Difference between revisions of "Hylozoism" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Hylozoism''' is the [[philosophy|philosophical]] doctrine that all or some material things possess life, or that all life is inseparable from matter.  The English term was introduced by [[Ralph Cudworth]] in [[1678]].
+
'''Hylozoism''' (Greek hyle, matter + zoe, life)  is the [[philosophy|philosophical]] doctrine that all matter possess life, or that all life is inseparable from matter.  The English term “hylozoism” was introduced by [[Ralph Cudworth]] in 1678. Hylozoism is logically distinct both from early forms of animism, which personify nature, and from panpsychism, which attributes some form of consciousness or sensation to all matter. Some of the ancient [[ancient Greece|Greek]] philosophers perceived a form of life in all material objects.  [[Thales]] taught that water was the primary substance and that all things were “full of gods;”  [[Anaximenes_of_Miletus|Anaximenes]] saw air as the universal animating principle; and [[Heraklitus]] taught that it as fire.  The [[Stoicism|Stoics]] believed that a ''world soul'' informed all things in the world.
  
==  Distinction from cognate doctrines ==
+
Neo-Pythagoreans and especially the Neo-Platonic school of Alexandria, accepted the Stoic concept of the world-soul, but gave priority to the soul as a spiritual principle emanating from God. The universe was perceived as a single organism, and life was imparted to all material beings from the one original source, God, with matter in the position farthest from God, and least perfect. This pantheistic concept of hylozoism was absorbed into medieval Jewish and Arabian philosophy, and reappeared in Christian countries during the Renaissance in the thought of nature philosophers such as Paracelsus, Cardanus, Giordano Bruno.  In the nineteenth century, developments in the biological sciences stimulated a new examination of the nature of life, which resulted in the development of scientific hylozoism.  [[Ernst Heinrich Haeckel]] developed a [[materialism|materialist]] form of hylozoism which erased the distinction between living and non-living things, maintaining that they are, essentially, the same and stipulating that they behave by a single set of laws.
Although there is a distinction between possessing soul ([[panpsychism]]) and possessing life (hylozoism), in practice this division is difficult to maintain, because the ancient hylozoists not only regarded the spirits of the [[matter|material]] universe and plant world as alive, but also as more or less conscious. Whereas [[animism]] tends to view life as taking the form of discrete [[soul|spirits]], and [[panpsychism]] tends to refer to strictly philosophical views like that of [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]], hylozoism refers largely to views such as those of the earliest Greek philosophers (6th and 5th centuries B.C.E.).  Certain of these treated the magnet as alive because of its attractive powers ([[Thales]]), or air as 'divine' ([[Anaximenes]]), perhaps because of its apparently spontaneous power of movement, or because of its role as essential for life in animals. Later this primitive hylozoism reappeared in modified forms.  Some scholars have since claimed that 'hylozoism' should properly be used only where body and soul are explicitly distinguished, the distinction then being rejected as invalid.  Nevertheless, hylozoism remains logically distinct both from early forms of animism, which personify nature, and from panpsychism, which attributes some form of consciousness or sensation to all matter.   
+
   
  
== Ancient hylozoism ==
+
== Animism and Panpsychism ==
Some of the ancient [[ancient Greece|Greek]] philosophers taught a version of hylozoism, as they, however vaguely, conceived the elemental matter as being in some sense animate if not actually conscious and [[will|conative]].  [[Thales]], [[Anaximenes_of_Miletus|Anaximenes]], and [[Heraklitus]] all taught that there is a form of life in all material objects, and the [[Stoicism|Stoics]] believed that a ''world soul'' informed all things in the worldA likely source for the Greek hylozoists was the Iranian philosopher [[Zarathushtra]], founder of the religion of [[Zoroastrianism]] and an early proponent of [[pantheism]], even if his religion later diversified to also include a variety of [[dualisms]]. It is important to note that these philosophies did not necessarily hold that material objects had ''separate life'' or ''identity'', necessarily, but only that they had life, either as part of an overriding entity or as living but insensible entities.
+
Although there is a logical distinction between possessing soul ([[panpsychism]]) and possessing life (hylozoism), in practice this division is difficult to maintain, because the ancient hylozoists regarded aspects of the [[matter|material]] universe and plant world not only as possessing life, but also as being more or less consciousWhereas [[animism]] tends to view life as taking the form of discrete [[soul|spirits]], and [[panpsychism]] tends to refer to strictly philosophical views like that of [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]] or Spinoza, hylozoism refers largely to views such as those of the earliest Greek philosophers (sixth and fifth centuries B.C.E.)Certain of these treated the magnet as alive because of its attractive powers ([[Thales]]), or air as 'divine' ([[Anaximenes]]), perhaps because of its apparently spontaneous power of movement, or because of its role as essential for life in animals. Later this primitive hylozoism reappeared in modified forms. Some scholars have since claimed that 'hylozoism' should properly be used only where body and soul are explicitly distinguished, the distinction then being rejected as invalid.  Nevertheless, hylozoism remains logically distinct both from early forms of animism, which personify nature, and from panpsychism, which attributes some form of consciousness or sensation to all matter.
  
== Hylozoism in Renaissance and early Modernity ==
+
== Ancient Hylozoism ==
In the [[Renaissance]], [[Bernardino Telesio]], [[Paracelsus]], [[Cardanus]],  and [[Giordano Bruno]] revived the doctrine of hylozoism. The latter, for example, held a form of [[Christian]] [[pantheism]]. [[God]] is the source, cause, medium, and end of all things, and therefore all things are participatory in the ongoing Godhead. Bruno's ideas were so radical that he was entirely rejected by the [[Roman Catholic Church]] as well as excommunicated from a few Protestant groups, and he was eventually burned at the stake for various heresies. Telesio, on the other hand, began from an [[Aristotle|Aristotelian]] basis and, through radical [[empiricism]], came to believe that a living force was what informed all matter.  Instead of the intellectual universals of Aristotle, he believed that life generated form.   
+
Some of the ancient [[ancient Greece|Greek]] philosophers taught a form of hylozoism when they conceived the elemental matter as being in some sense animate if not actually conscious and conative (tending to willful action). They perceived a form of life in all material objects. [[Thales]] taught that water was the primary substance and that all things were “full of gods;” [[Anaximenes_of_Miletus|Anaximenes]] saw air as the universal animating principle; and [[Heraklitus]] taught that it as fire.  The [[Stoicism|Stoics]] believed that a ''world soul'' informed all things in the world.   
  
In [[England]], some of the [[Cambridge Platonists]] approached hylozoism as well. Both [[Henry More]] and Ralph Cudworth (''the Younger'', 1617-1688), through their reconciliation of Platonic [[idealism]] with Christian doctrines of deific generation, came to see the divine lifeforce as the informing principle in the world. Thus, like Bruno, but not nearly to the extreme, they saw God's generative impulse as giving life to all things that exist. Accordingly Cudworth, the most systematic metaphysician of the [[Cambridge]] [[Platonist]] tradition, fought hylozoism. His work is primarily a critique of what he took to be the two principal forms of atheism. ''i.e.'' materialism and hylozoism. The hylozoist whom Cudworth had especially in mind is [[Thomas Hobbes]].
+
A possible source for the Greek hylozoists was the Iranian philosopher [[Zarathushtra]], founder of the religion of [[Zoroastrianism]] and an early proponent of [[pantheism]], though the religion he founded later diversified to also include a variety of dualisms. It is also possible that the Greek concepts of hylozoism were a natural consequence of the human tendency to interpret other existences in terms of human experiences and feelings.
 +
These ancient philosophies did not necessarily hold that material objects had ''separate life'' or ''identity,'' but only that they had life, either as part of an overriding entity or as living but insensible entities.
 +
Strato of Lampsacus, the second successor of Aristotle, espoused a kind of materialistic hylozoism.  Though  Strato repudiated the mechanicism of the Atomists, he reduced all reality to physical matter, and explained life as movement, a property of matter. The Stoics taught that  material bodies are made up of two principles, a passive principle, matter, and an active principle, form; but that form itself was corporeal, composed of pneuma (vapor) or pyr technikon (creative fire, or God).  
 +
Neo-Pythagoreans and especially the Neo-Platonic school of Alexandria, accepted the Stoic concept of the world-soul, but gave priority to the soul as a spiritual principle emanating from God, and placed matter in the position farthest from God, and least perfect. The universe was perceived as a single organism, and life was imparted to all material beings from the one original source, God. This pantheistic concept of hylozoism was absorbed into medieval Jewish and Arabian philosophy, and reappeared in Christian countries during the Renaissance in the thought of nature philosophers such as Paracelsus, Cardanus, Giordano Bruno,
  
Cudworth singled out Hobbes not only as a defender of the hylozoic atheism "which attributes life to matter", but also as one going beyond it and defending "hylopathian atheism, which attributes all to matter." Cudworth attempted to show that Hobbes had revived the doctrines of [[Protagoras]] and was therefore subject to the criticisms which [[Plato]] had deployed against Protagoras in the ''Theaetetus''. On the side of hylozoism, [[Strato]] was the official target. However, Cudworth's Dutch friends had reported to him the views which [[Spinoza]] was circulating in manuscript. Cudworth remarks in his ''Preface'' that he would have ignored hylozoism had he not been aware that a new version of it would shortly be published. 
 
  
::'''Reference'''
 
::''The True Intellectual System of the Universe: The First part; wherein, All the Reason and Philosophy of Atheism is Confuted; and Its Impossibility Demonstrated''. By Ralph Cudworth, D.D. London, Printed for Richard Royston, 1678.
 
  
[[Spinoza]]'s idealism also tends toward hylozoism.  In order to hold a balance even between matter and mind, Spinoza in fact combined materialistic with pantheistic hylozoism, by reducing both to the rank of mere attributes of the one infinite substance.  Although he specifically rejects identity in inorganic matter, he, like the Cambridge Platonists, sees a life force or living force within, as well as beyond, all matter.
+
== Hylozoism in Renaissance and Early Modern Thought ==
  
== Contemporary hylozoism ==
+
During the [[Renaissance]], [[Bernardino Telesio]], [[Paracelsus]], [[Cardanus]], and [[Giordano Bruno]] (1548-1600) revived the concept of hylozoism.  Giordano Bruno held that [[God]] is the source, cause, medium, and end of all things, and therefore all things are participatory in the ongoing Godhead.  Bruno's ideas were rejected by the [[Roman Catholic Church]]; he was excommunicated by several Protestant groups, and eventually burned at the stake as a heretic by the Inquisition. Telesio, through an empirical analysis of sensual data, came to believe that a living force was what informed all matter and that each separate thing develops in and for itself in accordance with its own nature. Since consciousness exists, and could not have been developed out of nothing, he concluded that matter also must have been from the first endowed with consciousness.
Inmanuel [[Kant]] developed cogent arguments against hylozoism in the third chapter of his ''Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaften'' ("First Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science," 1786) and also in his famous ''Kritik der reinen Vernunft'' ("Critique of Pure Reason," 1783).  Yet, in our times, scientific hylozoism – whether modified, or keeping the trend to make all beings conform to some uniform pattern with which it was adhered to in Modernity by [[Spencer]], [[Lotze]], and [[Haeckel]] – was often called upon as a protest against a [[mechanism|mechanicistic view]] of the world.
+
The word “hylozoism” was coined in the seventeenth century by Ralph Cudworth (''the Younger'', 1617-1688), a Cambridge Platonist, who with Henry More reconciled Platonic [[idealism]] with Christian doctrines of deific generation and came to see the divine life force as the informing principle in the world. They saw God's generative impulse as giving life to all things that exist, and characterized it as a “plastic nature,” an unconscious, incorporeal substance that controls and organizes matter (somewhat like a plant soul in vegetation) and thus produces natural events as a divine instrument of change.
::'''Reference'''
+
Cudworth, the most systematic metaphysician of the Cambridge Platonist tradition, critiqued what he took to be the two principal forms of atheism, materialism and “hylozoism.” Cudworth singled out Thomas Hobbes not only as a defender of the hylozoic atheism "which attributes life to matter", but also as one who defended "hylopathian atheism, which attributes all to matter." Cudworth attempted to show that Hobbes had revived the doctrines of [[Protagoras]] and was therefore subject to the criticisms which [[Plato]] had deployed against Protagoras in the ''Theaetetus''. He also launched an attack on the hylozoism of [[Strato]]. Cudworth had received reports from friends in the Netherlands of the views which [[Spinoza]] was circulating in manuscript, and remarked in his ''Preface'' that he would have ignored hylozoism had he not been aware that a new version of it would shortly be published.  
::[http://www2.rz.hu-berlin.de/phil/kantkongress/14/look.html Hylozoism and Dogmatism in Kant, Leibniz, and Newton]
 
  
In the 19th century, [[Ernst Heinrich Haeckel]] developed a [[materialism|materialist]] form of hylozoism, specially against [[Virchow]]'s and [[Helmholtz]]'s mechanical views of humans and nature.  In his ''Die Welträtsel'' of [[1899]] (''The Riddle of the Universe'' [[1901]]), Haeckel upheld a unity of organic and inorganic nature and derived all actions of both types of matter from natural causes and laws. Thus, his form of hylozoism reverses the usual course by maintaining that living and non-living things are, essentially, the same and by erasing the distinction between the two and stipulating that they behave by a single set of laws.
+
<ref>''The True Intellectual System of the Universe: The First part; wherein, All the Reason and Philosophy of Atheism is Confuted; and Its Impossibility Demonstrated''. By Ralph Cudworth, D.D. London, Printed for Richard Royston, 1678. .</ref>
  
In contrast, the Argentine-German neurobiological tradition terms ''hylozoic hiatus'' all of the parts of nature which can only behave lawfully or nomically and, upon such a feature, are described as lying outside of minds and amid them – ''i.e''., extramentally.  Thereby the hylozoic hiatus becomes contraposed to minds deemed able of behaving semoviently, ''i.e''. able of inaugurating new causal series (semovience).  Hylozoism in this contemporary neurobiological tradition is thus restricted to the portions of nature behaving nomically inside the minds, namely the minds' sensory reactions ([[Christfried Jakob]]'s "sensory intonations") whereby minds react to the stimuli coming from the hylozoic hiatus or extramental realm.
+
[[Spinoza]]'s idealism also tends toward hylozoism.  Seeking a balance between matter and mind, Spinoza combined materialistic with pantheistic hylozoism, reducing both matter and mind to mere attributes of one infinite substance.  Although he specifically rejected identity in inorganic matter, he, like the Cambridge Platonists, perceived a life force within, as well as beyond, all matter.
 +
Leibniz, resolving matter into spirit, looked on bodies as aggregates of simple unextended substances or monads, endowed with elementary perception and will. On the contrary, a group of French writers in the eighteenth century, Diderot, Cabanis, Robinet, etc., adhered to a dynamico-materialistic view of the world which recalls that of Strato.
 +
Denis Diderot, Pierre-Jean-Georges Cabanis, and J.B. Robinet, eighteenth-century Encyclopaedists, espoused a dynamic, materialistic view of nature (not unlike that of Strato), which treated life as an attribute of matter, and which was later adapted by nineteenth-century evolutionist philosophers.
 +
Immanuel [[Kant]] developed cogent arguments against hylozoism in the third chapter of his ''Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaften'' ("First Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science," 1786) and also in his famous ''Kritik der reinen Vernunft'' ("Critique of Pure Reason," 1783).   
 +
== Contemporary Hylozoism ==
 +
In the nineteenth century, developments in the biological sciences stimulated a new examination of the nature of life, which resulted in the development of scientific hylozoism. In reaction to a purely mechanistic view of the world, [[Spencer]], [[Lotze]], and [[Haeckel]] developed the concept of a unifying life force which animated all of nature. <ref>[http://www2.rz.hu-berlin.de/phil/kantkongress/14/look.html Hylozoism and Dogmatism in Kant, Leibniz, and Newton]</ref>
 +
 
 +
[[Ernst Heinrich Haeckel]] developed a [[materialism|materialist]] form of hylozoism, specially against [[Virchow]]'s and [[Helmholtz]]'s mechanical views of humans and nature.  In his ''Die Welträtsel'' of 1899 (''The Riddle of the Universe'' 1901), Haeckel upheld a unity of organic and inorganic nature and derived all actions of both types of matter from natural causes and laws.  His form of hylozoism erased the distinction between living and non-living things, maintaining that they are, essentially, the same and stipulating that they behave by a single set of laws.
  
::'''References'''
+
[[Martin Buber]] (1878 – 1965), too, took an approach that is quasi-hylozoic. By maintaining that the essence of things is identifiable and separate, although not pre-existing, he was able to see a soul within each thing.
::[http://electroneubio.secyt.gov.ar/commentl.htm Comment l’ hylozoïsme scientifique contemporain aborde-t-il la sélection naturelle du parenchyme neurocognitif?] (French)
 
::[http://cogprints.org/4662 On minds’ localization].
 
  
[[Martin Buber]], too, takes an approach that is quasi-hylozoicBy maintaining that the essence of things is identifiable and separate, although not pre-existing, he can see a soul within each thing.
+
==Hylozoic Hiatus==
 +
The Argentine-German neurobiological tradition uses the term ''hylozoic hiatus'' to refer to all of the parts of nature which can only behave lawfully or nomically.  These parts of nature are described as “extramental,” or lying outside of and amid “minds,” which are the aspects of nature deemed capable of behaving semoviently (in a way that inaugurates new causal series)In this contemporary neurobiological tradition, hylozoism is restricted to the portions of nature behaving nomically inside the minds, namely the minds' sensory reactions (Christfried Jakob's "sensory intonations") to the stimuli coming from the “hylozoic hiatus” or “extramental” realm.
  
==Hylozoists in Pop Culture==
+
<ref>
 
+
[http://electroneubio.secyt.gov.ar/commentl.htm Comment l’ hylozoïsme scientifique contemporain aborde-t-il la sélection naturelle du parenchyme neurocognitif?] (French)
The Hylozoists are a Canadian band that have produced two albums, the second of which is called "La fin du monde".
+
[http://cogprints.org/4662 On minds’ localization] </ref>
 
+
.
== Fiction: the monster "Hylozoist" ==
 
On a related note, the monster "Hylozoist" (sometimes spelled "Heirozoist") in the MMORPG [[Ragnarok Online]] is a plush rabbit doll with its mouth sewn shut, possessed by the spirit of a child. Although hylozoism has nothing to do with possession, it is clear that the name was derived from this ancient philosophy.
 
  
 +
[[Martin Buber]], too, takes an approach that is quasi-hylozoic.  By maintaining that the essence of things is identifiable and separate, although not pre-existing, he can see a soul within each thing.
  
  
 +
==Notes==
 +
<div class="references-small">
 +
<references/>
 +
</div>
 +
==References==
 +
*Emerton, Norma E. 1984. The scientific reinterpretation of form. Cornell history of science series. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. ISBN: 0801415837 9780801415838
 +
*McMullin, Ernan, Joseph Bobik, and Ernan McMullin. 1965. The concept of matter in Greek and medieval philosophy. Notre Dame, Ind.]: University of Notre Dame Press.
 +
*Nussbaum, Martha Craven, and Amélie Rorty. 1992. Essays on Aristotle's De anima. Oxford [England]: Clarendon Press. ISBN: 0198244614 9780198244615
 +
*Wulftange, Joseph, and Merrill Greene. 1952. Hylomorphism and contemporary physics. Woodstock, Md: Woodstock College Press.
 
== See also ==
 
== See also ==
  
 
* [[Animism]]
 
* [[Animism]]
* [[Hyle]]
 
 
* [[Hylomorphism]]
 
* [[Hylomorphism]]
 
* [[Panpsychism]]
 
* [[Panpsychism]]
Line 60: Line 72:
 
[[Category:History of science]]
 
[[Category:History of science]]
 
[[Category:20th century]]
 
[[Category:20th century]]
 
[[de:Hylozoismus]]
 
[[el:Υλοζωϊσμός]]
 
[[es:Hilozoísmo (filosofía)]]
 
[[eo:Hilozoismo]]
 
[[it:Ilozoismo]]
 
[[ru:Гилозоизм]]
 
[[sk:Hylozoizmus]]
 
 
{{Credit|101414274}}
 
{{Credit|101414274}}

Revision as of 16:06, 7 May 2007

Hylozoism (Greek hyle, matter + zoe, life) is the philosophical doctrine that all matter possess life, or that all life is inseparable from matter. The English term “hylozoism” was introduced by Ralph Cudworth in 1678. Hylozoism is logically distinct both from early forms of animism, which personify nature, and from panpsychism, which attributes some form of consciousness or sensation to all matter. Some of the ancient Greek philosophers perceived a form of life in all material objects. Thales taught that water was the primary substance and that all things were “full of gods;” Anaximenes saw air as the universal animating principle; and Heraklitus taught that it as fire. The Stoics believed that a world soul informed all things in the world.

Neo-Pythagoreans and especially the Neo-Platonic school of Alexandria, accepted the Stoic concept of the world-soul, but gave priority to the soul as a spiritual principle emanating from God. The universe was perceived as a single organism, and life was imparted to all material beings from the one original source, God, with matter in the position farthest from God, and least perfect. This pantheistic concept of hylozoism was absorbed into medieval Jewish and Arabian philosophy, and reappeared in Christian countries during the Renaissance in the thought of nature philosophers such as Paracelsus, Cardanus, Giordano Bruno. In the nineteenth century, developments in the biological sciences stimulated a new examination of the nature of life, which resulted in the development of scientific hylozoism. Ernst Heinrich Haeckel developed a materialist form of hylozoism which erased the distinction between living and non-living things, maintaining that they are, essentially, the same and stipulating that they behave by a single set of laws.


Animism and Panpsychism

Although there is a logical distinction between possessing soul (panpsychism) and possessing life (hylozoism), in practice this division is difficult to maintain, because the ancient hylozoists regarded aspects of the material universe and plant world not only as possessing life, but also as being more or less conscious. Whereas animism tends to view life as taking the form of discrete spirits, and panpsychism tends to refer to strictly philosophical views like that of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz or Spinoza, hylozoism refers largely to views such as those of the earliest Greek philosophers (sixth and fifth centuries B.C.E.). Certain of these treated the magnet as alive because of its attractive powers (Thales), or air as 'divine' (Anaximenes), perhaps because of its apparently spontaneous power of movement, or because of its role as essential for life in animals. Later this primitive hylozoism reappeared in modified forms. Some scholars have since claimed that 'hylozoism' should properly be used only where body and soul are explicitly distinguished, the distinction then being rejected as invalid. Nevertheless, hylozoism remains logically distinct both from early forms of animism, which personify nature, and from panpsychism, which attributes some form of consciousness or sensation to all matter.

Ancient Hylozoism

Some of the ancient Greek philosophers taught a form of hylozoism when they conceived the elemental matter as being in some sense animate if not actually conscious and conative (tending to willful action). They perceived a form of life in all material objects. Thales taught that water was the primary substance and that all things were “full of gods;” Anaximenes saw air as the universal animating principle; and Heraklitus taught that it as fire. The Stoics believed that a world soul informed all things in the world.

A possible source for the Greek hylozoists was the Iranian philosopher Zarathushtra, founder of the religion of Zoroastrianism and an early proponent of pantheism, though the religion he founded later diversified to also include a variety of dualisms. It is also possible that the Greek concepts of hylozoism were a natural consequence of the human tendency to interpret other existences in terms of human experiences and feelings.

These ancient philosophies did not necessarily hold that material objects had separate life or identity, but only that they had life, either as part of an overriding entity or as living but insensible entities. 

Strato of Lampsacus, the second successor of Aristotle, espoused a kind of materialistic hylozoism. Though Strato repudiated the mechanicism of the Atomists, he reduced all reality to physical matter, and explained life as movement, a property of matter. The Stoics taught that material bodies are made up of two principles, a passive principle, matter, and an active principle, form; but that form itself was corporeal, composed of pneuma (vapor) or pyr technikon (creative fire, or God). Neo-Pythagoreans and especially the Neo-Platonic school of Alexandria, accepted the Stoic concept of the world-soul, but gave priority to the soul as a spiritual principle emanating from God, and placed matter in the position farthest from God, and least perfect. The universe was perceived as a single organism, and life was imparted to all material beings from the one original source, God. This pantheistic concept of hylozoism was absorbed into medieval Jewish and Arabian philosophy, and reappeared in Christian countries during the Renaissance in the thought of nature philosophers such as Paracelsus, Cardanus, Giordano Bruno,


Hylozoism in Renaissance and Early Modern Thought

During the Renaissance, Bernardino Telesio, Paracelsus, Cardanus, and Giordano Bruno (1548-1600) revived the concept of hylozoism. Giordano Bruno held that God is the source, cause, medium, and end of all things, and therefore all things are participatory in the ongoing Godhead. Bruno's ideas were rejected by the Roman Catholic Church; he was excommunicated by several Protestant groups, and eventually burned at the stake as a heretic by the Inquisition. Telesio, through an empirical analysis of sensual data, came to believe that a living force was what informed all matter and that each separate thing develops in and for itself in accordance with its own nature. Since consciousness exists, and could not have been developed out of nothing, he concluded that matter also must have been from the first endowed with consciousness. The word “hylozoism” was coined in the seventeenth century by Ralph Cudworth (the Younger, 1617-1688), a Cambridge Platonist, who with Henry More reconciled Platonic idealism with Christian doctrines of deific generation and came to see the divine life force as the informing principle in the world. They saw God's generative impulse as giving life to all things that exist, and characterized it as a “plastic nature,” an unconscious, incorporeal substance that controls and organizes matter (somewhat like a plant soul in vegetation) and thus produces natural events as a divine instrument of change. Cudworth, the most systematic metaphysician of the Cambridge Platonist tradition, critiqued what he took to be the two principal forms of atheism, materialism and “hylozoism.” Cudworth singled out Thomas Hobbes not only as a defender of the hylozoic atheism "which attributes life to matter", but also as one who defended "hylopathian atheism, which attributes all to matter." Cudworth attempted to show that Hobbes had revived the doctrines of Protagoras and was therefore subject to the criticisms which Plato had deployed against Protagoras in the Theaetetus. He also launched an attack on the hylozoism of Strato. Cudworth had received reports from friends in the Netherlands of the views which Spinoza was circulating in manuscript, and remarked in his Preface that he would have ignored hylozoism had he not been aware that a new version of it would shortly be published.

[1]

Spinoza's idealism also tends toward hylozoism. Seeking a balance between matter and mind, Spinoza combined materialistic with pantheistic hylozoism, reducing both matter and mind to mere attributes of one infinite substance. Although he specifically rejected identity in inorganic matter, he, like the Cambridge Platonists, perceived a life force within, as well as beyond, all matter. Leibniz, resolving matter into spirit, looked on bodies as aggregates of simple unextended substances or monads, endowed with elementary perception and will. On the contrary, a group of French writers in the eighteenth century, Diderot, Cabanis, Robinet, etc., adhered to a dynamico-materialistic view of the world which recalls that of Strato. Denis Diderot, Pierre-Jean-Georges Cabanis, and J.B. Robinet, eighteenth-century Encyclopaedists, espoused a dynamic, materialistic view of nature (not unlike that of Strato), which treated life as an attribute of matter, and which was later adapted by nineteenth-century evolutionist philosophers. Immanuel Kant developed cogent arguments against hylozoism in the third chapter of his Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Naturwissenschaften ("First Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science," 1786) and also in his famous Kritik der reinen Vernunft ("Critique of Pure Reason," 1783).

Contemporary Hylozoism

In the nineteenth century, developments in the biological sciences stimulated a new examination of the nature of life, which resulted in the development of scientific hylozoism. In reaction to a purely mechanistic view of the world, Spencer, Lotze, and Haeckel developed the concept of a unifying life force which animated all of nature. [2]

Ernst Heinrich Haeckel developed a materialist form of hylozoism, specially against Virchow's and Helmholtz's mechanical views of humans and nature.  In his Die Welträtsel of 1899 (The Riddle of the Universe 1901), Haeckel upheld a unity of organic and inorganic nature and derived all actions of both types of matter from natural causes and laws.  His form of hylozoism erased the distinction between living and non-living things, maintaining that they are, essentially, the same and stipulating that they behave by a single set of laws.
Martin Buber (1878 – 1965), too, took an approach that is quasi-hylozoic.  By maintaining that the essence of things is identifiable and separate, although not pre-existing, he was able to see a soul within each thing.

Hylozoic Hiatus

The Argentine-German neurobiological tradition uses the term hylozoic hiatus to refer to all of the parts of nature which can only behave lawfully or nomically. These parts of nature are described as “extramental,” or lying outside of and amid “minds,” which are the aspects of nature deemed capable of behaving semoviently (in a way that inaugurates new causal series). In this contemporary neurobiological tradition, hylozoism is restricted to the portions of nature behaving nomically inside the minds, namely the minds' sensory reactions (Christfried Jakob's "sensory intonations") to the stimuli coming from the “hylozoic hiatus” or “extramental” realm.

[3] .

Martin Buber, too, takes an approach that is quasi-hylozoic. By maintaining that the essence of things is identifiable and separate, although not pre-existing, he can see a soul within each thing.


Notes

  1. The True Intellectual System of the Universe: The First part; wherein, All the Reason and Philosophy of Atheism is Confuted; and Its Impossibility Demonstrated. By Ralph Cudworth, D.D. London, Printed for Richard Royston, 1678. .
  2. Hylozoism and Dogmatism in Kant, Leibniz, and Newton
  3. Comment l’ hylozoïsme scientifique contemporain aborde-t-il la sélection naturelle du parenchyme neurocognitif? (French) On minds’ localization

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Emerton, Norma E. 1984. The scientific reinterpretation of form. Cornell history of science series. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. ISBN: 0801415837 9780801415838
  • McMullin, Ernan, Joseph Bobik, and Ernan McMullin. 1965. The concept of matter in Greek and medieval philosophy. Notre Dame, Ind.]: University of Notre Dame Press.
  • Nussbaum, Martha Craven, and Amélie Rorty. 1992. Essays on Aristotle's De anima. Oxford [England]: Clarendon Press. ISBN: 0198244614 9780198244615
  • Wulftange, Joseph, and Merrill Greene. 1952. Hylomorphism and contemporary physics. Woodstock, Md: Woodstock College Press.

See also

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.