Difference between revisions of "Antinomy" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 2: Line 2:
 
{{distinguish2|[[antimony]], a [[chemical element]]}}
 
{{distinguish2|[[antimony]], a [[chemical element]]}}
  
'''Antinomy''' ([[Greek language|Greek]] αντι-, against, plus νομος, law) literally means the mutual incompatibility, real or apparent, of two laws. It is a term often used in [[logic]] and [[epistemology]], when describing a [[paradox]] or unresolvable contradiction.
+
'''Antinomy''' ([[Greek language|Greek]] αντι-, against, plus νομος, law) literally means the mutual incompatibility, real or apparent, of two laws. It is a term often used in [[logic]] and [[epistemology]], when describing a [[paradox]] or unresolvable contradiction. Antinomy is best known for Kant's arguments in the “Transcendental Dialectic” of the ''Critique of Pure Reason.'' Antinomy is also discussed in the other two of three critiques (''Critique of Practical Reason'' and ''Critique of Judgment''). Kant tried to show that the faculty of reason can necessarily fall into contradictions or antinomy unless we take Kant's perspective. Antinomy is, thus, built into Kant's arguments themselves. In the ''Critique of Practical Reason,'' Kant presented the antinomy of [[morality]] and [[happiness]]. Morally good life does not necessarily bring about happiness on the earth. Morally goodness can result in persecution and even death. Kant argued that the [[existence of God]] and [[immortality]] of the soul in the life after death can be necessarily  postulated in order for the "supreme goodness" (realization of both moral goodness and happiness).
  
 
==Historical background==
 
==Historical background==

Revision as of 23:18, 24 March 2007

Not to be confused with antimony, a chemical element.

Antinomy (Greek αντι-, against, plus νομος, law) literally means the mutual incompatibility, real or apparent, of two laws. It is a term often used in logic and epistemology, when describing a paradox or unresolvable contradiction. Antinomy is best known for Kant's arguments in the “Transcendental Dialectic” of the Critique of Pure Reason. Antinomy is also discussed in the other two of three critiques (Critique of Practical Reason and Critique of Judgment). Kant tried to show that the faculty of reason can necessarily fall into contradictions or antinomy unless we take Kant's perspective. Antinomy is, thus, built into Kant's arguments themselves. In the Critique of Practical Reason, Kant presented the antinomy of morality and happiness. Morally good life does not necessarily bring about happiness on the earth. Morally goodness can result in persecution and even death. Kant argued that the existence of God and immortality of the soul in the life after death can be necessarily postulated in order for the "supreme goodness" (realization of both moral goodness and happiness).

Historical background

The term antinomy is found in Plutarch (46 – 127), but it became a key philosophical term with Kant. The term was used as a legal term since seventeenth century and it meant a contradiction among laws. Kant adopted this legal term as well as other legal terms and concepts into philosophy. With the term "antinomy," Kant tried to present that the faculty of reason can establish equally sound but incompatible or contradictory claims. With the argument of antinomy, Kant attempted show the limit of the valid use of the capacity of reason.

"Ideas" in Kant's critical works

Kant carried out the critique of the faculty of reason in his three critical works, Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of Practical Reason, and Critique of Judgment. He tried to present the limit of how reason can be used, by presenting antinomy or contradictory claims reason can reach. These critical works dealt with issues on epistemology or theory of knowledge, Ethics, and Aesthetics respectively. In the Critique of Pure Reason, he examined reason as a faculty of knowledge or cognition. In the Critique of Practical Reason, he dealt with reason as a faculty of moral judgment and actions, and in the Critique of Judgment, he examined reason as a faculty of aesthetic judgment. For Kant, critique meant a critical examination of reason as a faculty of judgment. Kant discussed issues of antinomy in all these critical works. Antinomy discussed in the Critique of Pure Reason is, however, best known.

The faculty of reason naturally pursues the unconditioned from the conditioned or the premise from the conclusion. Kant called the unconditioned “Ideas.” There are three Ideas, soul, world, and God.

When we have internal experiences, we try to think the totality of internal experiences and come to have the Idea (in Kantian sense) of the “soul.” Likewise, from experiences we have with external things, we tend to think the totality of the external things and have the Idea of the “world.” Similarly, from experiences we have with particular beings, we are led to think the totality of all beings and think the Idea of God.

For Kant, an object of cognition must have some sensible contents. We, however, tend to mistakenly conceive these Ideas (soul, world, and God) as the objects of cognition. These Ideas are, however, not the objects of cognition since they lack any sensible contents such as colors, shapes, sound, smells, and textures. We cannot see, smell, and touch them unlike other tangible objects. The problem arises, Kant argued, when we take these Ideas as real existence in the same sense that a tangible thing exists. Kant called these mistakenly understood Ideas “transcendental illusion” or “transcendental semblance” (in German, “transzendentaler Schein”).

For Kant, knowledge is the result of constitution of two components: first, sensible contents contents, such as colors and shapes, supplied by things; second, the forms which mind is equipped with such as space, time, quality, quantity, relation, and modality. We impose these categories or forms of mind, which mind has a priori, onto sensible contents we acquire from things outside of us. Human experience or cognition is the result of constitution of these forms of mind and sensible contents coming from outside. These Ideas such as God, soul, and world, are not directly observable and do not have any sensible contents (such as color, shape, smell, etc.), they cannot be an object of cognition. In the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant examined the mechanism of the process of how we gain experience and presented the limit of what is knowable.

Kant argued that these Ideas are not an element to constitute knowledge. In his phrase, Ideas are not “constitutive principle” (“konstitutives Prinzip”) of knowledge, but they should simply serve as the “regulative principle” (“regulatives Prinzip”) or “heuristic principle” (“heuristisches Prinzip”) that guide our thought.

Kant refused traditional speculative metaphysics which posited these Ideas as existence behind and above phenomena we can experience. Kant was accused of being a “destroyer” of metaphysics for his rejection of traditional metaphysicians' views. Kant denied metaphysicians’ approaches to Ideas but opened a practical approach to them in the sphere of morality. Kant argued that they are not the objects of cognition but they are postulated as necessary elements for moral reasoning.

Four Types of Antinomy in the “Transcendental Dialectic” of the Critique of Pure Reason

In the section, “Transcendental Dialectic” in the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant presented four types antinomy.

The First Antinomy

  • Thesis: The world is finite in time and space.
  • Antithesis: The world is infinite in time and space.

Kant's own formulation in the Critique of Pure Reason:

  • Thesis: The world has a beginning in time, and is also limited as regards space.
  • Antithesis: The world has no beginning, and no limits in space; it is infinite as regards both time and space.

(Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, Book II, Chapter II, Section 2. Norman Kemp-Smith's translation)

The first antinomy arises for the question of whether the world has the beginning in time or not, and whether it is specially finite or not. Reason can argue for each position but cannot reach any conclusive position. Reason cannot decide and resolve the antinomy.

The Second Antinomy

  • Thesis: The world is consisted of indivisible elements.
  • Antithesis: The world is not consisted of indivisible elements.

Kant's own formulation in the Critique of Pure Reason:

  • Thesis: Every composite substance in the world is made up of simple parts, and nothing anywhere exists save the simple or what is composed of the simple.
  • Antithesis: No composite thing in the world is made up of simple parts, and there nowhere exists in the world anything simple.

(Ibid)

The question is about the divisibility of components of the world. Can we divide the component of the world into such elements as atoms or particles, and further divide into finer components indefinitely? Or do we reach the final component whose further division is impossible?

The Third Antinomy

  • Thesis: There is freedom as a causailty in the world.
  • Antithesis: There is no freedom and everything in the world takes place according to laws of nature.

Kant's own formulation in the Critique of Pure Reason:

  • Thesis: Causality in accordance with laws of nature is not the only causality from which the appearances of the world can one and all be derived. To explain these appearances it is necessary to assume that there is also another causality, that of freedom.
  • Antithesis: There is no freedom; everything in the world takes place solely in accordance with laws of nature.

(Ibid)

If we trace a chain of cause and effect, do we reach the final point called freedom, which is the initial cause of the causal chain? Or do we never reach the final point and the chain of cause and effect continues endlessly? Is there any point outside of causal chain of beings in the universe?

The Fourth Antinomy

  • Thesis: There is the absolutely necessary being (such as God) in the causal chain of beings
  • Antithesis: There is no absolutely necessary being.
  • Thesis: There belongs to the world, either as its part or as its cause, a being that is absolutely necessary.
  • Antithesis: An absolutely necessary being nowhere exists in the world, nor does it exist outside the world as its cause.

(Ibid)

The question, here, is whether we can suppose the existence of God as the being which necessarily exists. Anselm of Canterbury formulated ontological proof of the existence of God: God is a unique being who exists by its essence. Anselm's was based upon the idea that God is that which "is" or who He "is." Validity of ontological argument had been discussed in the history of philosophy. Kant argued that we cannot settle the argument conclusively through rational arguments. Faculty of reason can make two incompatible claims.

Kant's arguments

Antinomy arises, Kant argued, upon two illegitimate presuppositions we make: first, space and time are forms of existence; second, we do not make a distinction between Phenomena and Noumena. For Kant, space and time are not forms of existence but subjective forms of mind. When a man has certain experiences, he or she unconsciously applies these forms of mind in order to organize the experiences. Furthermore, human cognition is limited to the sphere of phenomena which has certain sensible contents. But, things considered in themselves ("noumena" or "things in themselves") without consideration of human cognitive apparatus are, in principle, unknowable. (see Noumenon for further details.)

Antinomy arises when we take space and time as the forms of existing objects which are conceived as forms of "things in themselves" or "noumena." According to Kant, the first two forms of antinomy (Kant called "mathematical antinomy") are both false, and the third and the fourth forms of antinomy (Kant called "dynamic antinomy") are both true.

Examination of the Third Antinomy

The third antinomy is often considered to be of vital importance since the question of freedom is essential to moral philosophy. When we view the issue from two difference perspectives, Kant argued, antinomy disappears. When we view human actions as natural phenomena, we can perceive them in terms of causal chain and all phenomena occurs according to causality. If we view the same human actions from the perspective of will, which is outside of causal chains of beings, we can see them as caused by free will. In other words, freedom can be the cause in a different sense of natural cause.

Antinomy in the Critique of Practical Reason

Kant presents antinomy in the Critique of Practical Reason between morality and happiness. The supreme good is realized when both moral goodness and happiness are achieved. Human life on the earth, however, often presents contradictory reality. Even if a man tries to be morally good, he can be mistreated and led to misery. Injustice is rampant in human history. The faculty of reason demands both moral perfection and attainment of happiness at the same time, although there is no grantee for the attainment of both of them. Pursuit of happiness likewise does not necessarily lead the person morally good.

For this antinomy or contradiction, Kant argues, we are led to postulate the existence of God and the immortality of the soul in the world after death. God guarantees the agreement of happiness and moral goodness or the realization of supreme good in the world after death.

Antinomy in the Critique of Judgment

In the Critique of Judgment, Kant discusses about the antinomy of teleological view of nature and mechanical view of nature. The nature can be seen as having a built in purpose or a mechanically organized being without purpose. Kant argued that both positions are true. The resolution can be made when we see teleology and mechanistic view not as the objective principles of being but the subjective principles of judgment.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

External links

  • Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Pure Reason translated by Norman Kemp Smith. Electronic edition, Palgrave Macmillan. Retrieved March 22, 2007. See Book II, Chapter II, Section 2 for issues about Antinomy.
  • Kant's Critique of Metaphysics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved March 22, 2007.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.

  • This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.
  • This article was originally based on material from the Free On-line Dictionary of Computing, which is licensed under the GFDL.