Difference between revisions of "Metaphysics" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
(Metaphysics)
 
(24 intermediate revisions by 8 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
I am working on this article.[[User:Keisuke Noda|Keisuke Noda]] 14:57, 20 Sep 2005 (CDT)
+
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{copyedited}}
 +
[[Image:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|250px|[[Plato]] and [[Aristotle]] (right), by [[Raphael]] (Stanza della Segnatura, [[Rome]]). Aristotle is regarded as the "father" of metaphysics.]]
 +
'''Metaphysics''' ([[Greek language|Greek]]: ''μετά (meta)''="after," ''φυσικά (phisiká)''="those on nature," derived from the arrangement of [[Aristotle]]'s works) is the branch of [[philosophy]] concerned with explaining the nature of the most fundamental aspects of the world. It addresses questions such as: What is the nature of reality? Does the world exist outside the mind? What is the nature of objects, events, places? Is [[free will]] possible in a world governed by [[causality|causal laws]]?
  
http://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Metaphysics&oldid=23603945
+
A central part of metaphysics is [[ontology]], which is the study of [[being]]. Ontology is, one might say, an attempt to determine what the most basic building blocks are, out of which the rest of reality is constructed. Philosophers of different times have shown different levels of optimism with respect to how much ontology can accomplish. It appears that [[Plato]], for instance, thought that ontology is capable of showing the existence of entities that are outside of the sensible world, but play some key role in determining the nature of that world. Many philosophers in the twentieth century, however, saw ontology as, at best, an attempt to understand the relations within a certain set of concepts used, such as that of [[substance]], property, and relation.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
It is important to distinguish the sense of "metaphysics" employed by philosophers from its recent association with [[spirituality]] and world-transcending thought, though the latter does stem from developments in the former. Because metaphysics concerns itself with fundamental questions, nearly every major philosopher has devoted a certain amount of thought to metaphysics. This means, however, that a history of metaphysics would be little less than a history of all of philosophy. This article will, therefore, survey the issues that have most concerned metaphysicians throughout history. A list of historical figures especially worth considering is provided at the end.
  
16:13 20 September 2005
+
==Five central questions of metaphysics==
 +
===Mind and matter===
 +
One of the central issues in metaphysics concerns how to understand the relation between minds and the world in which they exist. More specifically: Whether the most basic constituents of mind and the world were one and the same. [[Democritus]] and [[Epicurus]], for instance, claimed that the world was fundamentally made up of indivisible particles, but held that the mind was simply a special sort of particle. [[Descartes]] held that the material world was composed of material substance, and so fundamentally unlike the intellectual substance that was minds. [[Spinoza]] and [[Leibniz]] claimed that all of the finite world had both a physical and an intellectual aspect—so that even the most simple physical particle in some sense had a mind. An even more radical position is that of [[Berkeley]], who claimed that the material world is nothing more than ideas.
  
'''Metaphysics''' ([[Greek language|Greek]] words ''meta'' = after/beyond and ''physics'' = nature) is a branch of [[philosophy]] concerned with the study of "first principles" and "being" ([[ontology]]).
+
The root issue is that, in the task of trying to understand what the world is made up of, the metaphysician is faced with the fact that minds and matter appear to have very different natures. One is conscious, the other isn't. One appears to be divisible and complex, whereas the other seems simple. Yet the two also appear to interact, and it is plausible (as Spinoza explicitly states in Book 1 of his ''Ethics'') that only things with something in common can interact. Further, one intuitively believes oneself to possess at least ''some'' knowledge about the nature of the world (especially as the result of science), and this seems to require that the divide between mind and world not go too deep.
  
Problems that were not originally considered metaphysical have been added to metaphysics.  Other problems that were considered metaphysical problems for centuries are now typically relegated to their own separate subheadings in philosophy, such as [[philosophy of religion]], [[philosophy of mind]], [[philosophy of perception]], [[philosophy of language]], and [[philosophy of science]]. In rare cases subjects of metaphysical research have been found to be entirely physical and natural.
+
===Objects and their properties===
 +
In looking at objects in the world, one often will look for things they "have something in common." For instance, one might say that two apples have the same color, that two people are the same height, or that two books have the same number of chapters. But what is the nature of these entities that are "had in common?" They do not appear to be particular objects—these claims are not like the statement that two people might have a friend in common. The things appear to be "universal," not particular, in that they can be fully present in many things.
  
What might be called the ''core'' metaphysical problems would be the ones which have ''always'' been considered metaphysical.  What most of such problems have in common is that they are the problems of ''ontology,'' "the science of being ''[[wikt:qua|qua]]'' being".
+
There are two related questions one might raise about universals like redness, roundness, etc. The first concerns their ontological status: In what way do these things exist?  For instance, would redness still exist even if there weren't any particular objects that were red? After all, people don't think that destroying one red thing has any effect on redness itself, so why would the destruction of all of them do so? But if redness could exist without any particular red objects, then it must in some way be independent of them. This points to the second question: What is the relation between universals and particulars? Are particular objects something more than just a sum of universals, and if so, what? This latter question has a close relation to the issue of change.
  
Other philosophical traditions have very different conceptions such as "what came first, the chicken or the egg?" Problems from those in the Western philosophical tradition; for example, [[Taoism]] and indeed, much of [[Eastern philosophy]] completely reject many of the most basic tenets of Aristotelian metaphysics, principles which have by now become almost completely internalized and beyond question in Western philosophy, though a number of dissidents from Aristotelian metaphysics have emerged in the west, such as [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]]'s ''Science of Logic''.
+
The most extended discussions of this problem in ancient philosophy are found in the dialogues of [[Plato]] (in particular, the ''Parmenides''). In much of his work, Plato argues that universals are ''more real'' than particulars, and as such philosophers who defend the claim that universals have some sort of independent existence are often called "Platonists."  The opposing view, called "[[nominalism]]," holds that universals exist only in name—in other words, that humans merely have words that are applicable to many objects, but that there is no sense in which the words refer to some entities that are separate from particular objects.
  
In modern times, the meaning of the word ''metaphysics'' has become confused by popular significations that are really unrelated to metaphysics or ontology ''per se'', viz. [[esotericism]] and [[occult|occultism]]. Esotericism and occultism, in their many forms, are not so much concerned with inquiries into first principles or the nature of being, though they do tend to proceed on the metaphysical assumption that all being is "one".
+
=== Identity and change ===
 +
Puzzles associated with change go back at least to [[Heraclitus]]' famous claim that "you cannot step into the same river twice." As it is most often interpreted, Heraclitus is making the following point: Given that there is a single river from moment to moment, since there is a change in what is present (for instance, a difference in water levels), it cannot be strictly true that the ''same'' river is there. That is, consider the following two claims:
  
== The origin of the word 'metaphysics' ==
+
#The river has the property of being 4 meters deep on Tuesday
 +
#The river has the property of being 3.5 meters deep on Wednesday
  
The ancient Greek philosopher [[Aristotle]] produced a number of works which together were called the ''Physics''. In an early edition, the works of Aristotle were organized in such a way that another set of works was placed right after the ''Physics.''  These books seemed to concern a basic, fundamental area of philosophical inquiry, which at the time did not have a name; Aristotle himself just called it "first philosophy".  So early Aristotelian scholars called those books τὰ μετὰ τὰ φυσικά, "ta meta ta physika", which means "the (books that come) after the (books about) physics."  That is the origin of the word 'metaphysics' (in [[Greek language|Greek]], μεταφυσικά).
+
But since no river can be ''both'' 4 meters deep and 3.5 meters deep, it would seem that the river found on Tuesday cannot be the river found on Wednesday.
  
Hence, [[etymology|etymologically]] speaking, metaphysics is the subject of those books by Aristotle which were called, collectively, the ''Metaphysics''. Technically, it was so named because it came after the book of Physics. But the actual subject matter in the book, perhaps coincidentally, are on the topic of things that underlie the physical—"beyond" the physical, so to speak—therefore fitting the word in two ways.
+
One option is to accept the claim that the same river cannot be present at two times if there is any change. Yet this would lead one to claim that very few of the things one thought lasted through time do, since almost everything in the universe undergoes at least ''some'' change from moment to moment. Many philosophers have therefore tried to find ways to vindicate talk of persisting objects that don't involve the unacceptable claim that the same object can have incompatible properties.
  
The ''Metaphysics'' was divided into three parts, now regarded as the traditional branches of Western metaphysics, called (1) [[ontology]], (2) [[theology]], and (3) [[universal science]]. There were also some smaller, perhaps tangential matters: a philosophical lexicon, an attempt to define philosophy in general, and several extracts from the ''Physics'' repeated verbatim.
+
One option is to deny that it is correct to say that (for instance) the river has both the property of being 4 meters deep and the property of being 3.5 meters deep, since those properties are incompatible. Rather, one might insist, the river has two properties that can be described by the phrases "being 4 meters deep on Tuesday" and "being 3.5 meters deep on Wednesday." The properties described by those phrases are obviously compatible. One might describe this solution as one of time-relativizing the properties themselves.
  
* ''Ontology'' is the study of [[existence]]; it has been traditionally defined as 'the science of [[being]] ''qua'' being'.  
+
Another option is to see the object as broken down into "time-slices." The river is then seen as some sort of composite of slices that might be referred to by phrases such as "the river on Tuesday" and "the river on Wednesday." In this view, it's not strictly true that the properties of being being 4 meters deep and of being 3.5 meters deep are ascribed to the ''same'' object. Rather, they are ascribed to different objects (the time-slices), which are components of some larger object. This solution can be described as time-relativizing the objects.
* ''Theology'' means, here, the study of [[God]] or the [[deity|gods]] and of questions about the divine.
 
* ''Universal science'' is supposed to be the study of so-called [[Aristotelian first principles|first principle]]s, which underlie all other inquiries; an example of such a principle is the [[law of non-contradiction]]: ''A thing cannot both be and not be at the same time, and in the same respect.'' A particular apple cannot both exist and not exist at the same time.  It can't be all red and all green at the same time. Universal science or first philosophy treats of "being ''qua'' being" — that is, what is basic to all science before one adds the particular details of any one science. This includes matters like causality, substance, species, and elements.
 
  
== Examples ==
+
A third option is to relativize the ''relation'' between the object and the property. In this view, the above statements should be recast as: "The river is—onTuesday—4 meters deep" and "The river is—on Wednesday—3.5 meters deep." 
  
It is sometimes difficult to understand what the issues even ''are'' in metaphysics.  It might help to begin with a fairly simple example that will help to introduce the problems of metaphysics.
+
Though these distinctions seem overly subtle, the ramifications of the choice are very significant, for this is a choice about how to understand one of the most fundamental features of the universe: Change.
  
Imagine now that we are in a room, and in the middle of the room there is a table, and in the middle of the table there is a big, fresh, juicy, red [[apple]]. We can ask many ''metaphysical'' questions about this apple. This will, hopefully, help us understand better what metaphysics is.
+
===The structure of space and time===
 +
Space and time are some of the most basic features of the world. Things have spatiotemporal locations, and spatiotemporal relations to each other. One of the longest-standing metaphysical questions about space and time concerns how to understand the relationship between locations and relations.
  
The apple is an excellent example of a [[physical object]]: one can pick it up, throw it around, eat it, and so on.  It occupies [[spacetime|space and time]] and has a variety of [[Property (philosophy)|properties]].  Suppose we ask: ''what'' ''are'' physical objects?  This might seem like the sort of question to which one ''cannot'' give an answer ("What is, what is?"). What could one possibly use to explain what physical objects are?  But philosophers actually do try to give some general sorts of accounts of what they are.  They ask: Are physical objects just bundles of their properties?  Or are they substances which ''have'' those properties?  That is called the ''problem of substance'' or ''[[objecthood]]''.
+
A number of philosophers, including the great physicist Isaac [[Newton]], have considered the notion of location to be more fundamental than that of the relations. They saw space, in particular, as a sort of ''substance,'' which is in principle capable of existing on its own. What explains two objects being, say, 20 miles apart on this view is some more basic facts along the lines of:
  
Here is another sort of question.  We said that the apple has ''properties'', like being red, being big, being juicy. How are properties different from objects?  Notice, we say that things like apples have properties like redness.  But apples and redness are different sorts of items, of things, of entities.  One can pick up and touch an apple, but cannot pick up and touch redness, except perhaps in the sense that you can pick up and touch red ''things.''  So how can we best think about what properties ''are''?  This is one of the central questions in what is known as the ''[[problem of universals]]''.
+
#Object A is at location 0,0,0.
 +
#Object B is at location 20,0,0.
  
Here is another question about what physical objects are: when ''in'' ''general'' can we say that physical objects ''come'' ''into'' ''being'' and when they ''cease'' ''to'' ''exist''?  Surely the apple can ''change'' in many ways without ceasing to exist. It could get brown and rotten but it would still be that apple. But if someone ate it, it would not just have changed; it would no longer exist.  So there are some metaphysical questions to be answered about the notions of [[identity]], or being the same thing over time, and [[change]]. (See Also: [[identity and change]])
+
The opposing line of thought, advanced by philosophers such as [[Leibniz]], held that relations are more basic than locations. But relations, obviously, only exist insofar as there are objects that are related. This in turn means that objects are more fundamental than their relations, and so more basic than space and time. Talk of particular locations, for someone like Leibniz, is merely a short-hand for describing relations between objects.  
  
This apple exists in [[space]] (it sits on a table in a room) and in [[time]] (it was not on the table a week ago and it will not be on the table a week from now). But what does this talk of space and time mean?  Can we say, for example, that space is like an invisible three-dimensional grid in which the apple is located? Suppose the apple, and every other physical object in the universe, were to be entirely removed from existence: then would space, that "invisible grid," still exist? Some people say not—they say that without physical objects, space would not exist, because space is the framework in which we understand how physical objects are related to each other. There are many other metaphysical questions to ask about space and time.
+
One of the key arguments Leibniz gave for his view was the following: Assume that the Newtonian view is correct. In that case, it is possible that every object in the universe be moved two feet to the left, changing absolute location, but with no change of relations. In Leibniz's own case, he appealed to God's rationality at this point, asking what ''reason'' God could have for choosing one location rather than another for the universe, and concluding that the question must have been confused to begin with. More recent philosophers have run the argument without the appeal to God, merely using it to point out the superfluousness of absolute location.
  
There are some other very different sorts of problems in metaphysics.  The apple is one sort of thing; now if Sally is in the room, and we say Sally has a [[mind]], we are surely going to say that Sally's mind is a different sort of thing from the apple (if it is a sort of ''thing'' at all). I might say that my mind is immaterial, but the apple is a material object, (although there is much disagreement amongst philosophers about the metaphysical status of minds). Moreover, it sounds a little strange to say that Sally's mind is located in any ''particular'' ''place''; maybe we could say it is somewhere in the room; but the apple is obviously located in a particular place, namely on the middle of the table. It ''seems'' clear that [[mind]]s are fundamentally different from physical [[body|bodies]].  But if so, how can something mental, like a decision to eat, cause a physical event to occur, like biting down on the apple? How are the mind and body [[Causality|causally]] interconnected if they are two totally different sorts of things? This is called the ''[[mind-body problem]]'', which is now typically relegated to a philosophical subdiscipline called ''[[philosophy of mind]].''  The mind-body problem is sometimes still considered part of metaphysics, however.  Perhaps the most profound problem belonging to this branch is the question of consciousness.  No discipline has been able to explain what consciousness is or how it works.
+
In response, Newtonians have worried whether it is intelligible to see space (and time, for which exactly similar arguments apply) as being dependent on objects in the way Leibniz's view requires.
  
== Criticism ==
+
===[[Determinism]] and [[free will]]===
 +
One of the most recurrent philosophical problems comes from the apparent incompatibility of two independently plausible claims:
  
Metaphysics has been attacked, at different times in history, as being futile and overly vague. [[Lord Byron]] often mocked the subject in his works.  [[David Hume]] and [[Immanuel Kant]] both prescribed a limited role to the subject and argued against knowledge progressing beyond the world of our representations (except, in the case of Kant, to knowledge that the ''[[Noumenon|noumena]]'' exist). [[Ayer|A.J. Ayer]] is famous for leading a "revolt against metaphysics", where he claimed that its propositions were meaningless.  [[Martin Heidegger]] often criticised metaphysics, yet he dealt with questions that many would consider to be metaphysical.  British universities became less concerned with the area for much of the 20th century, but it has revived itself in recent times, amongst philosophy departments.
+
#Everything in the universe is causally determined, and what is causally determined could not have been otherwise.
 +
#In acting in the universe, one sometimes could have done otherwise than he actually did.
  
A more nuanced view is that metaphysical statements are not ''meaningless'' statements, but rather that they are generally not ''fallible'', ''testable'' or ''provable'' statements. That is to say, there is no valid set of empirical observations nor a valid set of logical arguments which could ''definitively'' prove metaphysical statements to be true or false. Hence, a metaphysical statement usually implies a ''belief'' about the world or about the universe which may seem reasonable but is ultimately not provable. That belief could be changed in a ''non-arbitrary'' way, based on experience or argument, yet there exists no evidence or argument so compelling that it could rationally ''force'' a change in that belief, in the sense of definitely proving it false. Yet this does not mean that science can be altogether freed from metaphysical assumptions or beliefs, since scientific thought often also goes well beyond whatever the available data warrant, or operates with assumptions which no one knows yet how to test or prove. One reason for that is that, typically, there are always more theories, than valid data that could corroborate or falsify those theories (Cf. also Stefan Amsterdamski's reflections on this topic). But whereas the metaphysician is likely to say, "this is how it is", the scientist says "We could be wrong".
+
The first question addressed by philosophers on this point is whether the claims are in fact incompatible.
  
== Metaphysical subdisciplines ==
+
"Compatibilists" claim that the apparent inconsistency of free will and determinism can be avoided if one properly specifies what each claim means. For instance, a compatibilist might claim that the "could have done otherwise" in (2) isn't about what really could have been otherwise, but perhaps merely what would have been otherwise ''if'' (as was in fact impossible) one had had a different set of desires of beliefs.
  
* [[Ontology]]
+
"Incompatibilists" are those who find no compatibilist solution acceptable, insisting that no compatibilist way of understanding the claims actually captures what was originally meant. Given this, incompatibilists think people have a choice between rejecting one claim or the other. "Libertarians" reject (1), insisting that their confidence in the freedom of their wills is sufficient to convince them that the universe cannot be causally determined. "Hard determinists" reject (2), concluding that the freedom of human will is a mere illusion (both [[Spinoza]] and [[Hume]] offer interests diagnoses of tendencies to believe that human wills are free).
* [[Philosophy of religion]]
 
* [[Philosophy of mind]]
 
* [[Philosophy of perception]]
 
  
== Metaphysical topics and problems ==
+
A small number of recent philosophers have thought that developments in modern physics offered some help on this issue, particularly developments that suggest that there is no genuine determinacy. Unfortunately, the lack of determinism in such theories doesn't appear to be in the right "place." For instance, the fact that the location of particles is not determined by antecedent conditions doesn't seem to make room for human wills to be free, for the general laws of psychology still hold well enough.
  
* [[Identity and change]]
+
==Criticisms of metaphysics==
 +
Though some metaphysical projects have no ambitions beyond conceptual analysis, others have, to varying degrees, attempted to make substantive claims about the nature of reality ([[Plato]] again being a prime example). But the very suggestion that philosophers are in a position to discover substantive conclusions about the fundamental aspects of reality has struck many thinkers of an [[empiricism|empiricist]] bent as patently absurd. This most frequently takes form as a challenge to whether such metaphysical claims can be ''justified,'' but an important movement known as logical positivism denied that metaphysics claims could even be ''meaningful.''
  
== Metaphysical jargon ==
+
===Criticisms about justification===
 +
The line of thought that has lead some philosophers to claim that metaphysical statements cannot be justified runs roughly as follows: (1) Metaphysical statements are about the world, and (2) all that is known about the world is learned through the senses. Yet, as metaphysicians themselves admit, (3) metaphysical claims cannot be justified merely through the senses. Therefore, metaphysical claims cannot be justified. Such a sentiment is especially obvious in some of the writings of the Scottish philosopher [[David Hume]]:
  
* [[Abstract]]
+
<blockquote>If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion ''(An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding)''.</blockquote>
* [[Being]]
 
* [[Category of being]]
 
* [[Concrete]]
 
  
== People ==
+
The obvious premise for the metaphysician to reject in the above argument is (2), the claim that all that is known about the world is based in the senses. Plato, for instance, held that prior to birth, one encountered more fundamental aspects of reality, and merely needed sensory promptings to recall those aspects. [[Descartes]] held that God had imprinted certain basic ideas in human minds in creating them, and that we could draw substantive conclusions from those ideas.
  
*''[[:Category:Metaphysics writers|Metaphysics writers]]''
+
[[Kant]], while being sympathetic to the basic anti-metaphysical argument, only accepted a qualified form of premise (1), the claim that metaphysical statements are about the world. He held that some metaphysical claims (such as "every change has a cause") are not about a world that is completely independent of humans, but rather about how objects appear to people. Moreover, the way that objects appear to people is partially determined by features of their own minds, and it is by knowing about those features that people can be justified in substantive claims about how objects will appear.
  
 +
===Criticisms about meaningfulness===
 +
[[Logical positivism]], a movement started in Vienna that held a strong following in Britain, advanced a strong form of "verificationism," the view that the only meaningful statements were those that could, in principle, be verified by some set of observations. The positivists intended to use this view, which has at least some intuitive appeal, to do away with a large portion of religious doctrine and metaphysical disputes.
 +
 +
Three important features of most substantive metaphysical statements, such as "every event has a cause," are their ''universality,'' ''necessity,'' and ''non-analyticity''. In other words, they say that, with respect to entire group of things (for example, events), that each member of that group ''cannot exist'' without having some feature (that is, "having a cause"), even though that feature wouldn't be mentioned in a fully adequate definition of the group. The most experiential observations can show people, however, that some ''particular'' thing ''actually'' has some feature. No set of observations can establish any non-definitional property of everything in a group, so all metaphysical claims would fail the verificationist test.
 +
 +
While it enjoyed considerable popularity for a time, the positivist project was eventually abandoned, for it became apparent that core statements of scientific theories (for example, the statement of universal gravitation) share some of the features of metaphysical statements, and so cannot be directly verified by observations. In the wake of positivism, their lessons were taken instead to show that metaphysical statements are not ''meaningless'' statements, but rather that they are generally not ''fallible,'' ''testable,'' or ''provable'' statements.
 +
 +
==Major metaphysicians ==
 +
{|width=100%
 +
|-valign=top
 +
|width=25%|
 +
* [[Peter Abelard]]
 
* [[Aristotle]]
 
* [[Aristotle]]
* Saint [[Thomas Aquinas]], eminent [[Catholic]] metaphysician
+
* [[Thomas Aquinas]]
* [[Louis-Victor de Broglie]]
+
* [[Augustine of Hippo|St. Augustine]]
* [[William Kingdon Clifford]]
+
* [[Avicenna]] (Ibn Sina)
* [[Donald Davidson (philosopher)|Donald Davidson]]
+
* [[George Berkeley]]
* [[Gilles Deleuze]], who attempted to create a [[poststructuralism|poststructuralist]] metaphysics.
+
* [[Boethius]]
* [[René Descartes]], famous for the assertion ''cogito, ergo sum'' ("I think, therefore I am.")
+
|width=25%|
* [[Albert Einstein]], developed the [[Theory of Relativity]], which asserted [[mathematics|mathematically]] that there is no absolute [[frame of reference]]
+
* [[René Descartes]]
* [[Charles Fillmore]]
+
* [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]]
* [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]], formulated a complex non-Aristotelian metaphysics based on [[dialectics]]
 
 
* [[Martin Heidegger]]
 
* [[Martin Heidegger]]
* [[Werner Heisenberg]]
 
 
* [[Immanuel Kant]]
 
* [[Immanuel Kant]]
* [[Saul Kripke]]
 
 
* [[Gottfried Leibniz]]
 
* [[Gottfried Leibniz]]
* [[David Lewis (philosopher)|David Lewis]]
+
* [[John Locke]]
* [[George Edward Moore]]
 
* [[Charles Peirce]]
 
* [[Robert M. Pirsig]], Author of the popular ''[[Zen and the Art of Motorcycle Maintenance]]'', which established the theory of reality known as the [[Metaphysics of Quality]]
 
 
* [[Plato]]
 
* [[Plato]]
* [[Max Planck]]
+
|width=25%|
* [[Karl Popper]]
+
* [[Plotinus]]
* [[W. V. Quine]]
+
* [[Willard Van Orman Quine]]
* [[Ayn Rand]]
 
* [[Carl Reichenbach]]
 
* [[Richard Rorty]]
 
 
* [[Bertrand Russell]]
 
* [[Bertrand Russell]]
* [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], author of seminal [[existentialist]] text ''[[Being and Nothingness]]''
+
* [[Jean-Paul Sartre]]
* [[Erwin Schrödinger]], [[quantum mechanics|quantum mechanic]], suggested the famous [[Schrödinger's cat]] [[thought experiment]]
+
* [[Arthur Schopenhauer]]
* [[Lao Tzu]], author of the [[Tao Te Ching]]
+
* [[John Duns Scotus]]
 
+
* [[Baruch Spinoza]]
== See also ==
+
|}
 
 
* [[Aesthetics]]
 
* [[Buddhist philosophy]]
 
* [[Dualism]]
 
* [[Eastern philosophy]]
 
* [[Epistemology]]
 
* [[Ethics]]
 
* [[Fractal metaphysics]]
 
* [[List of spirituality-related topics]]
 
* [[Logical positivism]]
 
* [[Metaphysics of Quality]]
 
* [[Monism]]
 
* [[Mysticism]]
 
* [[Ontology]]
 
* [[Philosophy]]
 
* [[Pluralism (philosophy of mind)|Pluralism]]
 
* [[Reason]]
 
* [[Taoism]]
 
* [[Theology]]
 
* [[Transcendental]]
 
 
 
== References ==
 
 
 
* Lowe, E. J. (2002). ''A survey of metaphysics''. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 
* Loux, M. J. (2002). ''Metaphysics: A contemporary introduction'' (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.
 
*Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa Ed. (1999). Metaphysics:An Anthology. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies.
 
*Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, Ed. (2000). A Companion to Metaphysics. Malden Massachusetts, Blackwell, Publishers.
 
* Fillmore, Charles (1931, 17th printing July 2000). ''Metaphysical Bible Dictionary''.  Unity Village, Missouri: Unity House.  ISBN 0-871-59067-0
 
 
 
== External Links ==
 
 
 
* [http://www.galilean-library.org/int3.html Metaphysics 1] and [http://www.galilean-library.org/int19.html Metaphysics 2], Introductions to Metaphysics by Paul Newall, aimed at beginners.
 
* [http://www.formalontology.it Ontology. A resource guide for philosophers]
 
* [http://etext.library.adelaide.edu.au/a/a8m/ trans. by W. D. Ross]
 
* [http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?lookup=Aristot.+Met.+980a trans. by Hugh Tredennick (HTML at Perseus)]
 
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ Aristotle's Metaphysics at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 
*[http://waysofseeing.net Ways of Seeing], A Common Sense Exploration of Modern Metaphysics, including Science, Freedom, Interpretation, Yoga, and a single-sentence characterization of "Reality".
 
*Stefan Amsterdamski, Between Experience and Metaphysics. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science 35. Dordrecht—Boston, Reidel, 1975.
 
 
 
[[Category:Metaphysics| ]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Aristotle]]
 
 
 
[[bg:Метафизика]]
 
[[bn:অধিবিদ্যা]]
 
[[cs:Metafyzika]]
 
[[da:Metafysik]]
 
[[de:Metaphysik]]
 
[[et:Metafüüsika]]
 
[[es:Metafísica]]
 
[[eo:Metafiziko]]
 
[[fr:Métaphysique]]
 
[[gl:Metafísica]]
 
[[ko:형이상학]]
 
[[it:Metafisica (Aristotele)]]
 
[[he:מטאפיזיקה]]
 
[[la:Metaphysica]]
 
[[lt:Metafizika]]
 
[[nl:Metafysica]]
 
[[ja:形而上学]]
 
[[no:Metafysikk]]
 
[[pt:Metafísica]]
 
[[ro:Metafizică]]
 
[[ru:Метафизика]]
 
[[sk:Metafyzika]]
 
[[fi:Metafysiikka]]
 
[[sv:Metafysik]]
 
[[tl:Metapisika]]
 
[[tr:Metafizik]]
 
[[zh:形而上学]]
 
  
 +
==References==
 +
* Gale, Richard M. 2002. ''The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics''. Oxford: Blackwell. ISBN 0631221204
 +
* Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, eds. 1999. ''Metaphysics: An Anthology''. Blackwell Publishers. ISBN 0631202781
 +
* Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, eds. 1999. ''A Companion to Metaphysics''. Cambridge: Blackwell Reference. ISBN 0631227687
 +
* Loux, M.J. 1998. ''Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction''. London: Routledge. ISBN 0203283538
 +
* Lowe, E.J. 2002. ''A Survey of Metaphysics''. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0198752539
  
 +
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved November 9, 2022.
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics/ Aristotle's Metaphysics] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/metaphysics/ Metaphysics] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/change/ Change and Inconsistency] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties/ Properties] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/freewill/ Free Will] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 
 +
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/spacetime-theories/ Absolute and Relational Theories of Space and Motion] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 
  
 +
===General philosophy sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
 +
 +
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 +
[[Category:philosophy]]
  
[[category:philosophy and religion]]
+
{{credit|109023037}}

Latest revision as of 16:22, 9 November 2022

Plato and Aristotle (right), by Raphael (Stanza della Segnatura, Rome). Aristotle is regarded as the "father" of metaphysics.

Metaphysics (Greek: μετά (meta)="after," φυσικά (phisiká)="those on nature," derived from the arrangement of Aristotle's works) is the branch of philosophy concerned with explaining the nature of the most fundamental aspects of the world. It addresses questions such as: What is the nature of reality? Does the world exist outside the mind? What is the nature of objects, events, places? Is free will possible in a world governed by causal laws?

A central part of metaphysics is ontology, which is the study of being. Ontology is, one might say, an attempt to determine what the most basic building blocks are, out of which the rest of reality is constructed. Philosophers of different times have shown different levels of optimism with respect to how much ontology can accomplish. It appears that Plato, for instance, thought that ontology is capable of showing the existence of entities that are outside of the sensible world, but play some key role in determining the nature of that world. Many philosophers in the twentieth century, however, saw ontology as, at best, an attempt to understand the relations within a certain set of concepts used, such as that of substance, property, and relation.

It is important to distinguish the sense of "metaphysics" employed by philosophers from its recent association with spirituality and world-transcending thought, though the latter does stem from developments in the former. Because metaphysics concerns itself with fundamental questions, nearly every major philosopher has devoted a certain amount of thought to metaphysics. This means, however, that a history of metaphysics would be little less than a history of all of philosophy. This article will, therefore, survey the issues that have most concerned metaphysicians throughout history. A list of historical figures especially worth considering is provided at the end.

Five central questions of metaphysics

Mind and matter

One of the central issues in metaphysics concerns how to understand the relation between minds and the world in which they exist. More specifically: Whether the most basic constituents of mind and the world were one and the same. Democritus and Epicurus, for instance, claimed that the world was fundamentally made up of indivisible particles, but held that the mind was simply a special sort of particle. Descartes held that the material world was composed of material substance, and so fundamentally unlike the intellectual substance that was minds. Spinoza and Leibniz claimed that all of the finite world had both a physical and an intellectual aspect—so that even the most simple physical particle in some sense had a mind. An even more radical position is that of Berkeley, who claimed that the material world is nothing more than ideas.

The root issue is that, in the task of trying to understand what the world is made up of, the metaphysician is faced with the fact that minds and matter appear to have very different natures. One is conscious, the other isn't. One appears to be divisible and complex, whereas the other seems simple. Yet the two also appear to interact, and it is plausible (as Spinoza explicitly states in Book 1 of his Ethics) that only things with something in common can interact. Further, one intuitively believes oneself to possess at least some knowledge about the nature of the world (especially as the result of science), and this seems to require that the divide between mind and world not go too deep.

Objects and their properties

In looking at objects in the world, one often will look for things they "have something in common." For instance, one might say that two apples have the same color, that two people are the same height, or that two books have the same number of chapters. But what is the nature of these entities that are "had in common?" They do not appear to be particular objects—these claims are not like the statement that two people might have a friend in common. The things appear to be "universal," not particular, in that they can be fully present in many things.

There are two related questions one might raise about universals like redness, roundness, etc. The first concerns their ontological status: In what way do these things exist? For instance, would redness still exist even if there weren't any particular objects that were red? After all, people don't think that destroying one red thing has any effect on redness itself, so why would the destruction of all of them do so? But if redness could exist without any particular red objects, then it must in some way be independent of them. This points to the second question: What is the relation between universals and particulars? Are particular objects something more than just a sum of universals, and if so, what? This latter question has a close relation to the issue of change.

The most extended discussions of this problem in ancient philosophy are found in the dialogues of Plato (in particular, the Parmenides). In much of his work, Plato argues that universals are more real than particulars, and as such philosophers who defend the claim that universals have some sort of independent existence are often called "Platonists." The opposing view, called "nominalism," holds that universals exist only in name—in other words, that humans merely have words that are applicable to many objects, but that there is no sense in which the words refer to some entities that are separate from particular objects.

Identity and change

Puzzles associated with change go back at least to Heraclitus' famous claim that "you cannot step into the same river twice." As it is most often interpreted, Heraclitus is making the following point: Given that there is a single river from moment to moment, since there is a change in what is present (for instance, a difference in water levels), it cannot be strictly true that the same river is there. That is, consider the following two claims:

  1. The river has the property of being 4 meters deep on Tuesday
  2. The river has the property of being 3.5 meters deep on Wednesday

But since no river can be both 4 meters deep and 3.5 meters deep, it would seem that the river found on Tuesday cannot be the river found on Wednesday.

One option is to accept the claim that the same river cannot be present at two times if there is any change. Yet this would lead one to claim that very few of the things one thought lasted through time do, since almost everything in the universe undergoes at least some change from moment to moment. Many philosophers have therefore tried to find ways to vindicate talk of persisting objects that don't involve the unacceptable claim that the same object can have incompatible properties.

One option is to deny that it is correct to say that (for instance) the river has both the property of being 4 meters deep and the property of being 3.5 meters deep, since those properties are incompatible. Rather, one might insist, the river has two properties that can be described by the phrases "being 4 meters deep on Tuesday" and "being 3.5 meters deep on Wednesday." The properties described by those phrases are obviously compatible. One might describe this solution as one of time-relativizing the properties themselves.

Another option is to see the object as broken down into "time-slices." The river is then seen as some sort of composite of slices that might be referred to by phrases such as "the river on Tuesday" and "the river on Wednesday." In this view, it's not strictly true that the properties of being being 4 meters deep and of being 3.5 meters deep are ascribed to the same object. Rather, they are ascribed to different objects (the time-slices), which are components of some larger object. This solution can be described as time-relativizing the objects.

A third option is to relativize the relation between the object and the property. In this view, the above statements should be recast as: "The river is—onTuesday—4 meters deep" and "The river is—on Wednesday—3.5 meters deep."

Though these distinctions seem overly subtle, the ramifications of the choice are very significant, for this is a choice about how to understand one of the most fundamental features of the universe: Change.

The structure of space and time

Space and time are some of the most basic features of the world. Things have spatiotemporal locations, and spatiotemporal relations to each other. One of the longest-standing metaphysical questions about space and time concerns how to understand the relationship between locations and relations.

A number of philosophers, including the great physicist Isaac Newton, have considered the notion of location to be more fundamental than that of the relations. They saw space, in particular, as a sort of substance, which is in principle capable of existing on its own. What explains two objects being, say, 20 miles apart on this view is some more basic facts along the lines of:

  1. Object A is at location 0,0,0.
  2. Object B is at location 20,0,0.

The opposing line of thought, advanced by philosophers such as Leibniz, held that relations are more basic than locations. But relations, obviously, only exist insofar as there are objects that are related. This in turn means that objects are more fundamental than their relations, and so more basic than space and time. Talk of particular locations, for someone like Leibniz, is merely a short-hand for describing relations between objects.

One of the key arguments Leibniz gave for his view was the following: Assume that the Newtonian view is correct. In that case, it is possible that every object in the universe be moved two feet to the left, changing absolute location, but with no change of relations. In Leibniz's own case, he appealed to God's rationality at this point, asking what reason God could have for choosing one location rather than another for the universe, and concluding that the question must have been confused to begin with. More recent philosophers have run the argument without the appeal to God, merely using it to point out the superfluousness of absolute location.

In response, Newtonians have worried whether it is intelligible to see space (and time, for which exactly similar arguments apply) as being dependent on objects in the way Leibniz's view requires.

Determinism and free will

One of the most recurrent philosophical problems comes from the apparent incompatibility of two independently plausible claims:

  1. Everything in the universe is causally determined, and what is causally determined could not have been otherwise.
  2. In acting in the universe, one sometimes could have done otherwise than he actually did.

The first question addressed by philosophers on this point is whether the claims are in fact incompatible.

"Compatibilists" claim that the apparent inconsistency of free will and determinism can be avoided if one properly specifies what each claim means. For instance, a compatibilist might claim that the "could have done otherwise" in (2) isn't about what really could have been otherwise, but perhaps merely what would have been otherwise if (as was in fact impossible) one had had a different set of desires of beliefs.

"Incompatibilists" are those who find no compatibilist solution acceptable, insisting that no compatibilist way of understanding the claims actually captures what was originally meant. Given this, incompatibilists think people have a choice between rejecting one claim or the other. "Libertarians" reject (1), insisting that their confidence in the freedom of their wills is sufficient to convince them that the universe cannot be causally determined. "Hard determinists" reject (2), concluding that the freedom of human will is a mere illusion (both Spinoza and Hume offer interests diagnoses of tendencies to believe that human wills are free).

A small number of recent philosophers have thought that developments in modern physics offered some help on this issue, particularly developments that suggest that there is no genuine determinacy. Unfortunately, the lack of determinism in such theories doesn't appear to be in the right "place." For instance, the fact that the location of particles is not determined by antecedent conditions doesn't seem to make room for human wills to be free, for the general laws of psychology still hold well enough.

Criticisms of metaphysics

Though some metaphysical projects have no ambitions beyond conceptual analysis, others have, to varying degrees, attempted to make substantive claims about the nature of reality (Plato again being a prime example). But the very suggestion that philosophers are in a position to discover substantive conclusions about the fundamental aspects of reality has struck many thinkers of an empiricist bent as patently absurd. This most frequently takes form as a challenge to whether such metaphysical claims can be justified, but an important movement known as logical positivism denied that metaphysics claims could even be meaningful.

Criticisms about justification

The line of thought that has lead some philosophers to claim that metaphysical statements cannot be justified runs roughly as follows: (1) Metaphysical statements are about the world, and (2) all that is known about the world is learned through the senses. Yet, as metaphysicians themselves admit, (3) metaphysical claims cannot be justified merely through the senses. Therefore, metaphysical claims cannot be justified. Such a sentiment is especially obvious in some of the writings of the Scottish philosopher David Hume:

If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion (An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding).

The obvious premise for the metaphysician to reject in the above argument is (2), the claim that all that is known about the world is based in the senses. Plato, for instance, held that prior to birth, one encountered more fundamental aspects of reality, and merely needed sensory promptings to recall those aspects. Descartes held that God had imprinted certain basic ideas in human minds in creating them, and that we could draw substantive conclusions from those ideas.

Kant, while being sympathetic to the basic anti-metaphysical argument, only accepted a qualified form of premise (1), the claim that metaphysical statements are about the world. He held that some metaphysical claims (such as "every change has a cause") are not about a world that is completely independent of humans, but rather about how objects appear to people. Moreover, the way that objects appear to people is partially determined by features of their own minds, and it is by knowing about those features that people can be justified in substantive claims about how objects will appear.

Criticisms about meaningfulness

Logical positivism, a movement started in Vienna that held a strong following in Britain, advanced a strong form of "verificationism," the view that the only meaningful statements were those that could, in principle, be verified by some set of observations. The positivists intended to use this view, which has at least some intuitive appeal, to do away with a large portion of religious doctrine and metaphysical disputes.

Three important features of most substantive metaphysical statements, such as "every event has a cause," are their universality, necessity, and non-analyticity. In other words, they say that, with respect to entire group of things (for example, events), that each member of that group cannot exist without having some feature (that is, "having a cause"), even though that feature wouldn't be mentioned in a fully adequate definition of the group. The most experiential observations can show people, however, that some particular thing actually has some feature. No set of observations can establish any non-definitional property of everything in a group, so all metaphysical claims would fail the verificationist test.

While it enjoyed considerable popularity for a time, the positivist project was eventually abandoned, for it became apparent that core statements of scientific theories (for example, the statement of universal gravitation) share some of the features of metaphysical statements, and so cannot be directly verified by observations. In the wake of positivism, their lessons were taken instead to show that metaphysical statements are not meaningless statements, but rather that they are generally not fallible, testable, or provable statements.

Major metaphysicians

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Gale, Richard M. 2002. The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell. ISBN 0631221204
  • Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, eds. 1999. Metaphysics: An Anthology. Blackwell Publishers. ISBN 0631202781
  • Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, eds. 1999. A Companion to Metaphysics. Cambridge: Blackwell Reference. ISBN 0631227687
  • Loux, M.J. 1998. Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction. London: Routledge. ISBN 0203283538
  • Lowe, E.J. 2002. A Survey of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0198752539

External links

All links retrieved November 9, 2022.

General philosophy sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.