Difference between revisions of "Gorgias" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m
m
 
(13 intermediate revisions by 7 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
:''This article is about the Greek rhetorician.  For the [[Plato]]nic dialogue, see [[Gorgias (dialogue)]]. For the [[Seleucid]] general, see [[Gorgias (general)]]. "Gorgias" is also the name of a disputed text of [[Aristotle]] (see below).''
+
{{Ebapproved}}{{Copyedited}}{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{submitted}}
 
'''Gorgias''' (in [[Greek language|Greek]] Γοργἰας, circa [[483 B.C.E.|483]]-[[375 B.C.E.]]), [[Greece|Greek]] [[sophist]], [[philosophy|philosopher]] and [[rhetoric]]ian, was a native of [[Leontini]] in [[Sicily]].
 
 
In [[427 B.C.E.|427]], he was sent to Athens by his fellow-citizens at the head of an embassy to ask for Athenian protection against the aggression of the [[Syracuse, Italy|Syracusans]]. He subsequently settled in Athens, and supported himself by the practice of oratory and by teaching rhetoric. He died at [[Larissa]] in [[Thessaly]].
 
 
His chief claim to recognition resides in the fact that he transplanted rhetoric to Greece, and contributed to the diffusion of the [[Attic Greek|Attic dialect]] as the language of literary prose. He was the author of a lost work: ''On Nature or the Non-existent'', the substance of which may be gathered from the writings of [[Sextus Empiricus]], and also from the treatise (attributed to [[Aristotle]]; ascribed to [[Theophrastus]]) ''De Melisso, Xenophane, Gorgia''. In this work he argued a formulation of skeptical philosophy that states:
 
 
# Nothing exists;
 
# Even if something exists, nothing can be known about it; and
 
# Even if something could be known about it, knowledge about it can't be communicated to others.
 
  
== Introduction ==
+
'''Gorgias''' (in [[Greek language|Greek]] &#915;&#959;&#961;&#947;&#7984;&#945;&#962;; c. 483 - 375 <small>B.C.E.</small>), was one of the most important Greek [[sophism|sophists]] of the fifth century <small>B.C.E.</small>, a philosopher, rhetorician, and a gifted writer of artistic prose.
Due to his ushering in of rhetorical innovations involving structure and ornamentation and his introduction of ''paradoxologia'' the idea of paradoxical thought and paradoxical expression – Gorgias of Leontini has been labeled the ‘father of [[sophistry]](Wardy 6). Gorgias is also known for contributing to the diffusion of the [[Attic Greek|Attic dialect]] as the language of literary prose.  
+
Originally a native of Leontini in [[Sicily]], he was sent to [[Athens]] in 427 <small>B.C.E.</small> at the head of an embassy to ask for Athenian protection against the aggression of neighboring [[Syracuse]]. He subsequently settled in Athens, and supported himself by the practice of oratory and by teaching rhetoric. He died at Larissa in [[Thessaly]]. A brilliant rhetorician, Gorgias also contributed to the diffusion of the [[Attic dialect]] as the language of literary prose. Several of his works remain in existence. Two of his performatory speeches, ''Encomium'' and ''Palamedes'', illustrate the principles he used to make a weak argument strong, and ''On the Nature of Things'' uses [[Eleatic philosophers|Eleatic]] arguments to reach a number of [[nihilism|nihilistic]] conclusions. Gorgias appeared in [[Plato]]'s dialogues as a [[moral relativism|moral relativist]] and one of dialogues was named after him.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
== Life ==
 +
Gorgias was a native of Leontini, a Greek colony in Sicily, which is often called the home of [[Greek rhetoric]]. Very little is known of his life before he emigrated to Athens, except that he had a father named Charmantides and two siblings; a brother named Herodicus and a sister who dedicated a statue to Gorgias in Delphi (McComiskey 2001, 6-7). In 427 <small>B.C.E.</small> Gorgias was sent to Athens as an ambassador to ask Athenian protection from the aggressive Syracusans (Leitch, et al 29). Gorgias’ impressive oratorical style was said to have brought many of the leading politicians and intellectuals under his influence (Wardy 1996, 6). His mission completed, Gorgias settled in Athens. He was a student of [[Empedocles]], and made a successful living by practicing oratory and teaching rhetoric to students, including [[Pericles]], Critias, Menos, Isocrates and possibly Aspasia. [[Philostratus]] ''(Lives of the Sophists I 9, I)'' recounts that Gorgias began the practice of extemporaneous oratory, and that he would say to his audiences, "'suggest a subject' ...he was the first to proclaim himself willing to take the chance, showing apparently that he knew everything and would trust the moment to speak on any subject." He spoke at Panhellenic festivals, becoming well-known in [[Olympia]] and [[Delphi]]. His existing works include the ''Encomium of Helen'', the ''Defense of Palamedes'', ''On Non-Existence'' (or ''On Nature''), and ''Epitaphios''. Gorgias is reputed to have lived to be over one hundred years old. He died at Larissa in Thessaly in 375 <small>B.C.E.</small>
  
Gorgias’ surviving rhetorical works (''Encomium of Helen'', ''Defense of Palamedes'', ''On Non-Existence'', and ''Epitaphios'') exist in the form of rhetorical exercises that were used to teach his pupils and demonstrate various principles of rhetorical practice (Leitch, et al 29). Although some scholars claim that each work presents opposing statements, the four texts can be read as interrelated contributions to the up-and-coming theory and art (''technê'') of rhetoric (McComiskey 32).  Of Gorgias’ surviving works, only the ''Encomium'' and the ''Defense'' are believed to exist in their entirety.  Meanwhile, Gorgias’ ''Epitaphios'' is thought to be only a small fragment of what used to be a significantly larger funeral oration, and ''On Non-Existence'' appears in summary form.  These works are each part of the Diels-Kranz collection, and although academics consider this source reliable, many of the works included are fragmentary and corrupt.  Questions have also been raised as to the authenticity and accuracy of the texts attributed to Gorgias (Consigny 4).
+
== Thought and Works ==
 +
Gorgias of Leontini has been credited with introducing rhetorical innovations involving structure and ornamentation; and ''paradoxologia'', the idea of [[paradoxical thought]] and paradoxical expression, to Greece, and is sometimes called the ‘father of sophistry’ (Wardy 1996, 6). Gorgias is also known for contributing to the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the language of literary prose.  
  
Gorgias’ writings are both rhetorical and performative.  He goes to great lengths to exhibit his ability of making an absurd, argumentative position appear stronger. Consequently, each of his works defend positions that are unpopular, paradoxical and even absurd. The performative nature of Gorgias’ writings is exemplified by the way that he playfully approaches each argument with stylistic devices such as parody, artificial figuration and theatricality (Consigny 149). Gorgias’ style of argumentation can be described as poetics-minus-the-meter (''poiêsis-minus-meter''). Gorgias argues that persuasive words have power (''dunamis'') that is equivalent to that of the gods and as strong as physical force. In the ''Encomium'', Gorgias likens the effect of speech on the soul to the effect of drugs on the body: “Just as different drugs draw forth different humors from the body – some putting a stop to disease, others to life – so too with words: some cause pain, others joy, some strike fear, some stir the audience to boldness, some benumb and bewitch the soul with evil persuasion” (Gorgias 32).
+
Gorgias’ surviving rhetorical works (''Encomium of Helen, Defense of Palamedes, On Non-Existence'', and ''Epitaphios'') exist in the form of rhetorical exercises that were used to teach his pupils and demonstrate various principles of rhetorical practice. Although some scholars claim that each work presents opposing statements, the four texts can be read as interrelated contributions to the up-and-coming theory and art ''(technê)'' of rhetoric (McComiskey 2001, 32). Of Gorgias’ surviving works, only the ''Encomium'' and the ''Defense'' are believed to exist in their entirety. Gorgias’ ''Epitaphios'' is probably only a fragment of a significantly larger funeral oration, and ''On Non-Existence'' appears in summary form. These works are each part of the Diels-Kranz collection; although academics consider this source reliable, many of the works included in it are fragmentary and corrupt.
 +
 +
Gorgias’ writings are both rhetorical and performative, exhibiting his ability to make a weak argument appear strong. Each of his works defends positions that are unpopular, paradoxical and even absurd. The performative nature of Gorgias’ writings is exemplified by the way that he playfully approaches each argument with stylistic devices such as parody, artificial figuration and theatricality (Consigny 2001, 149). Gorgias’ style of argumentation can be described as poetics-minus-the-meter ''(poiêsis-minus-meter)''. Gorgias argues that persuasive words have power ''(dunamis)'' equivalent to that of the gods and as strong as physical force. In the ''Encomium'', Gorgias likens the effect of speech on the [[soul]] to the effect of drugs on the [[body]]: “Just as different drugs draw forth different humors from the body – some putting a stop to disease, others to life – so too with words: some cause pain, others joy, some strike fear, some stir the audience to boldness, some benumb and bewitch the soul with evil persuasion” (Gorgias, 32).  
  
Gorgias also believed that his "magical incantations" would bring healing to the human psyche by controlling powerful emotions. He paid particular attention to the sounds of words, which, like poetry, could captivate audiences. His florid, rhyming style seemed to hypnotize his audiences (Herrick 42). Gorgias' legendary powers of persuasion would suggest that he had a somewhat supernatural influence over his audience and their emotions.
+
Gorgias also believed that his "magical incantations" could bring healing to the human psyche by controlling powerful emotions. He paid particular attention to the sounds of words, which, like poetry, could captivate audiences. His florid, rhyming style seemed to hypnotize his audiences (Herrick, 42). Gorgias' legendary powers of persuasion would suggest that he had a somewhat supernatural influence over his audience and their emotions.  
 +
Gorgias thought that an orator had an ethical obligation to avoid deception, and that it was "…the duty of the same man both to declare what he should rightly and to refute what has been spoken falsely."
  
Much debate over both the nature and value of rhetoric begins with Gorgias.  [[Plato]]’s dialogue entitled ''Gorgias'' presents a counter-argument to Gorgias’ embrace of rhetoric, its elegant form, and performative nature (Wardy 2).  The dialog shows that rhetoric does not meet the requirements to actually be considered a ''technê'' but is a somewhat dangerous "knack" to posess both for the orator and for his audience. This is because it gives the ignorant the power to seem more knowledgable than an expert to a group.
+
== Rhetoric and Oratory ==
 +
=== ''Encomium of Helen'' ===
 +
Of the three divisions of rhetoric discussed by [[Aristotle]] in his ''Rhetoric'' ([[forensic]], [[deliberative]], and [[epideictic]]), the ''Encomium'' can be classified as an epideictic speech, expressing praise for [[Helen of Troy]] and absolving her of responsibility for causing the [[Trojan War]]. The popular and literary tradition of the time blamed Helen of Troy for instigating the Trojan War by leaving her husband and eloping with Paris.  
 +
   
 +
The ''Encomium'' opens with Gorgias explaining that “a man, woman, speech, deed, city or action that is worthy of praise should be honored with acclaim, but the unworthy should be branded with blame” (Gorgias, 30). Gorgias discusses the possible reasons for Helen’s journey to Troy. He explains that Helen could have been persuaded in one of four ways: by the gods, by physical force, by love, or by speech ''(logos)''. If it was the plan of the gods that caused Helen to depart for Troy, Gorgias argues that those who blame her should face blame themselves, “for a human’s anticipation cannot restrain a god’s inclination” (Gorgias, 31). Gorgias explains that, by nature, the weak are ruled by the strong, and, since the gods are stronger than humans in all respects, Helen should not be held responsible. If Helen was abducted by force, it is clear that the aggressor committed a crime and should be blamed for the consequences. And if Helen was persuaded by love, she should also be absolved because “…if love is a god, with the divine power of the gods, how could a weaker person refuse and reject him? But if love is a human sickness and a mental weakness, it must not be blamed as mistake, but claimed as misfortune” (Gorgias, 32). Finally, if it was speech that persuaded Helen, she should not be blamed, because speech ''(logos)'' is a powerful force that can persuade people to do things against their own interests. In the final section of the ''Encomium'' he writes: “I wished to write this speech for Helen’s encomium and my amusement” (Gorgias, 33).
  
== Biography ==
+
=== ''Defense of Palamedes'' ===
Gorgias originated from [[Leontini]], a Greek colony in [[Sicily]], and what is often called the home of Greek rhetoric.  Very little is known of his life before he emigrated to [[Athens]] in 427 B.C.E. as an ambassador to ask Athenian protection against the threat of Syracusan aggressors (Leitch, et al 29).  It is known, however, that Gorgias had a father named Charmantides and two siblings – a brother named Herodicus and a sister who dedicated a statue to Gorgias in [[Delphi]] (McComiskey 6-7).  Once in Athens, Gorgias’ impressive oratorical style was said to have brought many of the leading politicians and intellectuals under his influence (Wardy 6).  Settling in Athens, Gorgias made an impressive living by practicing oratory and teaching rhetoric to students, including [[Pericles]], [[Critias]] and [[Isocrates]].  He also spoke at Panhellenic festivals becoming well-known in [[Olympia]] and Delphi. His existing works include the ''Encomium of Helen'', the ''Defense of Palamedes'', ''On Non-Existence (or On Nature)'', and ''Epitaphios'' (McComiskey 32).  Gorgias is reputed to have lived to be over one hundred years old.  He died at [[Larissa]] in [[Thessaly]] in 376 B.C.E..  
+
''Defense of Palamedes'' is another performative speech in which Gorgias shows how plausible arguments can cause an audience to doubt conventional truths. The speech is presented as the legal self-defense, in a trial setting, of [[Palamedes]], a figure from [[Greek mythology]] credited with the invention of the alphabet, written laws, numbers, armor, and measures and weights. [[Odysseus]] feigned madness in order to avoid going to [[Troy]] with [[Agamemnon]] and [[Menelaus]] to bring Helen back to [[Sparta]]. Palamedes tricked Odysseus into revealing that he was only pretending to be mad, and Odysseus never forgave him. Later Odysseus accused him of cooperating with Troy, and Palamedes was condemned and executed.  
  
== Rhetorical Works ==
+
Throughout the speech, Gorgias composes logical ''([[logos]])'' and ethical ''([[ethos]])'' arguments from possibility, a type of argument that Aristotle later defined as forensic ''topoi''. Palamedes rejects the use of emotional arguments ''(pathos)'', saying "among you, who are the foremost of the Greeks...there is no need to persuade such ones as you with the aid of friends and sorrowful prayers and lamentations." Gorgias posits that in order to prove that treason was committed, we must first establish that a set of possible events took place. In the ''Defense'' these events are: communication between Palamedes and the enemy, exchange of a pledge in the form of hostages or money, and not being detected by guards or citizens. In his defense, Palamedes claims that a small sum of money would not have warranted such a large undertaking and reasons that a large sum of money, if indeed such a transaction had been made, would have required the aid of many confederates to transport it. Palamedes reasons further that such an exchange could neither have occurred at night because the guards would be watching, nor in the day because everyone would be able to see. Palamedes continues, explaining that if the aforementioned conditions were, in fact, arranged then action would need to follow. Such action would take place either with or without confederates. If these confederates were free men then they were free to disclose any information they desired, and had not done so. If they were slaves there was a risk of them voluntarily accusing to earn freedom, or accusing by force when tortured. Slaves, Palamedes says, are untrustworthy. Palamedes goes on to list a variety of possible motives for committing treason, such as status, wealth, honor or security, all of which he proves groundless.
===''Encomium of Helen''===
 
In their writings, Gorgias and other sophists speculated "about the structure and function of language” as a framework for expressing the implications of action and the ways decisions about such actions were made” (Jarratt 103).  And this is exactly the purpose of Gorgias’ ''Encomium of Helen''. Of the three divisions of rhetoric discussed by [[Aristotle]] in his ''Rhetoric'' (forensic, deliberative, and epideictic), the ''Encomium'' can be classified as an epideictic speech, expressing praise for [[Helen of Troy]] and ridding her of the blame she faced for leaving Sparta with Paris (Wardy 26).
 
  
Helen – the proverbial “Helen of Troy” – exemplified both sexual passion and tremendous beauty for the Greeks.  She was the daughter of [[Zeus]] and Leda, the Queen of Sparta, and her beauty was the direct cause of the decade long [[Trojan War]] between [[Greece]] and [[Troy]].  The war began after the goddesses [[Hera]], [[Athena]], and [[Aphrodite]] asked Paris (a Trojan prince) to select who was the most beautiful of the three.  Each goddess tried to influence Paris’ decision, but he ultimately chose Aphrodite who then promised Paris the most beautiful woman.  Paris then traveled to Greece where he was greeted by Helen and her husband [[Menelaus]]. Under the influence of Aphrodite, Helen allowed Paris to persuade her to elope with him.  Together they traveled to Troy, not only sparking the war, but also a popular and literary tradition of blaming Helen for her wrongdoing.  It is this tradition which Gorgias confronts in the ''Encomium''.
+
=== ''On Nature, or the Non-Existent'' ===
 +
The original work has been lost, and there are two existing transcripts which differ slightly from each other, one preserved by the philosopher [[Sextus Empirica]] in ''Against the Professors'', and another by the author (possible Aristotle or [[Theophrastus]]) of ''De Melissus, Xenophane, Gorgia''. There is some disagreement among scholars as to whether this was intended as a serious philosophical work, or as a caricature of the metaphysical arguments of [[Parmenides]].  
 +
   
 +
The subject of ''On Nature'' is [[ontology|ontological]] (about the nature of being), and it also discusses [[epistemology]] and language. It is also a rhetorical exercise that showcases Gorgias’ oratorical skill. He attacks the idea that if we examine our world, we must conclude that things exist, and demonstrates that 1) Nothing exists; 2) Even if existence exists, it cannot be known; and 3) Even if it could be known, it cannot be communicated.  
  
The ''Encomium'' opens with Gorgias explaining that “a man, woman, speech, deed, city or action that is worthy of praise should be honored with acclaim, but the unworthy should be branded with blame” (Gorgias 30).  In the speech Gorgias discusses the possible reasons for Helen’s journey to Troy.  He explains that Helen could have been persuaded in one of four ways: by the gods, by physical force, by love, or by speech (''logos''). If it was indeed the plan of the gods that caused Helen to depart for Troy, Gorgias argues that those who blame her should face blame themselves, “for a human’s anticipation cannot restrain a god’s inclination” (Gorgias 31).  Gorgias explains that, by nature, the weak are ruled by the strong, and, since the gods are stronger than humans in all respects, Helen should be freed from her undesirable reputation.  If, however, Helen was abducted by force, it is clear that the aggressor committed a crime.  Thus, it should be he, not Helen, who should be blamed.  And if Helen was persuaded by love, she should also be rid of ill repute because “if love is a god, with the divine power of the gods, how could a weaker person refuse and reject him?  But if love is a human sickness and a mental weakness, it must not be blamed as mistake, but claimed as misfortune” (Gorgias 32).  Finally, if it was speech that persuaded Helen, Gorgias claims he can easily clear her of blame.  Gorgias explains: “Speech is a powerful master and achieves the most divine feats with the smallest and least evident body.  It can stop fear, relieve pain, create joy, and increase pity” (Gorgias 31).  It is here that Gorgias compares the effect of speech on the body with the effect of drugs.
+
He does not completely deny the possibility of communication altogether; rather it is ''[[logos]]'' that is communicated to others (Jarratt 1991, 55), because those things that the human mind can know, believe, and communicate are merely mental representations created by ''logos''. But the relationship between ''logos'' and reality presents a problem because ''logos'', existing only within the realm of human speech and thought, is different from the reality it represents (Walker 2000, 27).  
  
The ''Encomium'' demonstrates Gorgias’ love of ''paradoxologia''.  The performative nature of the ''Encomium'' requires a reciprocal relationship between the performer and the audience, one which relies on the cooperation between the deceptive performer and the equally deceived audience (Wardy 36). Gorgias reveals this paradox in the final section of the ''Encomium'' where he writes: “I wished to write this speech for Helen’s encomium and my amusement” (Gorgias 33).  Additionally, if one were to accept Gorgias’ argument for Helen’s exoneration, it would fly in the face of a whole literary tradition of blame directed towards Helen.  This too is paradoxical.
+
This argument has led some to label Gorgias as either an ontological [[skepticism|skeptic]] or a [[nihilism|nihilist]] (one who believes nothing exists, or that the world is incomprehensible, and that the concept of truth is fictitious). But it can also be interpreted as an assertion that it is ''logos'' and ''logos'' alone which is the proper object of our inquiries, since it is the only thing we can really know. ''On Nature'' is sometimes seen as a refutation of [[Pre-Socratic philosophy|pre-Socratic]] essentialist philosophy (McComiskey 2001, 37).
  
===''Defense of Palamedes''===
+
=== Critics ===
In the ''Defense of Palamedes'' Gorgias describes logos as a positive instrument for creating ethical arguments (McComiskey 38).  The ''Defense'', an oration that deals with issues of morality and political commitment (Consigny 38), defends [[Palamedes]] who, in [[Greek mythology]], is credited with the invention of the alphabet, written laws, numbers, armor, and measures and weights (McComiskey 47). 
+
Gorgias and other sophists were often criticized for placing more emphasis on rhetoric and oratory than on a legitimate quest for truth, and for tearing down arguments rather than building a system of thought which could make a positive contribution to the improvement of society. Oratory played an important role in the [[Athenian democracy]], where the ability to persuade an audience meant political influence and power. Teachers of rhetoric made a living by giving instruction on how to argue successfully.
 
 
In the speech Palamedes defends himself against the charge of treason.  In Greek mythology, [[Odysseus]] – in order to avoid going to Troy with [[Agamemnon]] and Menelaus to bring Helen back to [[Sparta]] – pretended to have gone mad and began sowing the fields with salt.  Palamedes got Odysseus to disclose this information by throwing his son [[Telemachus]] in front of the plow.  Odysseus, who never forgave Palamedes for making him reveal himself, later accused Palamedes of working with the Trojans.  Soon after, Palamedes was condemned and killed (Jarratt 58).
 
 
 
In this epideictic speech, like the ''Encomium'', Gorgias is concerned with experimenting with how plausible arguments can cause conventional truths to be doubted (Jarratt 59).  Throughout the text, Gorgias presents a method for composing logical (''logos''), ethical (''ethos'') and emotional (''pathos'') arguments from possibility, which are similar to those described by Aristotle in ''Rhetoric''.  These types of arguments about motive and capability presented in the ''Defense'' are later described by Aristotle as forensic ''[[topoi]]''.  Gorgias demonstrates that in order to prove that treason had been committed, a set of possible occurrences also need to be established.  In the ''Defense'' these occurrences are as follows: communication between Palamedes and the enemy, exchange of a pledge in the form of hostages or money, and not being detected by guards or citizens.  In his defense, Palamedes claims that a small sum of money would not have warranted such a large undertaking and reasons that a large sum of money, if indeed such a transaction had been made, would require the aid of many confederates in order for it to be transported.  Palamedes reasons further that such an exchange could neither have occurred at night because the guards would be watching, nor in the day because everyone would be able to see.  Palamedes continues, explaining that if the aforementioned conditions were, in fact, arranged then action would need to follow.  Such action needed to take place either with or without confederates; however, if these confederates were free men then they were free to disclose any information they desired, but if they were slaves there was a risk of them voluntarily accusing to earn freedom, or accusing by force when tortured.  Slaves, Palamedes says, are untrustworthy.  Palamedes goes on to list a variety of possible motives, all of which he proves false. 
 
 
 
Through the ''Defense'' Gorgias demonstrates that a motive requires an advantage such as status, wealth, honour, and security, and insists that Palamedes lacked a motive (McComiskey 47-49).
 
 
 
===''On Non-Existence'' (or ''On Nature'')===
 
The original ''On Non-Existence'' was lost and today we only have two sketches of it.  The first is preserved by the philosopher [[Sextus Empiricus]] in ''Against the Professors'' and the other by the anonymous author of ''De Melissus, Xenophane, Gorgia''.  Each work, however, excludes material that is discussed in the other, which suggests that each version may represent intermediary sources (Consigny 4).  Gorgias’ ''On Non-Existence'' does not present a theory of rhetoric; rather it provides a general theory of the ways human beings encourage others to take action by means of ''logos'' (McComiskey 38). 
 
 
 
''On Non-Existence'' is a philosophical discussion of existence, truth, knowledge and communication (Consigny 37), and it is here that Gorgias outlines his [[nihilism|nihilistic]] and [[solipsism|solipsistic]] philosophy of existence, whereby he makes a tripartite claim that appears as follows: 1) Nothing exists.  2) Even if something exists, it cannot be known.  3) If it could be known, it could not be communicated (Jarratt 53).  But he does not completely deny the possibility of communication altogether; rather it is [[logos|''logos'']] that is communicated to others (Jarratt 55), because those things that the human mind can know, believe, and communicate are merely mental representations created by ''logos''.  But the relationship between ''logos'' and reality presents a problem because ''logos'', existing only within the realm of human speech and thought, is different from the reality it represents (Walker 27).  The further implications of this argument are that, because human beings are only able to think ''about'' things and cannot think the actual things themselves, as soon as something real is identified by a human it no longer exists in reality (McComiskey 24).
 
 
 
With the aim of establishing a “''technê of logos''” and defending it as a justifiable item of study, Gorgias shows that realities impact the human soul less than had been thought by pre-Socratic theorists (McComiskey 35).
 
 
 
===''Epitaphios'' (or ''Athenian Funeral Oration'')===
 
This text is considered to be an important contribution to the genre of epitaphios.  During the fifth and fourth centuries B.C.E., such funeral orations were delivered by well-known orators during public burial ceremonies in Athens, whereby those who died in wars were honoured.  Gorgias’ text provides a clever critique of fifth century propagandist rhetoric in imperial Athens and is the basis for Plato’s parody, ''[[Menexenus]]'' (Consigny 2).
 
 
 
== Critics ==
 
Plato is one of Gorgias’ greatest critics.  Plato’s dislike for sophistic doctrines is well known, and it is in his eponymous dialogue that both Gorgias himself as well as his rhetorical beliefs are ridiculed (McComiskey 17). 
 
 
 
In the ''Gorgias'', Plato distinguishes between [[philosophy]] and [[rhetoric]], characterizing Gorgias as an orator who entertains his audience with his eloquent words and who believes that it is unnecessary to learn the truth about actual matters when one has discovered the art of persuasion (Consigny 36).  In the dialogue, Gorgias responds to one of Socrates’ statements as follows: “Rhetoric is the only area of expertise you need to learn.  You can ignore all the rest and still get the better of the professionals!” (Plato 24).
 
 
 
Plato is sure to make the distinction between playful oration and serious philosophy, arguing that Gorgias, despite his so-called philosophical work ''On Non-Existence'', is not a true philosopher. Gorgias, whose ''On Non-Existence'' is taken to be critical of the [[Eleatic]] tradition and its founder [[Parmenides]], describes philosophy as a type of seduction, but he does not deny philosophy entirely, giving some respect to philosophers (Consigny 37).
 
 
 
Plato answers Gorgias by reaffirming the Parmenidean ideal that being is the basic substance and reality of which all things are composed, insisting that it is a philosophical dialectic distinct from and superior to rhetoric (Wardy 52).
 
 
 
Aristotle also criticizes Gorgias, labeling him as a mere Sophist whose primary goal is to make money by appearing wise and clever, thus deceiving the public by means of misleading or sophistic arguments (Consigny 36).
 
 
 
== External link ==
 
* [http://www.missouri.edu/~engjnc/texts/gorgias_helen.html Encomium on Helen (engl. translation)]
 
 
 
{{1911}}
 
 
 
{{Presocratics}}
 
 
 
[[Category:483 B.C.E. births]]
 
[[Category:375 B.C.E. deaths]]
 
[[Category:Rhetoricians]]
 
[[Category:Sophists]]
 
[[Category:Sicilian Greeks]]
 
  
 +
[[Plato]] ridiculed Gorgias and his rhetorical beliefs in a well-known dialogue, ''Gorgias''. Plato distinguished between philosophy and rhetoric, characterizing Gorgias as an orator who entertained his audience with eloquent words and who believed that it is unnecessary to learn the truth about actual matters when one has discovered the art of persuasion (Consigny 2001, 36). In the dialogue, Gorgias responded to one of [[Socrates]]’ statements as follows: “Rhetoric is the only area of expertise you need to learn. You can ignore all the rest and still get the better of the professionals!” (Plato, 24). Plato argued that Gorgias was not a true philosopher. Gorgias described philosophy as a type of seduction, but did offer some respect to philosophers (Consigny 2001, 37). Plato answered Gorgias by reaffirming the Parmenidean ideal that being is the basic substance and reality of which all things are composed, insisting that it is a philosophical dialectic distinct from and superior to rhetoric (Wardy 1996, 52).
 +
 +
Aristotle also criticized Gorgias, calling him a mere sophist whose primary goal was to make money by appearing wise and clever, and faulting his excessive use of compound words and overly poetic language.
  
 
== References ==
 
== References ==
 
* Consigny, Scott. ''Gorgias: Sophist and Artist''. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2001.
 
* Consigny, Scott. ''Gorgias: Sophist and Artist''. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2001.
* Gorgias. “Encomium of Helen.” ''The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism''. Eds.  
+
* Gorgias. “Encomium of Helen.” ''The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism''. Eds. Vincent B. Leitch, et al. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 2001. 30-33.
* Vincent B. Leitch, et al. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 2001. 30-33.
 
 
* Jarratt, Susan C. ''Rereading the Sophists: Classical Rhetoric Refigured''. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991.
 
* Jarratt, Susan C. ''Rereading the Sophists: Classical Rhetoric Refigured''. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991.
* Leitch, Vincent B., et al, eds. ''The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism''. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2001.
 
 
* McComiskey, Bruce. ''Gorgias and the New Sophistic Rhetoric''. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 2001.
 
* McComiskey, Bruce. ''Gorgias and the New Sophistic Rhetoric''. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 2001.
 
* Plato. ''Gorgias''. Trans. Robin Waterfield. Oxford University Press, 1994.
 
* Plato. ''Gorgias''. Trans. Robin Waterfield. Oxford University Press, 1994.
Line 90: Line 53:
 
* Wardy, Robert. ''The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato and Their Successors''. New York: Routledge, 1996.
 
* Wardy, Robert. ''The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato and Their Successors''. New York: Routledge, 1996.
  
 +
== External Links ==
 +
All links retrieved June 26, 2017.
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/g/gorgias.htm Gorgias, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/gorgias.html Plato’s Dialogue ''Gorgias'']
 +
===General Philosophy Sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
 +
[[Category:Biography]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
 
 
{{Credit|42996204}}
 
{{Credit|42996204}}

Latest revision as of 14:19, 26 June 2017


Gorgias (in Greek Γοργἰας; c. 483 - 375 B.C.E.), was one of the most important Greek sophists of the fifth century B.C.E., a philosopher, rhetorician, and a gifted writer of artistic prose. Originally a native of Leontini in Sicily, he was sent to Athens in 427 B.C.E. at the head of an embassy to ask for Athenian protection against the aggression of neighboring Syracuse. He subsequently settled in Athens, and supported himself by the practice of oratory and by teaching rhetoric. He died at Larissa in Thessaly. A brilliant rhetorician, Gorgias also contributed to the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the language of literary prose. Several of his works remain in existence. Two of his performatory speeches, Encomium and Palamedes, illustrate the principles he used to make a weak argument strong, and On the Nature of Things uses Eleatic arguments to reach a number of nihilistic conclusions. Gorgias appeared in Plato's dialogues as a moral relativist and one of dialogues was named after him.

Life

Gorgias was a native of Leontini, a Greek colony in Sicily, which is often called the home of Greek rhetoric. Very little is known of his life before he emigrated to Athens, except that he had a father named Charmantides and two siblings; a brother named Herodicus and a sister who dedicated a statue to Gorgias in Delphi (McComiskey 2001, 6-7). In 427 B.C.E. Gorgias was sent to Athens as an ambassador to ask Athenian protection from the aggressive Syracusans (Leitch, et al 29). Gorgias’ impressive oratorical style was said to have brought many of the leading politicians and intellectuals under his influence (Wardy 1996, 6). His mission completed, Gorgias settled in Athens. He was a student of Empedocles, and made a successful living by practicing oratory and teaching rhetoric to students, including Pericles, Critias, Menos, Isocrates and possibly Aspasia. Philostratus (Lives of the Sophists I 9, I) recounts that Gorgias began the practice of extemporaneous oratory, and that he would say to his audiences, "'suggest a subject' ...he was the first to proclaim himself willing to take the chance, showing apparently that he knew everything and would trust the moment to speak on any subject." He spoke at Panhellenic festivals, becoming well-known in Olympia and Delphi. His existing works include the Encomium of Helen, the Defense of Palamedes, On Non-Existence (or On Nature), and Epitaphios. Gorgias is reputed to have lived to be over one hundred years old. He died at Larissa in Thessaly in 375 B.C.E.

Thought and Works

Gorgias of Leontini has been credited with introducing rhetorical innovations involving structure and ornamentation; and paradoxologia, the idea of paradoxical thought and paradoxical expression, to Greece, and is sometimes called the ‘father of sophistry’ (Wardy 1996, 6). Gorgias is also known for contributing to the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the language of literary prose.

Gorgias’ surviving rhetorical works (Encomium of Helen, Defense of Palamedes, On Non-Existence, and Epitaphios) exist in the form of rhetorical exercises that were used to teach his pupils and demonstrate various principles of rhetorical practice. Although some scholars claim that each work presents opposing statements, the four texts can be read as interrelated contributions to the up-and-coming theory and art (technê) of rhetoric (McComiskey 2001, 32). Of Gorgias’ surviving works, only the Encomium and the Defense are believed to exist in their entirety. Gorgias’ Epitaphios is probably only a fragment of a significantly larger funeral oration, and On Non-Existence appears in summary form. These works are each part of the Diels-Kranz collection; although academics consider this source reliable, many of the works included in it are fragmentary and corrupt.

Gorgias’ writings are both rhetorical and performative, exhibiting his ability to make a weak argument appear strong. Each of his works defends positions that are unpopular, paradoxical and even absurd. The performative nature of Gorgias’ writings is exemplified by the way that he playfully approaches each argument with stylistic devices such as parody, artificial figuration and theatricality (Consigny 2001, 149). Gorgias’ style of argumentation can be described as poetics-minus-the-meter (poiêsis-minus-meter). Gorgias argues that persuasive words have power (dunamis) equivalent to that of the gods and as strong as physical force. In the Encomium, Gorgias likens the effect of speech on the soul to the effect of drugs on the body: “Just as different drugs draw forth different humors from the body – some putting a stop to disease, others to life – so too with words: some cause pain, others joy, some strike fear, some stir the audience to boldness, some benumb and bewitch the soul with evil persuasion” (Gorgias, 32).

Gorgias also believed that his "magical incantations" could bring healing to the human psyche by controlling powerful emotions. He paid particular attention to the sounds of words, which, like poetry, could captivate audiences. His florid, rhyming style seemed to hypnotize his audiences (Herrick, 42). Gorgias' legendary powers of persuasion would suggest that he had a somewhat supernatural influence over his audience and their emotions. Gorgias thought that an orator had an ethical obligation to avoid deception, and that it was "…the duty of the same man both to declare what he should rightly and to refute what has been spoken falsely."

Rhetoric and Oratory

Encomium of Helen

Of the three divisions of rhetoric discussed by Aristotle in his Rhetoric (forensic, deliberative, and epideictic), the Encomium can be classified as an epideictic speech, expressing praise for Helen of Troy and absolving her of responsibility for causing the Trojan War. The popular and literary tradition of the time blamed Helen of Troy for instigating the Trojan War by leaving her husband and eloping with Paris.

The Encomium opens with Gorgias explaining that “a man, woman, speech, deed, city or action that is worthy of praise should be honored with acclaim, but the unworthy should be branded with blame” (Gorgias, 30). Gorgias discusses the possible reasons for Helen’s journey to Troy. He explains that Helen could have been persuaded in one of four ways: by the gods, by physical force, by love, or by speech (logos). If it was the plan of the gods that caused Helen to depart for Troy, Gorgias argues that those who blame her should face blame themselves, “for a human’s anticipation cannot restrain a god’s inclination” (Gorgias, 31). Gorgias explains that, by nature, the weak are ruled by the strong, and, since the gods are stronger than humans in all respects, Helen should not be held responsible. If Helen was abducted by force, it is clear that the aggressor committed a crime and should be blamed for the consequences. And if Helen was persuaded by love, she should also be absolved because “…if love is a god, with the divine power of the gods, how could a weaker person refuse and reject him? But if love is a human sickness and a mental weakness, it must not be blamed as mistake, but claimed as misfortune” (Gorgias, 32). Finally, if it was speech that persuaded Helen, she should not be blamed, because speech (logos) is a powerful force that can persuade people to do things against their own interests. In the final section of the Encomium he writes: “I wished to write this speech for Helen’s encomium and my amusement” (Gorgias, 33).

Defense of Palamedes

Defense of Palamedes is another performative speech in which Gorgias shows how plausible arguments can cause an audience to doubt conventional truths. The speech is presented as the legal self-defense, in a trial setting, of Palamedes, a figure from Greek mythology credited with the invention of the alphabet, written laws, numbers, armor, and measures and weights. Odysseus feigned madness in order to avoid going to Troy with Agamemnon and Menelaus to bring Helen back to Sparta. Palamedes tricked Odysseus into revealing that he was only pretending to be mad, and Odysseus never forgave him. Later Odysseus accused him of cooperating with Troy, and Palamedes was condemned and executed.

Throughout the speech, Gorgias composes logical (logos) and ethical (ethos) arguments from possibility, a type of argument that Aristotle later defined as forensic topoi. Palamedes rejects the use of emotional arguments (pathos), saying "among you, who are the foremost of the Greeks...there is no need to persuade such ones as you with the aid of friends and sorrowful prayers and lamentations." Gorgias posits that in order to prove that treason was committed, we must first establish that a set of possible events took place. In the Defense these events are: communication between Palamedes and the enemy, exchange of a pledge in the form of hostages or money, and not being detected by guards or citizens. In his defense, Palamedes claims that a small sum of money would not have warranted such a large undertaking and reasons that a large sum of money, if indeed such a transaction had been made, would have required the aid of many confederates to transport it. Palamedes reasons further that such an exchange could neither have occurred at night because the guards would be watching, nor in the day because everyone would be able to see. Palamedes continues, explaining that if the aforementioned conditions were, in fact, arranged then action would need to follow. Such action would take place either with or without confederates. If these confederates were free men then they were free to disclose any information they desired, and had not done so. If they were slaves there was a risk of them voluntarily accusing to earn freedom, or accusing by force when tortured. Slaves, Palamedes says, are untrustworthy. Palamedes goes on to list a variety of possible motives for committing treason, such as status, wealth, honor or security, all of which he proves groundless.

On Nature, or the Non-Existent

The original work has been lost, and there are two existing transcripts which differ slightly from each other, one preserved by the philosopher Sextus Empirica in Against the Professors, and another by the author (possible Aristotle or Theophrastus) of De Melissus, Xenophane, Gorgia. There is some disagreement among scholars as to whether this was intended as a serious philosophical work, or as a caricature of the metaphysical arguments of Parmenides.

The subject of On Nature is ontological (about the nature of being), and it also discusses epistemology and language. It is also a rhetorical exercise that showcases Gorgias’ oratorical skill. He attacks the idea that if we examine our world, we must conclude that things exist, and demonstrates that 1) Nothing exists; 2) Even if existence exists, it cannot be known; and 3) Even if it could be known, it cannot be communicated.

He does not completely deny the possibility of communication altogether; rather it is logos that is communicated to others (Jarratt 1991, 55), because those things that the human mind can know, believe, and communicate are merely mental representations created by logos. But the relationship between logos and reality presents a problem because logos, existing only within the realm of human speech and thought, is different from the reality it represents (Walker 2000, 27).

This argument has led some to label Gorgias as either an ontological skeptic or a nihilist (one who believes nothing exists, or that the world is incomprehensible, and that the concept of truth is fictitious). But it can also be interpreted as an assertion that it is logos and logos alone which is the proper object of our inquiries, since it is the only thing we can really know. On Nature is sometimes seen as a refutation of pre-Socratic essentialist philosophy (McComiskey 2001, 37).

Critics

Gorgias and other sophists were often criticized for placing more emphasis on rhetoric and oratory than on a legitimate quest for truth, and for tearing down arguments rather than building a system of thought which could make a positive contribution to the improvement of society. Oratory played an important role in the Athenian democracy, where the ability to persuade an audience meant political influence and power. Teachers of rhetoric made a living by giving instruction on how to argue successfully.

Plato ridiculed Gorgias and his rhetorical beliefs in a well-known dialogue, Gorgias. Plato distinguished between philosophy and rhetoric, characterizing Gorgias as an orator who entertained his audience with eloquent words and who believed that it is unnecessary to learn the truth about actual matters when one has discovered the art of persuasion (Consigny 2001, 36). In the dialogue, Gorgias responded to one of Socrates’ statements as follows: “Rhetoric is the only area of expertise you need to learn. You can ignore all the rest and still get the better of the professionals!” (Plato, 24). Plato argued that Gorgias was not a true philosopher. Gorgias described philosophy as a type of seduction, but did offer some respect to philosophers (Consigny 2001, 37). Plato answered Gorgias by reaffirming the Parmenidean ideal that being is the basic substance and reality of which all things are composed, insisting that it is a philosophical dialectic distinct from and superior to rhetoric (Wardy 1996, 52).

Aristotle also criticized Gorgias, calling him a mere sophist whose primary goal was to make money by appearing wise and clever, and faulting his excessive use of compound words and overly poetic language.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Consigny, Scott. Gorgias: Sophist and Artist. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press, 2001.
  • Gorgias. “Encomium of Helen.” The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. Eds. Vincent B. Leitch, et al. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 2001. 30-33.
  • Jarratt, Susan C. Rereading the Sophists: Classical Rhetoric Refigured. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991.
  • McComiskey, Bruce. Gorgias and the New Sophistic Rhetoric. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 2001.
  • Plato. Gorgias. Trans. Robin Waterfield. Oxford University Press, 1994.
  • Walker, Jeffrey. Rhetoric and Poetics in Antiquity. New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.
  • Wardy, Robert. The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato and Their Successors. New York: Routledge, 1996.

External Links

All links retrieved June 26, 2017.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.