Difference between revisions of "Al-Ghazali" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 11: Line 11:
 
Now, love of retirement and of a life of ease seemed to be keeping him from teaching and when he consulted his friends urged him to return to Nish which had become lax, pointing out the promise of a renewer (''mujaddid'') towards the start of each new century (499)
 
Now, love of retirement and of a life of ease seemed to be keeping him from teaching and when he consulted his friends urged him to return to Nish which had become lax, pointing out the promise of a renewer (''mujaddid'') towards the start of each new century (499)
 
...............................
 
...............................
Finally he returned to his hometown of Tus, where he took charge of a khanka (Sufi hospice or even monastery, which included a study house). During this time Ghazali had written his most important work, ''Ihya ulum al-din'' (''The Revivication of the Religious Sciences''), which again immediately singled him out as the most important theologians of the day. He ended his seclusion for a short lecturing period, at the behest of [[Fakhr al-Mulk]], the vizier of the [[Seljuk]] ruler of Khorasan, at the Nizamiyyah of Tus in [[1106]]. Here he wrote his autobiography ''[[al-Munqidh min al-dalal]]''. Here he remained until his death in [[December]], [[1111]].
+
Finally he returned to his hometown of Tus, where he took charge of a khanka (Sufi hospice or even monastery, which included a study house). During this time Ghazali had written his most important work, ''Ihya ulum al-din'' (''The Revivication of the Religious Sciences''), which again immediately singled him out as the most important theologians of the day. The work is in many respects his own answer to the Incoherency, since he details in four volumes and ten books how the religious life shoould be lived, what knowledge is beneficial, what knowledge harmful (or blameworthy) and how beneficial knowledge should be acquired and spread.  He regards both the pursuit and the sharing of knowledge as profoundly Islamic, and suggests that knowledge is 'seeing things as they really are, which is one of the attributes of Allah' (Faris edition, Book One, Section Three: 1).
 +
He ended his seclusion for a short lecturing period, at the behest of [[Fakhr al-Mulk]], the vizier of the [[Seljuk]] ruler of Khorasan, at the Nizamiyyah of Tus in [[1106]]. He wrote t his autobiography ''[[al-Munqidh min al-dalal]]'' there and remained until his death in December, 1111.  
  
Ghazali, throughout his life, also identified himself with the [[Asharite]] [[kalam]]. This identification is bolstered by the fact that his teacher, al-Juwayni, was also in his lifetime a leading master of Asharite kalam. And this association affected much of his theological output. This is evidenced in his [[11th century]] book ''"[[The Incoherence of the Philosophers]]"'' which marks a major turn in Islamic [[epistemology]], as Ghazali effectively discovered philosophical [[skepticism]] that would not be commonly seen in the [[Western world|west]] until [[George Berkeley]] and [[David Hume]] in the [[18th century]]. The encounter with skepticism led Ghazali to embrace a form of theological [[occasionalism]], or the belief that all causal events and interactions are not the product of material conjunctions but rather the immediate and present will of [[Allah]], the Islamic [[divine being]]. Some regard that logical consequence of this belief in practice, and an outcome that has developed in part from it over the subsequent centuries, has been a turn towards [[Islamic fundamentalism|fundamentalism in many Islamic societies]]. Ghazali probably did contribute to the decline of philosophy in Islamic thought.  However, it can be argued that his criticism was not of philosophy per se but of an approach to philosophy that elevated reason, or even empiricism, over revelation.  
+
Ghazali, throughout his life, also identified himself with the [[Asharite]] [[kalam]]. This identification is bolstered by the fact that his teacher, al-Juwayni, was also in his lifetime a leading master of Asharite kalam. And this association affected much of his theological output. This is evidenced in his [[11th century]] book ''"[[The Incoherence of the Philosophers]]"'' which marks a major turn in Islamic [[epistemology]], as Ghazali effectively discovered philosophical [[skepticism]] that would not be commonly seen in the [[Western world|west]] until [[George Berkeley]] and [[David Hume]] in the [[18th century]]. The encounter with skepticism led Ghazali to embrace a form of theological [[occasionalism]], or the belief that all causal events and interactions are not the product of material conjunctions but rather the immediate and present will of [[Allah]], the Islamic [[divine being]]. Some regard that logical consequence of this belief in practice, and an outcome that has developed in part from it over the subsequent centuries, has been a turn towards [[Islamic fundamentalism|fundamentalism in many Islamic societies]]. Ghazali probably did contribute to the decline of philosophy in Islamic thought.  However, it can be argued that his criticism was not of philosophy per se but of an approach to philosophy that elevated reason, or even empiricism, over revelation.
  
 
==Criticism of Philosophy==
 
==Criticism of Philosophy==
The ''Incoherence'' also marked a turning point in [[Islamic philosophy]] in its vehement rejections of [[Aristotle]] and [[Plato]]. The book took aim at the ''[[falasifa]]'', a loosely defined group of Islamic philosophers from the [[8th century|8th]] through the 11th centuries (most notable among them [[Ibn Sina]] ([[Avicenna]]) who drew intellectually upon the [[Ancient Greece|Ancient Greeks]]. Ghazali bitterly denounced Plato, [[Socrates]] and other [[List of Greek writers|Greek writers]] as ''mushrikuwn'' ('polytheist') and labelled those who employed their methods and ideas as corrupters of the Islamic faith.  His criticism was that they cited the Qur'an to support their ideas but derived these from philosophy, not from revelation.  The Qur'an was window dressing. Reason and philosoply, he said, could not prove the existence of God or the createdness or un-createdness of the world.  Rather, belief in these is an act of faith based on revelation.  For example, the Philosphers denied the creation in favor of emanation (in Ghazali's view the Qur'an teaches creation but some cite "The Day We roll up the heavens with the same parallel of a scroll rolling up books; as We produced the first creation We repeat it, a promise We have undertaken, verily We shall fulfill it" (21: 104) to support emanation) on the basis that this would constitute causation, a change in the nature of God, and, since all moments of time are exactly the same, even God cannot choose a particular moment in time for creation. AI-Ghazali's retort is that God had decided to create the world in the eternal past, therefore creation does not mean any change in God.  According to Ghazali, God is the creator of time itself. Too often, philosophers drew their notion from observation (''mushahadah''). For example, their view of causality posited that a necessary cause and effect exists between fire and buring, light and sunshine.  He argued that the relationship between these derives from the order in which God created them, not from any necessity and that either could exist without the other.  Observation could not actually prove that fire causes burning, only that burning occurs where there is also fire. Ghazali argued that as a lifeless 'object', fire is not capable to perform any action so could not be the agent (''al-fa`il'') that causes burning.
+
The ''Incoherence'' (''Tuhafut al-Tuhafut''), which Ghazali wrote while teaching in Baghdad, marked a turning point in [[Islamic philosophy]] in its vehement rejections of [[Aristotle]] and [[Plato]]. The book took aim at the ''[[falasifa]]'', a loosely defined group of Islamic philosophers from the [[8th century|8th]] through the 11th centuries.  It especially singled out [[Ibn Sina]] ([[Avicenna]]) who drew intellectually upon the [[Ancient Greece|Ancient Greeks]] and al-Farabi. He takes their views as 'the authentic expression of their mis-leaders' (4), namely Socrates, Hippocrates, Plato, and Aristotle, who had deceived Muslims by their claims that the 'principles they have discovered are unquestionable', thus reducing 'the positive contents of historical religion' to 'sanctimonious lies and trivilaity'(Gazali, 1963: 2). He bitterly denounced the Greeks philosopherps as ''mushrikuwn'' ('polytheist') and labelled those who employed their methods and ideas as corrupters of the Islamic faith.  His criticism was that they cited the Qur'an to support their ideas but derived these from philosophy, not from revelation: 'What ... we assert is that the philosophers are unable to know these things by rational demonstration. If these things were true, the prophets would know them through inspiration or revelation; but rational arguments cannot prove them' (Ghazali, 1963: 163)The error is in trying to 'discover Hidden Things by deductive methods' (2). The Qur'an was window dressing. Reason and philosoply, he said, could not prove the existence of God or the createdness or un-createdness of the world.  Rather, belief in these is an act of faith based on revelation.  For example, the Philosphers denied the creation in favor of emanation (in Ghazali's view the Qur'an teaches creation but some cite "The Day We roll up the heavens with the same parallel of a scroll rolling up books; as We produced the first creation We repeat it, a promise We have undertaken, verily We shall fulfill it" (21: 104) to support emanation) on the basis that this would constitute causation, a change in the nature of God, and, since all moments of time are exactly the same, even God cannot choose a particular moment in time for creation. AI-Ghazali's retort is that God had decided to create the world in the eternal past, therefore creation does not mean any change in God.  According to Ghazali, God is the creator of time itself (Ghazali, 1963: 23). Too often, philosophers drew their notion from observation (''mushahadah''). Muslims should 'accept the authority of the prohepts in regard to the fundamentals of these things and' should submit to that authority', without inquiring about 'the Why, and How Much, and What, for these things lie beyond the power of man' (Ghazali, 1963: 88). For example, their view of causality posited that a necessary cause and effect exists between fire and buring, light and sunshine.  He argued that the relationship between these derives from the order in which God created them, not from any necessity and that either could exist without the other.  Observation could not actually prove that fire causes burning, only that burning occurs where there is also fire. Ghazali argued that as a lifeless 'object', fire is not capable to perform any action so could not be the agent (''al-fa`il'') that causes burning (Ghazali, 1963: 186).
  
  
Line 35: Line 36:
 
*''Mizan al-?amal''
 
*''Mizan al-?amal''
 
'''[[Sufism]]'''
 
'''[[Sufism]]'''
*''Ihya ?ulum al-din'', "The revival of the religious sciences", Ghazali's most important work
+
*''Ihya Ulum al-din'', "The revival of the religious sciences", Ghazali's most important work; see Nabih Amin Faris's translation (Lahore, Ashraf, 1962)  at http://www.ghazali.org/ihya/
 
*''Kimiya?-yi sa?adat'', "The Alchemy of Happiness"
 
*''Kimiya?-yi sa?adat'', "The Alchemy of Happiness"
 
*''Mishkat al-anwar'', "The Niche of Lights"
 
*''Mishkat al-anwar'', "The Niche of Lights"
 
'''[[Islamic philosophy]]'''
 
'''[[Islamic philosophy]]'''
 
*''Maqasid al-falasifa''
 
*''Maqasid al-falasifa''
*''Tahafut al-falasifa'', "[[The Incoherence of the Philosophers]]", on which [[Ibn Rushd]] wrote his famous refutation ''Tahafut al-tahafut'' ([[The Incoherence of the Incoherence]])
+
*''Tahafut al-falasifa'', "[[The Incoherence of the Philosophers]]", on which [[Ibn Rushd]] wrote his famous refutation ''Tahafut al-tahafut'' ([[The Incoherence of the Incoherence]])http://www.ghazali.org/works/taf-eng.pdf'''[[Fiqh]]'''
'''[[Fiqh]]'''
 
 
*''al-Mustasfa min ?ilm al-usul''
 
*''al-Mustasfa min ?ilm al-usul''
 
'''[[Logic]]'''
 
'''[[Logic]]'''

Revision as of 06:58, 10 November 2005

File:Haruniyeh.JPG
Haruniyeh tomb, named after Harun al-Rashid. The present structure, located in Tus, was probably built in the 13th century. The great Sufi Sheikh Imam Mohammad Ghazali is also buried here.

Abu Hamid Muhammad ibn Muhammad al-Ghazali (Arabic: ابو حامد محمد بن محمد الغزالى for short: الغزالى ) (born 1058C.E. in Tus, Khorasan province of Persia, modern day Iran, died 1111C.E. in Tus) was a Muslim theologian and philosopher, known as Algazel to the western medieval world. Abu Hamid Al-Ghazali, or al-Ghazzali as he is written sometimes. Al-Ghazali is credited with reconciling legalistic and mystical Islam, and gained a reputation within Christian as well as Muslim circles for his piety and godliness. He influenced Thomas Aquinas who cited one of his works 31 times.

His life

Early Life

Al-Ghazali is one of the greatest jurists, theologians and mystical thinkers in the Islamic tradition. Ghazali and his brother, Ahmad, were entrusted by their father, when he died while they were still in their childhood, to a Sufi friend, mainly so that they would receive an edcucation. The Sufi taught them reading and writing then arranged for them to attend a school, which provided both board and a stipend. He later joined the famous Nizamiyyah school in Nishapur were he was taught by Abul Maali al-Juwayni (d. 1085C.E.), who not only held a chair in Shafi law, but was sponsored by the vizier Nizam al-Mulk (d. 1092) who was one of the most powerful men of his day. Ghazali was trained in the Asharite school. He studied in Nishapur for eight years, until Juwayni's death. Ghazali's initial love was for Islamic law. Early on in his career he excelled as a lecturer in Shafi jurisprudence. Having been noted for his outstanding abilities, Nizam al-Mulk, following the death of al-Juwayni, appointed him head of the Nizamiyyah College at Baghdad in 1091. As a lecturer until 1095 Ghazali managed to attract literally hundreds of scholars, demonstrating his extensive contemporary popularity. He was the scholar per excellence in the Islamic world. His audience also included scholars from other schools of jurisprudence. This position won him prestige, wealth and respect that even princes and viziers could not match. He thus was justifiably referred to as Hujjat-ul Islam ('The Testimony of Islam'). However, he grew skeptical about the possibiliy of any certainty in knowledge and this uncertainty eventually resulted in a crises that was to change his life.

Spiritual Crises

Only four years after being appointed to the head of the Nizamiyyah College, he started to doubt the usefulness of his teaching career and comfortable life and became profoundly conscious of a struggle within himself between his spiritual thirst on the one hand and his attachment to worldly pursuits on the other. He later wrote that .............Having provided for his family, he renounced his position, and worldly possessions and left Baghdad. His brother Ahmad took over his teaching responsibility and he made sure that financail provision was made for the support of his family. He told colleagues that he was going on the haj (pilgrimage) to Mecca. Most implored him not to leave. He left for Damascus, where he lived in seclusion in the city's principle minaret, and then on to Jerusalem and the Dome of the Rock, and Hebron. He went on pilgrimage to Mecca and Medina in 1096 and subsequently travelled widely to Baghdad and Egypt visiting Cairo and Alexandria. and many other places. ...............................He saw himself as searching for the truth. He had investigated many different schools of thought and found them wanting.

Now, love of retirement and of a life of ease seemed to be keeping him from teaching and when he consulted his friends urged him to return to Nish which had become lax, pointing out the promise of a renewer (mujaddid) towards the start of each new century (499) ............................... Finally he returned to his hometown of Tus, where he took charge of a khanka (Sufi hospice or even monastery, which included a study house). During this time Ghazali had written his most important work, Ihya ulum al-din (The Revivication of the Religious Sciences), which again immediately singled him out as the most important theologians of the day. The work is in many respects his own answer to the Incoherency, since he details in four volumes and ten books how the religious life shoould be lived, what knowledge is beneficial, what knowledge harmful (or blameworthy) and how beneficial knowledge should be acquired and spread. He regards both the pursuit and the sharing of knowledge as profoundly Islamic, and suggests that knowledge is 'seeing things as they really are, which is one of the attributes of Allah' (Faris edition, Book One, Section Three: 1). He ended his seclusion for a short lecturing period, at the behest of Fakhr al-Mulk, the vizier of the Seljuk ruler of Khorasan, at the Nizamiyyah of Tus in 1106. He wrote t his autobiography al-Munqidh min al-dalal there and remained until his death in December, 1111.

Ghazali, throughout his life, also identified himself with the Asharite kalam. This identification is bolstered by the fact that his teacher, al-Juwayni, was also in his lifetime a leading master of Asharite kalam. And this association affected much of his theological output. This is evidenced in his 11th century book "The Incoherence of the Philosophers" which marks a major turn in Islamic epistemology, as Ghazali effectively discovered philosophical skepticism that would not be commonly seen in the west until George Berkeley and David Hume in the 18th century. The encounter with skepticism led Ghazali to embrace a form of theological occasionalism, or the belief that all causal events and interactions are not the product of material conjunctions but rather the immediate and present will of Allah, the Islamic divine being. Some regard that logical consequence of this belief in practice, and an outcome that has developed in part from it over the subsequent centuries, has been a turn towards fundamentalism in many Islamic societies. Ghazali probably did contribute to the decline of philosophy in Islamic thought. However, it can be argued that his criticism was not of philosophy per se but of an approach to philosophy that elevated reason, or even empiricism, over revelation.

Criticism of Philosophy

The Incoherence (Tuhafut al-Tuhafut), which Ghazali wrote while teaching in Baghdad, marked a turning point in Islamic philosophy in its vehement rejections of Aristotle and Plato. The book took aim at the falasifa, a loosely defined group of Islamic philosophers from the 8th through the 11th centuries. It especially singled out Ibn Sina (Avicenna) who drew intellectually upon the Ancient Greeks and al-Farabi. He takes their views as 'the authentic expression of their mis-leaders' (4), namely Socrates, Hippocrates, Plato, and Aristotle, who had deceived Muslims by their claims that the 'principles they have discovered are unquestionable', thus reducing 'the positive contents of historical religion' to 'sanctimonious lies and trivilaity'(Gazali, 1963: 2). He bitterly denounced the Greeks philosopherps as mushrikuwn ('polytheist') and labelled those who employed their methods and ideas as corrupters of the Islamic faith. His criticism was that they cited the Qur'an to support their ideas but derived these from philosophy, not from revelation: 'What ... we assert is that the philosophers are unable to know these things by rational demonstration. If these things were true, the prophets would know them through inspiration or revelation; but rational arguments cannot prove them' (Ghazali, 1963: 163). The error is in trying to 'discover Hidden Things by deductive methods' (2). The Qur'an was window dressing. Reason and philosoply, he said, could not prove the existence of God or the createdness or un-createdness of the world. Rather, belief in these is an act of faith based on revelation. For example, the Philosphers denied the creation in favor of emanation (in Ghazali's view the Qur'an teaches creation but some cite "The Day We roll up the heavens with the same parallel of a scroll rolling up books; as We produced the first creation We repeat it, a promise We have undertaken, verily We shall fulfill it" (21: 104) to support emanation) on the basis that this would constitute causation, a change in the nature of God, and, since all moments of time are exactly the same, even God cannot choose a particular moment in time for creation. AI-Ghazali's retort is that God had decided to create the world in the eternal past, therefore creation does not mean any change in God. According to Ghazali, God is the creator of time itself (Ghazali, 1963: 23). Too often, philosophers drew their notion from observation (mushahadah). Muslims should 'accept the authority of the prohepts in regard to the fundamentals of these things and' should submit to that authority', without inquiring about 'the Why, and How Much, and What, for these things lie beyond the power of man' (Ghazali, 1963: 88). For example, their view of causality posited that a necessary cause and effect exists between fire and buring, light and sunshine. He argued that the relationship between these derives from the order in which God created them, not from any necessity and that either could exist without the other. Observation could not actually prove that fire causes burning, only that burning occurs where there is also fire. Ghazali argued that as a lifeless 'object', fire is not capable to perform any action so could not be the agent (al-fa`il) that causes burning (Ghazali, 1963: 186).


Though Ghazali was an Asharite and avowedly anti-philosophical it is notable—as pointed out by Ibn Rushd (Averroes), in his bitterly entitled Incoherence of the Incoherence)—that he refutes the falasifa on their own terms, by employing philosophical models of his own.

Some of his other works, most notably The Niche of Lights, does in fact display a definite affinity for the rational faculty, which would suggest that Ghazali saw a benefit in using reason to support living faith.

It is, however, clear that Ghazali self-identified as an Asharite throughout his life, and also that by the time Ghazali's writing that Asharite theology was appreciably more rationalistic than it had been at its inception, 120 years before Ghazali's birth. Therefore although it has often been assumed that with Ibn Rushd's funeral the truly philosophical elements of Islamic culture died, it is clear that on closer inspection it is perhaps more sensible to look for these philosophical traits within the tradition of Asharite theology.

This debate does, however, seem to fade into insignificance, on the realisation of Ghazali’s eventual association to the Sufi way of thinking. His adoption of Sufism in the later stages of life seems to indicate, as Ghazali himself professes, that this mystical path was in fact the only verifiable way of coming to terms with the divine presence. His conclusion, as it appears in his autobiography (al-Mustafa min ‘ilm al-usul), seems to suggest that Ghazali found fault with both a purely faith based approach and a purely rationalistic approach. The problem was that each of these established what to believe, but did not in themselves entail a living realization of faith. Ghazali therefore turned to a mystical approach to engage with the divine, which he thought transcended both of these and enabled the individual Sufi traveller to ‘taste’ the divine union – and therefore to experience annihilation of self-hood in the presence of God. Ghazali was thus instrumental in cementing the position of Sufism in mainstream Islamic tradition.

Works

Islamic theology

  • al-Munqidh min al-dalal, "Deliverance from Error"
  • al-1qtisad fi'I-i`tiqad
  • al-Risala al-Qudsiyya
  • Kitab al-arba?in fi usul al-din
  • Mizan al-?amal

Sufism

  • Ihya Ulum al-din, "The revival of the religious sciences", Ghazali's most important work; see Nabih Amin Faris's translation (Lahore, Ashraf, 1962) at http://www.ghazali.org/ihya/
  • Kimiya?-yi sa?adat, "The Alchemy of Happiness"
  • Mishkat al-anwar, "The Niche of Lights"

Islamic philosophy

  • Maqasid al-falasifa
  • Tahafut al-falasifa, "The Incoherence of the Philosophers", on which Ibn Rushd wrote his famous refutation Tahafut al-tahafut (The Incoherence of the Incoherence)http://www.ghazali.org/works/taf-eng.pdfFiqh
  • al-Mustasfa min ?ilm al-usul

Logic

  • Mi?yar al-?ilm (The Standard Measure of Knowledge)
  • al-Qistas al-mustaqim (The Just Balance)
  • Mihakk al-nazar f'l-mantiq (The Touchstone of Proof in Logic)

Literature

  • Laoust, H: La politique de Gazali, 1970
  • Campanini, M.: Al-Ghazzali, in S.H. Nasr and O. Leaman, History of Islamic Philosophy 1996
  • Watt, W M.: Muslim Intellectual: A Study of al-Ghazali, Edinburgh 1963
  • Marmura: Al-Ghazali The Incoherence of the Philosophers, (2nd ed.). Brigham: Printing Press. ISBN 0-8425-2466-5.
  • Frank, Richard: Al-Ghazali and the Asharite School, London, 1994

Quotations

From 'The Way of The Sufi' by Idris Shah:

  • Possessions - You possess only whatever will not be lost in a shipwreck.
  • Gain and Loss - I should like to know what a man who has no knowledge has really gained, and what a man of knowledge has not gained.

External links

See also

  • List of Iranian Scientists

ar:الغزالي de:Al-Ghazali fr:Al-Ghazali gl:Al-Ghazali id:Al-Ghazali ja:ガザーリー [[tr:{İmam-ı Gazali]]

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.