, where he earned the degree of Licence-ès-Lettres, and later in 1881, the Agrégation de philosophie.

Professional career

In 1884, while teaching at Clermont-Ferrand, Bergson published an excellent edition of extracts from Lucretius. Also, during this period Bergson began what was to become the first of his four major works, Time and Free Will (Essai sur les données immédiates de la conscience). The work was submitted, along with a short thesis on Aristotle’s interpretation of Lucretius, for the degree of Docteur-ès-Lettres, which was awarded by the University of Paris in 1889. After teaching for some months at the Municipal College in Paris, Bergson received an appointment at the Lycée Henri-Quatre, where he remained for eight years. In 1896, he published his second major work, entitled Matter and Memory (Matière et mémoire). This rather difficult but brilliant work explores some of the problems of the mind-body relation. In the work, he considered the function of the brain, particularly as it relates to the cognitive powers of perception and memory.

In 1901, Bergson published a relatively short essay entitled Laughter (Le rire), one of the most important of his minor productions. This essay centers upon the meaning of comedy, and it reflects some of the essential aspects of Bergson's views on life. The main thesis of the work is that laughter is a corrective evolved to make social life possible for human beings. People laugh at those who fail to adapt to the demands of society when their failure is a result of an inflexible mechanism. Comic novelists and poets, in particular, exploit this human tendency to laugh at such social misfits by revealing the way "something mechanical” exists “in something living."

In 1903, Bergson wrote a short but important essay entitled Introduction to Metaphysics (Introduction à la metaphysique), which serves as a useful preface to the study of his larger works. Bergon’s third and perhaps most important major work, Creative Evolution (L'Evolution créatrice) appeared in 1907. The work was widely known and much discussed, as it offered a profound and original philosophical interpretation of the theory of evolution. Following the appearance of this book, Bergson's popularity increased enormously, not only in academic circles, but also among the general public. People in a variety of academic, literary, and artistic fields frequented his lectures at the Collège de France and even tourists would drop in to what became known as “the House of Bergson.”

Relationship with James and pragmatism

In 1908, Bergson went to London and visited the well-known American philosopher William James. James had been instrumental in alerting the Anglo-American public to the work of the French professor. In fact, James's impression of Bergson is given in a letter dated October 4, 1908. "So modest and unpretending a man but such a genius intellectually! I have the strongest suspicions that the tendency which he has brought to a focus, will end by prevailing, and that the present epoch will be a sort of turning point in the history of philosophy."

Comparisons are often made between the philosophies of Bergson and James due to the similarities in their work. For example, both thinkers rejected rationalism and materialism in favor of an interpretation of reality as transpiring in a temporal flux. Nevertheless Bergson’s metaphysics went beyond the pragmatism of James and so Bergson argued that utility, far from being a test of truth, was in fact the very source of error. As Jean Wahl described, the "ultimate disagreement" between James and Bergson: "for James, the consideration of action is necessary for the definition of truth, according to Bergson, action…must be kept from our mind if we want to see the truth."

Later life

Bergson visited the United States in 1913, where he lectured in several American cities and was welcomed by large audiences. Shortly thereafter he was elected as a member of the Académie française and later he delivered the famous Gifford Lectures under the title of The Problem of Personality. In 1927, Bergson won the Nobel Prize for Literature, “in recognition of his rich and vitalizing ideas and the brilliant skill with which they have been presented.”

In 1932, Bergson completed his final major work, The Two Sources of Morality and Religion (Les deux sources de la morale et de la religion). Here he extended his philosophical theories to the realms of morality, religion, and art. Although the work was respectfully received by the public and philosophical community, Bergson's influence had by this time begun to fade. He was, however, able to give force to his core beliefs near the end of his life when he renounced all the posts and honors previously received rather than accept exemption from the anti-Semitic laws imposed by the Vichy government. Bergson died on January 4, 1941. He is buried in the Cimetière de Garches.

Main philosophical ideas

Duration

Bergson’s philosophy can be viewed as challenging two fundamental positions in the history of philosophy. The first is a scientific materialism which views all reality as being controlled or determined by mechanical laws or necessities. This view was prominent in the philosophical milieu of the late nineteenth century, in which Bergson had been educated. Although Bergson agreed with certain undeniable aspects of a “philosophy of becoming” such as the biological evolutionism of Darwin, he nevertheless did not hold to the randomness of natural selection or the interpretation of all order to a brute, biological force. There was for him something more “vital” which animated the process of becoming and which raised it above mechanistic laws.

On the other hand, Bergson also argued against a kind of rationalism which reduced all becoming to static natures or essences that are known through intellect. Such a reduction was common within the entire history of philosophy understood as metaphysics. In contrast, Bergson held to the irreducible flux of becoming. This notion of becoming for Bergson was the fundamental reality, which he called “duration.” Duration is the irreducible flux or flow of time. Although we are able to break up or isolate different pieces of this continuous flow into fragments of time or “states of consciousness,” this “knowledge” is merely derived or abstracted from the original source of duration as “concrete time.” For this reason, duration cannot be known in the normal sense of the word “knowing.” It requires a particular kind of access or descent into the self in order to experience this flux in its originality.

Élan Vital

But duration as the ultimate reality does merely encompass individual selves, it also envelopes or runs through all things. When people turn their attention to “outward things” which initially appear to be stable entities in themselves, they can discover that like themselves, they exist in a kind of transience or flux, never standing still but always “caught up” in this passage of time. For this reason everything changes; everything is in movement. And yet, as mentioned above, this change is neither random nor mechanistic. Rather freedom itself is a fundamental component within duration. Here we see how Bergson sought to go beyond a Darwinian conception of evolution to a creative one, hence, the title of his major work Creative Evolution. The creative force of becoming Bergson calls the élan vital or vital force. It is the original dynamism or animating energy of the universe which is always in a flow of becoming and yet, at the same time, creative. Although Bergson acknowledges that the evolutionary process is limited by material forces, freedom nonetheless provides the possibility for new orders and structures to emerge or evolve within this ceaseless flux.

Critique of intellect

Given that absolute reality is a duration or flow one is most attuned to, this flow not in one's thought (which halts or stops this irreducible flux) but in actions in which one participates in and so move along with this flow. All theoretical knowing, therefore, is founded on a more primordial or original practical attitude of the knower to what is known. The mistake of metaphysics is to assume that universals or essences actually exist in the real things; rather all rational analysis is a kind of “objectifying” the absolute reality of duration into “segments” or static objects to be known. By adding up a number of segments or perspectives as “propositions” about the object we represent to ourselves an image of the thing that is known. In this way, one builds up or constructs a unity out of the parts which one has gathered or perceived. This knowledge can be very useful in practical affairs but it should not be confused with the ultimate reality itself, as if one were really knowing the things in themselves. Rather this unity of parts belongs to the symbol as opposed to the ultimate reality which has no parts. This capacity of intellectual knowing Bergson attributes to analysis. In analyzing, one dissects or breaks up into parts, only in order to later construct or unify that knowledge of the object under analysis. This tendency to analyze is a result of conceptual reason which always thinks in this way, that is, by objectifying. In doing this, time as the ultimate reality is conceived of in the form of space. But for Bergson time eludes all spatial representation and so there must be a more original way of accessing this ultimate reality.

Intuition

Since in all rational knowledge, one understands through concepts, which “freeze” the ultimate reality of duration into static representations, there must be a way to penetrate this ultimate reality in order to “know” it. Bergson calls this means of access “intuition.” Intuition is opposed to intellect and is used as a philosophical method by which one enters into a reality in order to experience it immediately in its original manner. For Bergson, intuition is deeper than intellect and so is able to penetrate the reality and so experience it even if it can’t know it, strictly speaking, through rational analysis.

Although not rational analysis itself, intuition is still a kind of reflection rather than some kind of instinct, feeling, or sensible perception. The disclosure of duration occurs, therefore, through an introspection of self whereby one sees through memory the flux of time, which passes through all one's various experiences, knowledge, associations, and so forth. But given this limitation of intuition, Bergson is forced into metaphorical imagery to evoke this more original experience of time. Moreover, he holds that one can “think” in duration by reflecting upon this ultimate flow from within this very flow itself, which is what metaphorical language is able to achieve because its imagery is more basic to the original flux than is the "imagery" of conceptual representation. Furthermore, because such “knowledge” is based on this original metaphysical experience, Bergson refers to his philosophy as the “true empiricism.” Therefore, he encourages his readers to penetrate for themselves the hidden depths by which the original dynamism of duration can be experienced. Likewise, the freedom, which is inherent in duration, can also be experienced within this metaphysical intuition; thus, one encounters the élan vital which eludes the mechanical necessity of brute force and so opens the space for creative possibility.

Influence of Bergson

As mentioned, Bergson was extremely popular during his lifetime, not only with philosophers but also with artists, theologians, social theorists, and even the general public. For this reason, Bergson acquired disciples of many types, and in France, movements such as Neo-Catholicism, Modernism, and Marxism tried to absorb and appropriate his central ideas in their own ways and for their own purposes. Marxism, for example, suggested that the realism of Karl Marx and Pierre-Joseph Proudhon is hostile to all forms of intellectualism; therefore, supporters of Marxist socialism should welcome a philosophy such as Bergson’s. Moreover, many religious thinkers as well, particularly the more liberal-minded theologians, showed a keen interest in his writings, and many of them sought encouragement and stimulus in his work. Finally, artists too were greatly inspired by his work. Many of the ideas of Marcel Proust, for example, are considered to have been highly influenced by Bergson.

Criticisms

From his first publications, Bergson's philosophy drew strong criticism. His favoring of intuition over intellect led to the charge that his thought was “anti-intellectual” or even “irrational.” For this reason, many philosophers of the early twentieth century criticized his intuitionism as being too “indeterminate” or “psychological,” and so was a confused interpretation of the scientific impulse. Among those who explicitly criticized Bergson were Bertrand Russell, George Santayana, G. E. Moore, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and C. S. Peirce. Pierce, for instance, took strong exception to being aligned with Bergson. In response to a letter comparing his work with that of Bergson he wrote, "a man who seeks to further science can hardly commit a greater sin than to use the terms of his science without anxious care to use them with strict accuracy; it is not very gratifying to my feelings to be classed along with a Bergson who seems to be doing his prettiest to muddle all distinctions."

Also, according to Santayana and Russell, Bergson projected false claims onto the aspirations of scientific method. Russell takes particular exception to Bergson's understanding of number in Time and Free-will. According to Russell, Bergson uses an outmoded spatial metaphor ("extended images") to describe the nature of mathematics as well as logic in general. Furthermore, Bergson’s notion of élan vital was seen to be a projection of the inner life onto the world at large. The external world, according to certain theories of probability, provides less and less indeterminism with further refinement of scientific method. For this reason, an important distinction must be maintained between our inner sense of becoming and the non-human character of the outer world.

Bibliography

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Ansell Pearson, K. Philosophy and the Adventure of the Virtual: Bergson and the Time of Life. Routledge, 2002.
  • Deleuze, G. Bergsonism. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam, trans. Zone Books, 1991.
  • Lawlor, L. The Challenge of Bergsonism: Phenomenology, Ontology, Ethics. Continuum Press, 2003.
  • Maritain, J. Bergsonian Philosophy and Thomism. Mabelle L. Andison, trans. Philosophical Library, 1955.

External links

All links retrieved December 15, 2017.

General philosophy sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.