Knight, Frank Hyneman

From New World Encyclopedia
({{Contracted}})
m
(16 intermediate revisions by 5 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
[[Category:Politics and social sciences]]
+
[[Category:Economists]]
[[Category:Economics]]
 
[[Category:Biography]]
 
{{Claimed}}{{Started}}{{Contracted}}
 
{{epname}}
 
  
'''Frank Hyneman Knight''' (November 7, 1885 - April 15, 1972) was an [[United States|American]] [[economics|economist]], the central figure in the development of the [[Chicago School of Economics]]. He remains famous for his ''Knightian uncertainty'', the distinction between [[risk]] and uncertainty, and for his work on [[ethics]] in economics.
+
{{Submitted}}{{Images OK}}{{Approved}}{{Paid}}{{Copyedited}}
 +
{{epname|Knight, Frank Hyneman}}
  
 +
'''Frank Hyneman Knight''' (November 7, 1885 - April 15, 1972) was an [[United States|American]] [[economics|economist]]. He remains famous for his "Knightian uncertainty," the distinction between [[risk]] and uncertainty, and for his work on [[ethics]] in economics. Knight was the central figure in the development of the "[[Chicago School of Economics]]," and the teacher of [[Nobel Prize]] winners in economics [[Milton Friedman]], [[George Stigler]], and [[James M. Buchanan]]. An eclectic thinker, Knight contributed significantly to the development of American economic thought in the twentieth century, and thus, directly or indirectly, was influential in determining the course of prosperity in human [[society]].
 +
{{toc}}
 
==Life==
 
==Life==
  
'''Frank Knight''' was born in MacLean County, [[Illinois]] into a family of devoutly [[Christianity|Christian]] farmers. He never completed high school but was admitted in 1905 to the American University in [[Tennessee]]. He graduated in 1911 from the Milligan College. At the [[University of Tennessee]], he obtained a B.S. and an M.A. (the latter in [[German language|German]]) in 1913. He then moved to [[Cornell University]] for doctoral studies. His initial subject of interest was [[philosophy]], but he soon switched to [[economics]]. He studied with [[Alvin Johnson]] and [[Allyn Young]], who both supervised the work on his dissertation, that was completed in 1916 under the title ''Cost, Value and Profit'' (later renamed into ''Risk, Uncertainty and Profit'' and published in 1921).
+
'''Frank Hyneman Knight''' was born on November 7, 1885 in MacLean County, [[Illinois]] into a family of devoutly [[Christianity|Christian]] farmers. He never completed [[high school]] but was admitted in 1905 to the American University in [[Tennessee]]. He graduated in 1911 from the Milligan College. At the [[University of Tennessee]], he obtained a B.S. and an M.A. (the latter in [[German language|German]]) in 1913. He then moved to [[Cornell University]] for doctoral studies. His initial subject of interest was [[philosophy]], but he soon switched to [[economics]]. He studied with [[Alvin Johnson]] and [[Allyn Young]], who both supervised the work on his dissertation, which was completed in 1916 under the title ''Cost, Value and Profit'' (later renamed into ''Risk, Uncertainty and Profit'' and published in 1921).
  
Knight first taught at the [[University of Iowa]] from 1919 to 1927, after which he transferred to the [[University of Chicago]], where he served as Professor of Economics from 1927 until 1955, and as emeritus professor until his death. Under his presidency, the Department of Economics at the University of Chicago grew to become one of the dominant schools of economical thought in the [[United States]].  
+
Knight first taught at the [[University of Iowa]] from 1919 to 1927, after which he transferred to the [[University of Chicago]], where he served as Professor of Economics from 1927 until 1955, and as emeritus professor until his death. Under his presidency, the Department of Economics at the University of Chicago grew to become one of the dominant schools of economic thought in the [[United States]].  
  
 
Knight died on April 15, 1972 in [[Chicago]], [[Illinois]].
 
Knight died on April 15, 1972 in [[Chicago]], [[Illinois]].
Line 17: Line 16:
 
==Work==
 
==Work==
  
Knight’s famous dissertation ''Risk, Uncertainty and Profit'' from 1921 remains one of the most interesting reads in [[economics]] even today. In it, Knight made his famous distinction between "[[risk]]" (randomness with knowable probabilities) and "uncertainty" (randomness with unknowable [[probability|probabilities]]), set forth the role of the entrepreneur in a distinctive [[theory of profit]] and gave one of the earliest presentations of the now-famous law of variable proportions in the [[theory of production]].  
+
Knight’s famous dissertation ''Risk, Uncertainty and Profit'' from 1921 remains one of the most interesting reads in [[economics]] even today. Knight made his famous distinction between "[[risk]]" (randomness with knowable [[probability|probabilities]]) and "uncertainty" (randomness with unknowable probabilities) and set forth the role of the [[entrepreneur]] in a distinctive theory of [[profit]].
 +
<blockquote>Uncertainty must be taken in a sense radically distinct from the familiar notion of Risk, from which it has never been properly separated...The essential fact is that "risk" means in some cases a quantity susceptible of measurement, while at other times it is something distinctly not of this character; and there are far-reaching and crucial differences in the bearings of the phenomena depending on which of the two is really present and operating...It will appear that a measurable uncertainty, or "risk" proper, as we shall use the term, is so far different from an unmeasurable one that it is not in effect an uncertainty at all (Knight 1921).  
 +
</blockquote>
  
He argued that situations with risk were those where decision making was made faced with unknown outcomes but known ex-ante probability distributions. He argued that these situations, where decision making rules such as maximizing expected [[utility]] can be applied, differ in a deep way from those where the [[probability]] distribution of a random outcome is unknown. While most economists today would recognize the difference between the two situations, there has been little progress in terms of writing models and doing empirical tests of problems with ''Knightian uncertainty''. A possible exception is the "Markets from Networks" model developed by [[sociology|sociologist]] [[Harrison White]] in 2002.
+
He argued that situations with risk were those where decision making was made faced with unknown outcomes but known probability distributions. He argued that these situations, where decision making rules such as maximizing expected [[utility]] can be applied, differ in a deep way from those where the probability distribution of a random outcome is unknown. While most economists now recognize the difference between the two situations, there has been little progress in terms of writing models and doing empirical tests of problems with "Knightian uncertainty," with the exception of the "Markets from Networks" model developed by [[sociology|sociologist]] [[Harrison White]] in 2002.
  
Knight also made contributions to the arguments about [[toll road]]s. He said that rather than congestion justifying government tolling of roads, privately owned roads would set tolls to reduce congestion to its efficient level. In particular, he developed the argument that forms the basis of analysis of traffic equilibrium, and has since become known as [[Wardrop's Principle]].
+
Knight also made a contribution to the debate over toll roads. He said that rather than congestion justifying government tolling of roads as argued by [[Arthur Cecil Pigou|Pigou]], privately owned roads would set tolls to reduce congestion to its efficient level. In particular, he developed a simple behavioral principle to describe the spreading of trips over alternate routes due to congested conditions. Knight's concept has since become known as [[Wardrop's Principle]] and forms the basis of the analysis of traffic equilibrium.  
  
While irreducibly [[Neoclassical economics|Neoclassical]] in a general sense, Knight's peculiar economics were a direct inheritance of his Cornell professor, [[Herbert J. Davenport]] and what was then called the "American Psychological School" which sought to ground the Marginalist high theory of [[Jevons]], [[Philip Wicksteed|Wicksteed]] and the [[Austrian school|Austrians]] in the relativist foundations of [[Thorstein Veblen]]'s methodology.  
+
While irreducibly [[Neoclassical economics|Neoclassical]] in a general sense, Knight's peculiar economics were a direct inheritance of his [[Cornell University|Cornell]] professor, [[Herbert J. Davenport]] and what was then called the "American Psychological School" which sought to ground the Marginalist high theory of [[William Stanley Jevons|Jevons]], [[Philip Wicksteed|Wicksteed]] and the [[Austrian school|Austrians]] in the relativist foundations of [[Thorstein Veblen]]'s methodology.  
  
Knight criticized other schools on several accounts while also adopting some of their ideas. For instance, from the [[Lausanne school|Walrasians]] he adopted the idea of theoretical rigor and viewing the economy in terms of multiple markets, but disparaged their mathematical propensities. From the Austrians, he adopted their theory of alternative cost, but attacked their theory of capital. From the [[Alfred Marshall|Marshallians]], he adopted their literary tone, but attacked their lack of rigor and their "real" theory of cost. From the [[David Ricardo|Ricardians]], he adopted a concern with the interaction between social structure and theory but attacked the objectivist basis of their theory. From the [[Marxian economics|Marxians]], he adopted many of their ideas about the ethical critique of capitalism as well as its tendency towards the concentration of capital, but he abhorred the [[labor theory of value]]. From the [[Institutional economics|Institutionalists]], he adopted their concern with social impact on behavior and evolution, but he opposed their empirical techniques and conclusions ("history is to be sensed, not plotted," as Knight put it).   
+
Knight criticized other schools on several accounts while also adopting some of their ideas. For instance, from the [[Leon Walras|Walrasians]] he adopted the idea of theoretical rigor and viewing the [[economy]] in terms of multiple [[market]]s, but disparaged their [[mathematics|mathematical]] propensities. From the [[Austria]]ns, he adopted their theory of alternative [[cost]], but attacked their theory of [[capital]]. From the [[Alfred Marshall|Marshallians]], he adopted their literary tone, but attacked their lack of rigor and their "real" theory of cost. From the [[David Ricardo|Ricardians]], he adopted a concern with the interaction between [[social structure]] and theory but attacked the objectivist basis of their theory. From the [[Marxism|Marxians]], he adopted many of their ideas about the ethical critique of capitalism as well as its tendency towards the concentration of capital, but he abhorred the [[labor theory of value]]. From the [[Institutional economics|Institutionalists]], he adopted their concern with social impact on behavior and evolution, but he opposed their empirical techniques and conclusions ("history is to be sensed, not plotted," as Knight put it).   
  
Knight was one of the leaders of the "Chicago School" (although we must keep in mind that during his stay there, the [[Chicago School]] had a much different tone than it acquired later). Knight's well-known dislike of quantitative methods and especially empirical techniques brought him into conflict with several colleagues - notably, [[Henry Schultz]], [[Paul Douglas]] and [[Oskar Lange]]. His opposition to the Marshallian propensities of his co-giant, [[Jacob Viner]], earned him the latter's respect but not necessarily his friendship. Even Knight's own unlikely protégé [[Henry Simons]], differed substantially from Knight on most matters.
+
Knight was one of the leaders of the "Chicago School" (although his Chicago School was much different from what it later became). However, his dislike of quantitative methods and empirical techniques brought him into conflict with several colleagues. His opposition to the Marshallian views of [[Jacob Viner]] earned him the latter's respect but not necessarily his friendship. Even [[Henry Simons]], Knight's student, differed substantially from Knight on most matters.
  
Like [[Joseph Schumpeter]] (whom he both admired and resembled in many ways), Knight was an avid proponent of a cosmopolitan [[laissez-faire]]. As is evident in his famous ''Ethics of Competition'' (1923) and in other works on [[ethics]] throughout his life, Knight does not regard the capitalist system as ethically defensible. Capitalism, he claims, does not produce what people want but merely creates the wants for what it produces. He said:
+
Like [[Joseph Schumpeter]] (whom he both admired and resembled in many ways), Knight was an avid proponent of a cosmopolitan [[laissez-faire]]. As is evident in his famous ''Ethics of Competition'' (1923) and in other works on [[ethics]] throughout his life, Knight did not regard the [[capitalism|capitalist]] system as ethically defensible. He argued that there was a tendency in market systems towards [[monopoly]], and that the "efficiency" of markets was misleading for there was no sense of "usefulness" of its output to society. Capitalism, he claimed, does not produce what people want but merely creates the wants for what it produces:
 +
<blockquote>the freest individual...is in large measure a product of the economic environment that has formed his desires and needs, given him whatever marketable productive capacities he has, and which largely controls his opportunities (Knight 1923). </blockquote>
  
:"the freest individual...is in large measure a product of the economic environment that has formed his desires and needs, given him whatever marketable productive capacities he has, and which largely controls his opportunities." (''Ethics of Competition', 1923).  
+
However, these attacks on capitalism did not cause him to reject laissez-faire as the best option. The economy, he argued, was very complex and unstable. Government intervention did not take into account the complexities of a market economy, making interventionism dangerous. Thus, he concluded that laissez-faire is recommended, not because it "works," but rather because it holds individual freedom as an absolute good and that the alternative may be much worse.  
  
Furthermore, he argued that there was a tendency in market systems towards [[monopoly]], that the "efficiency" of markets was misleading for there was no sense of "usefulness" of its output to society, that the [[marginal productivity|marginal productivity thesis]] had erroneous ethical implications.
+
As a result, Knight's position opposite to the Second Chicago School economists of the 1960s, including [[Milton Friedman|Friedman]] and [[George Stigler|Stigler]]. They tended to argue the positivist line that laissez-faire is desirable because it works, and not because it is a good in itself.
 
 
Knight's peculiar ethical assault on the market system and "apologetic economics" did not diminish his penchant for laissez-faire as a policy conclusion. The economy, he argued, was a very complex and unstable thing. Programs of government intervention were too simplistic and did not take into account the complexities of a market economy - thus making interventionism even more dangerous. Laissez-faire is recommended, he argued, not because it "works", but rather because it holds individual freedom as an absolute good and that the alternative may be much worse. 
 
 
 
As a result, Knight's position is quite the reverse of the Second Chicago School economists of the 1960s, (i.e. [[ Milton Friedman|Friedman]], [[ George Stigler|Stigler]] and company). The Second Chicago School tended to argue the positivist line that laissez-faire is desirable because it delivers the goods, and not because it is a good in itself. Indeed, throughout his life, Knight explicitly deplored and attacked many of the assumptions that the Second Chicago School held dear, e.g. the denial of the importance of monopolistic competition, the assumption of consumer sovereignty, stable preferences, efficient outcomes of markets, empirical-intuitive reasoning, interdisciplinary imperialism, etc.
 
  
 
==Legacy==
 
==Legacy==
  
Knight was one of the century's most eclectic economists and perhaps the deepest thinker and scholar American economics has produced. Jointly with [[Jacob Viner]], Knight presided over the Department of Economics at the [[University of Chicago]] from the 1920s to the late 1940s, and played a central role in setting the character of that department that was perhaps only comparable to [[Joseph Schumpeter|Schumpeter]]'s tenure over [[Harvard]] or [[Lionel Robbins|Robbins]]'s at the [[London School of Economics|L.S.E]].
+
Frank Hyneman Knight was one of the twentieth century's most eclectic [[economics|economists]] and one of the deepest thinkers American economics has produced. Jointly with [[Jacob Viner]], Knight presided over the Department of Economics at the [[University of Chicago]] from the 1920s to the late 1940s, playing a central role in setting the character of that department.
  
Knight carved a unique path in economics — being claimed by many schools of thought as one of their own, without really belonging to any. Unfortunately, although he educated and influenced many students, Knight failed to acquire any followers and failed to build up a distinctive "school of thought" around himself. We can see some traces of his perspective in the work of [[Kenneth E. Boulding]], [[Martin Bronfenbrenner]], [[James M. Buchanan]] and [[George J. Stigler]], but they can hardly be called "Knightians" in any meaningful sense.   
+
Knight carved his own unique path in economics, claimed by many schools of thought as one of their own, without really belonging to any. Unfortunately though, although he educated and influenced many students, he acquired no followers and thus failed to build up his own distinctive school of thought.   
  
Nobel laureate [[Milton Friedman]] was one of Knight's many students at the [[University of Chicago]].
+
Nobel laureates [[Milton Friedman]], [[James M. Buchanan]], and [[George J. Stigler]], were Knight's students at the [[University of Chicago]], although their ideas differed in many respects from those of Knight.
  
 
==Publications==
 
==Publications==
  
* Knight, Frank H. 1921. Cost of production and price over long and short periods.'' Journal of Political Economy, 29''(4), 304-335
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1921. "Cost of production and price over long and short periods" in ''Journal of Political Economy, 29''. (4), 304-335.
* Knight, Frank H. 1924. The limitations of scientific method in economics. In R.G. Tugwell (Ed.), ''Trend of Economics''. A.A. Knopf
+
*Knight, Frank H. [1921] 2006. ''Risk, uncertainty and profit''. Cosmo Classics. ISBN 1602060053
* Knight, Frank H. 1933. ''The economic organisation with an article: Notes on utility and cost''. New York: Harper and Row
+
*Knight, Frank H. [1923] 1997. ''The ethics of competition and other essays''. Transaction Publishers. ISBN 1560009551
* Knight, Frank H. 1935. ''Economic theory and nationalism''. London: Allen & Unwin.
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1924. "The limitations of scientific method in economics" in ''Trend of Economics''. A.A. Knopf.
* Knight, Frank H. 1936. ''The quantity of capital and the rate of interest''. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1933. ''The economic organisation with an article: Notes on utility and cost''. New York: Harper and Row.
* Knight, Frank H. 1942. Fact and value in social science. In R.N. Anshen (Ed.), ''Science and Man''. Harcourt, Brace and Company
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1935. ''Economic theory and nationalism''. London: Allen & Unwin.
* Knight, Frank H. 1956. ''On the history and methods of economics: Selected essays''. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226446891
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1936. ''The quantity of capital and the rate of interest''. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
* Knight, Frank H. 1960. ''Intelligence and democratic action''. Harvard University Press
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1942. "Fact and value in social science" in ''Science and Man''. Harcourt, Brace and Company.
* Knight, Frank H. 1982 (original published in 1947). ''Freedom and Reform: Essays in economics and social philosophy''. Liberty Fund. ISBN 086597005X
+
*Knight, Frank H. [1947] 1982. ''Freedom and Reform: Essays in economics and social philosophy''. Liberty Fund. ISBN 086597005X
* Knight, Frank H. 1991. The case for Communism: From the standpoint of an ex-liberal. In W.J. Samuels ''Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology'' (Supplement 2). JAI Press. ISBN 1559382457
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1956. ''On the history and methods of economics: Selected essays''. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226446891
* Knight, Frank H. 1997 (original published in 1923). ''The ethics of competition and other essays''. Transaction Publishers. ISBN 1560009551
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1960. ''Intelligence and democratic action''. Harvard University Press.
* Knight, Frank H. 2006 (original published in 1921). ''Risk, uncertainty and profit''. Cosmo Classics. ISBN 1602060053
+
*Knight, Frank H. 1991. "The case for Communism: From the standpoint of an ex-liberal" in ''Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology''. JAI Press. ISBN 1559382457
* Knight, Frank H. & T.W. Merriam. 1979 (original published in 1945). ''The economic order and religion''. Greenwood Press. ISBN 0313209707
+
*Knight, Frank H., and T.W. Merriam. [1945] 1979. ''The economic order and religion''. Greenwood Press. ISBN 0313209707
  
 
==References==
 
==References==
  
* Bookrags.com. ''Frank Hyneman Knight''. Retrieved on April 18, 2007, <http://www.bookrags.com/biography/frank-hyneman-knight/>
+
*Bookrags.com. [http://www.bookrags.com/biography/frank-hyneman-knight/ ''Frank Hyneman Knight'']. Bookrags, 2006. Retrieved on April 18, 2007.
* Emmett, Ross. 2007. Introduction. In Ross Emmett (Ed.) ''Selected Essays by Frank H. Knight'', (2 vols.). University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226446964
+
*Emmett, Ross. 2007. "Introduction" in ''Selected Essays by Frank H. Knight''. (2 vols.). University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226446964
* Kasper, Sherryl. 2003. ''The Revival of Laissez-Faire in American Macroeconomic Theory: A Case Study of Its Pioneers''. Edward Elgar Publishing. ISBN 1840646063
+
*Kasper, Sherryl. 2003. ''The Revival of Laissez-Faire in American Macroeconomic Theory: A Case Study of Its Pioneers''. Edward Elgar Publishing. ISBN 1840646063
* White, Harrison C. 2004. ''Markets from Networks: Socioeconomic Models of Production'', Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691120382
+
*White, Harrison C. 2004. ''Markets from Networks: Socioeconomic Models of Production''. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691120382
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved April 26, 2017.
  
* [http://cepa.newschool.edu/het/schools/chicago.htm Chicago School of Economics] – On the Chicago School of Economics
+
* [http://www.msu.edu/~emmettr/fhk/ Frank H. Knight Page] – Knight’s page on Minnesota State University website.
* [http://www.msu.edu/~emmettr/fhk/ Frank H. Knight Page] – Knight’s page on Minnesota State University website
+
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/bios/Knight.html Frank Hyneman Knight] – Biography in the Concise Encyclopedia of Economics.  
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/bios/Knight.html Frank Hyneman Knight] – Biography in the Concise Encyclopedia of Economics
 
* [http://cepa.newschool.edu/het/profiles/knight.htm Profile of Frank Knight] – Biography on the History of Economic Thought website
 
 
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Knight/knRUP.html ''Risk, Uncertainty and Profit''] – Full-text work by Knight (1921).  
 
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Knight/knRUP.html ''Risk, Uncertainty and Profit''] – Full-text work by Knight (1921).  
  
 +
{{Chicago school economists}}
 
{{Credits|Frank_Knight|118042844|}}
 
{{Credits|Frank_Knight|118042844|}}

Revision as of 15:20, 26 April 2017


Frank Hyneman Knight (November 7, 1885 - April 15, 1972) was an American economist. He remains famous for his "Knightian uncertainty," the distinction between risk and uncertainty, and for his work on ethics in economics. Knight was the central figure in the development of the "Chicago School of Economics," and the teacher of Nobel Prize winners in economics Milton Friedman, George Stigler, and James M. Buchanan. An eclectic thinker, Knight contributed significantly to the development of American economic thought in the twentieth century, and thus, directly or indirectly, was influential in determining the course of prosperity in human society.

Life

Frank Hyneman Knight was born on November 7, 1885 in MacLean County, Illinois into a family of devoutly Christian farmers. He never completed high school but was admitted in 1905 to the American University in Tennessee. He graduated in 1911 from the Milligan College. At the University of Tennessee, he obtained a B.S. and an M.A. (the latter in German) in 1913. He then moved to Cornell University for doctoral studies. His initial subject of interest was philosophy, but he soon switched to economics. He studied with Alvin Johnson and Allyn Young, who both supervised the work on his dissertation, which was completed in 1916 under the title Cost, Value and Profit (later renamed into Risk, Uncertainty and Profit and published in 1921).

Knight first taught at the University of Iowa from 1919 to 1927, after which he transferred to the University of Chicago, where he served as Professor of Economics from 1927 until 1955, and as emeritus professor until his death. Under his presidency, the Department of Economics at the University of Chicago grew to become one of the dominant schools of economic thought in the United States.

Knight died on April 15, 1972 in Chicago, Illinois.

Work

Knight’s famous dissertation Risk, Uncertainty and Profit from 1921 remains one of the most interesting reads in economics even today. Knight made his famous distinction between "risk" (randomness with knowable probabilities) and "uncertainty" (randomness with unknowable probabilities) and set forth the role of the entrepreneur in a distinctive theory of profit.

Uncertainty must be taken in a sense radically distinct from the familiar notion of Risk, from which it has never been properly separated...The essential fact is that "risk" means in some cases a quantity susceptible of measurement, while at other times it is something distinctly not of this character; and there are far-reaching and crucial differences in the bearings of the phenomena depending on which of the two is really present and operating...It will appear that a measurable uncertainty, or "risk" proper, as we shall use the term, is so far different from an unmeasurable one that it is not in effect an uncertainty at all (Knight 1921).

He argued that situations with risk were those where decision making was made faced with unknown outcomes but known probability distributions. He argued that these situations, where decision making rules such as maximizing expected utility can be applied, differ in a deep way from those where the probability distribution of a random outcome is unknown. While most economists now recognize the difference between the two situations, there has been little progress in terms of writing models and doing empirical tests of problems with "Knightian uncertainty," with the exception of the "Markets from Networks" model developed by sociologist Harrison White in 2002.

Knight also made a contribution to the debate over toll roads. He said that rather than congestion justifying government tolling of roads as argued by Pigou, privately owned roads would set tolls to reduce congestion to its efficient level. In particular, he developed a simple behavioral principle to describe the spreading of trips over alternate routes due to congested conditions. Knight's concept has since become known as Wardrop's Principle and forms the basis of the analysis of traffic equilibrium.

While irreducibly Neoclassical in a general sense, Knight's peculiar economics were a direct inheritance of his Cornell professor, Herbert J. Davenport and what was then called the "American Psychological School" which sought to ground the Marginalist high theory of Jevons, Wicksteed and the Austrians in the relativist foundations of Thorstein Veblen's methodology.

Knight criticized other schools on several accounts while also adopting some of their ideas. For instance, from the Walrasians he adopted the idea of theoretical rigor and viewing the economy in terms of multiple markets, but disparaged their mathematical propensities. From the Austrians, he adopted their theory of alternative cost, but attacked their theory of capital. From the Marshallians, he adopted their literary tone, but attacked their lack of rigor and their "real" theory of cost. From the Ricardians, he adopted a concern with the interaction between social structure and theory but attacked the objectivist basis of their theory. From the Marxians, he adopted many of their ideas about the ethical critique of capitalism as well as its tendency towards the concentration of capital, but he abhorred the labor theory of value. From the Institutionalists, he adopted their concern with social impact on behavior and evolution, but he opposed their empirical techniques and conclusions ("history is to be sensed, not plotted," as Knight put it).

Knight was one of the leaders of the "Chicago School" (although his Chicago School was much different from what it later became). However, his dislike of quantitative methods and empirical techniques brought him into conflict with several colleagues. His opposition to the Marshallian views of Jacob Viner earned him the latter's respect but not necessarily his friendship. Even Henry Simons, Knight's student, differed substantially from Knight on most matters.

Like Joseph Schumpeter (whom he both admired and resembled in many ways), Knight was an avid proponent of a cosmopolitan laissez-faire. As is evident in his famous Ethics of Competition (1923) and in other works on ethics throughout his life, Knight did not regard the capitalist system as ethically defensible. He argued that there was a tendency in market systems towards monopoly, and that the "efficiency" of markets was misleading for there was no sense of "usefulness" of its output to society. Capitalism, he claimed, does not produce what people want but merely creates the wants for what it produces:

the freest individual...is in large measure a product of the economic environment that has formed his desires and needs, given him whatever marketable productive capacities he has, and which largely controls his opportunities (Knight 1923).

However, these attacks on capitalism did not cause him to reject laissez-faire as the best option. The economy, he argued, was very complex and unstable. Government intervention did not take into account the complexities of a market economy, making interventionism dangerous. Thus, he concluded that laissez-faire is recommended, not because it "works," but rather because it holds individual freedom as an absolute good and that the alternative may be much worse.

As a result, Knight's position opposite to the Second Chicago School economists of the 1960s, including Friedman and Stigler. They tended to argue the positivist line that laissez-faire is desirable because it works, and not because it is a good in itself.

Legacy

Frank Hyneman Knight was one of the twentieth century's most eclectic economists and one of the deepest thinkers American economics has produced. Jointly with Jacob Viner, Knight presided over the Department of Economics at the University of Chicago from the 1920s to the late 1940s, playing a central role in setting the character of that department.

Knight carved his own unique path in economics, claimed by many schools of thought as one of their own, without really belonging to any. Unfortunately though, although he educated and influenced many students, he acquired no followers and thus failed to build up his own distinctive school of thought.

Nobel laureates Milton Friedman, James M. Buchanan, and George J. Stigler, were Knight's students at the University of Chicago, although their ideas differed in many respects from those of Knight.

Publications

  • Knight, Frank H. 1921. "Cost of production and price over long and short periods" in Journal of Political Economy, 29. (4), 304-335.
  • Knight, Frank H. [1921] 2006. Risk, uncertainty and profit. Cosmo Classics. ISBN 1602060053
  • Knight, Frank H. [1923] 1997. The ethics of competition and other essays. Transaction Publishers. ISBN 1560009551
  • Knight, Frank H. 1924. "The limitations of scientific method in economics" in Trend of Economics. A.A. Knopf.
  • Knight, Frank H. 1933. The economic organisation with an article: Notes on utility and cost. New York: Harper and Row.
  • Knight, Frank H. 1935. Economic theory and nationalism. London: Allen & Unwin.
  • Knight, Frank H. 1936. The quantity of capital and the rate of interest. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Knight, Frank H. 1942. "Fact and value in social science" in Science and Man. Harcourt, Brace and Company.
  • Knight, Frank H. [1947] 1982. Freedom and Reform: Essays in economics and social philosophy. Liberty Fund. ISBN 086597005X
  • Knight, Frank H. 1956. On the history and methods of economics: Selected essays. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226446891
  • Knight, Frank H. 1960. Intelligence and democratic action. Harvard University Press.
  • Knight, Frank H. 1991. "The case for Communism: From the standpoint of an ex-liberal" in Research in the History of Economic Thought and Methodology. JAI Press. ISBN 1559382457
  • Knight, Frank H., and T.W. Merriam. [1945] 1979. The economic order and religion. Greenwood Press. ISBN 0313209707

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Bookrags.com. Frank Hyneman Knight. Bookrags, 2006. Retrieved on April 18, 2007.
  • Emmett, Ross. 2007. "Introduction" in Selected Essays by Frank H. Knight. (2 vols.). University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0226446964
  • Kasper, Sherryl. 2003. The Revival of Laissez-Faire in American Macroeconomic Theory: A Case Study of Its Pioneers. Edward Elgar Publishing. ISBN 1840646063
  • White, Harrison C. 2004. Markets from Networks: Socioeconomic Models of Production. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691120382

External links

All links retrieved April 26, 2017.

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.