Philosophy of Mathematics

From New World Encyclopedia

Philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the philosophical assumptions, foundations, and implications of mathematics.

Recurrent themes include:

  • What are the sources of mathematical subject matter?
  • What does it mean to refer to a mathematical object?
  • What is the character of a mathematical proposition?
  • What is the relation between logic and mathematics?
  • What is the role of Hermeneutics in mathematics?
  • What kinds of inquiry play a role in mathematics?
  • What are the objectives of mathematical inquiry?
  • What gives mathematics its hold on experience?
  • What are the human traits behind mathematics?
  • What is mathematical beauty?

The terms philosophy of mathematics and mathematical philosophy are frequently used as synonyms.[1]

The latter, however, may be used to mean at least three other things. One sense refers to a project of formalizing a philosophical subject matter, say, aesthetics, ethics, logic, metaphysics, or theology, in a purportedly more exact and rigorous form, as for example the labors of Scholastic theologians, or the systematic aims of Leibniz and Spinoza. Another sense refers to the working philosophy of an individual practitioner or a like-minded community of practicing mathematicians. Additionally, some understand the term mathematical philosophy to be an allusion to the approach taken by Bertrand Russell in his book Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy.

Historical overview

Many thinkers have contributed their ideas concerning the nature of mathematics. Today, some philosophers of mathematics aim to give accounts of this form of inquiry and its products as they stand, while others emphasize a role for themselves that goes beyond simple interpretation to critical analysis. Western philosophies of mathematics go as far back as Plato, who studied the ontological status of mathematical objects, and Aristotle, who studied logic and issues related to infinity (actual versus potential).

Beginning with Leibniz, the focus shifted strongly to the relationship between mathematics and logic. This view dominated the philosophy of mathematics through the time of Frege and of Russell, but was brought into question by developments in the late nineteenth and early twentieth century.

In the twentieth century, philosophers of mathematics were beginning to divide into various schools, broadly distinguished by their pictures of mathematical epistemology and ontology. Three schools, formalism, intuitionism, and logicism, emerged at this time, partly in response to the increasingly widespread worry that mathematics as it stood might not live up to the standards of certainty and rigor that had been taken for granted in the presence of various foundational paradoxes such as Russell's paradox. Each school addressed the issues that came to the fore at that time, either attempting to resolve them or claiming that mathematics is not entitled to its status as our most trusted knowledge.

These currents of thoughts led to the developments in formal logic and set theory early in the twentieth century concerning the new questions about what the foundation of mathematics is. As the century unfolded, the initial focus of concern expanded to an open exploration of the fundamental axioms of mathematics, the axiomatic approach having been taken for granted since the time of Euclid as the natural basis for mathematics. Core concepts such as axiom, order, and set received fresh emphasis. In mathematics as in physics, new and unexpected ideas had arisen and significant changes were coming. Inquiries into the consistency of mathematical theories lead to the development of a new level of study, a reflective critique in which the theory under review "becomes itself the object of a mathematical study," what Hilbert called metamathematics or proof theory [2].

At the midpoint of the century, a new mathematical theory known as category theory arose as a new contender for the natural language of mathematical thinking [3]. As the twentieth century progressed, however, philosophical opinions diverged as to just how well-founded were the questions about foundations that were raised at its opening. Hilary Putnam summed up one common view of the situation in the last third of the century by saying:

When philosophy discovers something wrong with science, sometimes science has to be changed—Russell's paradox comes to mind, as does Berkeley's attack on the actual infinitesimal—but more often it is philosophy that has to be changed. I do not think that the difficulties that philosophy finds with classical mathematics today are genuine difficulties; and I think that the philosophical interpretations of mathematics that we are being offered on every hand are wrong, and that 'philosophical interpretation' is just what mathematics doesn't need. [4].

Philosophy of mathematics today proceeds along several different lines of inquiry, by philosophers of mathematics, logicians, and mathematicians, and there are many schools of thought on the subject. The schools are addressed separately in the next section, and their assumptions explained.

Contemporary schools of thought

The ones discussed here are a few of the main views regarding the various questions found in the philosophy of mathematics.

Mathematical realism

Mathematical realism, like realism in general, holds that mathematics is dependent on some reality independent of the human mind. Thus humans do not invent mathematics, but rather discover it, and any other intelligent beings in the universe would presumably do the same. In this point of view, there is really one sort of mathematics that can be discovered: Triangles, for example, are real entities, not the creations of the human mind.

One form of mathematical realism is the view called Platonism. This view is that mathematical entities are abstract, have no spatiotemporal or causal properties, and are eternal and unchanging. This is often claimed to be the naive view most people have of numbers. The term Platonism is used because such a view is seen to parallel Plato's belief in a "World of Ideas," an unchanging ultimate reality that the everyday world can only imperfectly approximate. The two ideas have a meaningful, not just a superficial connection, because Plato probably derived his understanding from the Pythagoreans of ancient Greece, who believed that the world was, quite literally, generated by numbers.

Another form of mathematical realism is based on mathematical empiricism. The view says that we discover mathematical facts as a result of empirical research, just like facts in any of the other sciences. It is not one of the classical three positions advocated in the early 20th century, but primarily arose in the middle of the century. However, an important early proponent of a view like this was John Stuart Mill. Mill's view was widely criticized, because it makes statements like "2 + 2 = 4" come out as uncertain, contingent truths, which we can only learn by observing instances of two pairs coming together and forming a quartet.

Contemporary mathematical empiricism, formulated by Quine and Putnam, is primarily supported by the indispensability argument: mathematics is indispensable to all empirical sciences, and if we want to believe in the reality of the phenomena described by the sciences, we ought also believe in the reality of those entities required for this description. That is, since physics needs to talk about electrons to say why light bulbs behave as they do, then electrons must exist. Since physics needs to talk about numbers in offering any of its explanations, then numbers must exist. In keeping with Quine and Putnam's overall philosophies, this is a naturalistic argument. It argues for the existence of mathematical entities as the best explanation for experience, thus stripping mathematics of some of its distinctness from the other sciences.

Logicism

Gottlob Frege, founder of logicism

Logicism is the thesis that mathematics is reducible to logic, and hence nothing but a part of logic [5]. Logicists hold that mathematics can be known a priori, but suggest that our knowledge of mathematics is just part of our knowledge of logic in general, and is thus analytic, not requiring any special faculty of mathematical intuition. In this view, logic is the proper foundation of mathematics, and all mathematical statements are necessary logical truths.

Gottlob Frege was the founder of logicism. In his seminal Die Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (Basic Laws of Arithmetic) he built up arithmetic from a system of logic with a general principle of comprehension, which he called "Basic Law V" (for concepts F and G, the extension of F equals the extension of G if and only if for all objects a, Fa if and only if Ga), a principle that he took to be acceptable as part of logic.

But Frege's construction was flawed. Russell discovered that Basic Law V is inconsistent (this is Russell's paradox). Frege abandoned his logicist program soon after this, but it was continued by Russell and Whitehead. They attributed the paradox to "vicious circularity" and built up what they called ramified type theory to deal with it. In this system, they were eventually able to build up much of modern mathematics but in an altered, and excessively complex, form (for example, there were different natural numbers in each type, and there were infinitely many types). They also had to make several compromises in order to develop so much of mathematics, such as an "axiom of reducibility." Even Russell said that this axiom did not really belong to logic.

Formalism

Formalism holds that mathematical statements may be thought of as statements about the consequences of certain string manipulation rules. For example, in the "game" of Euclidean geometry (which is seen as consisting of some strings called "axioms," and some "rules of inference" to generate new strings from given ones), one can prove that the Pythagorean theorem holds (that is, you can generate the string corresponding to the Pythagorean theorem). Mathematical truths are not about numbers and sets and triangles and the like—in fact, they aren't "about" anything at all!

Another version of formalism is often known as deductivism. In deductivism, the Pythagorean theorem is not an absolute truth, but a relative one: if you assign meaning to the strings in such a way that the rules of the game become true (i.e., true statements are assigned to the axioms and the rules of inference are truth-preserving), then you have to accept the theorem, or, rather, the interpretation you have given it must be a true statement. The same is held to be true for all other mathematical statements. Thus, formalism need not mean that mathematics is nothing more than a meaningless symbolic game. It is usually hoped that there exists some interpretation in which the rules of the game hold. (Compare this position to structuralism.) But it does allow the working mathematician to continue in his or her work and leave such problems to the philosopher or scientist. Many formalists would say that in practice, the axiom systems to be studied will be suggested by the demands of science or other areas of mathematics.

A major early proponent of formalism was David Hilbert, whose program was intended to be a complete and consistent proof axiomatization of all of mathematics. ("Consistent" here means that no contradictions can be derived from the system.) Hilbert aimed to show the consistency of mathematical systems from the assumption that the "finitary arithmetic" (a subsystem of the usual arithmetic of the positive integers, chosen to be philosophically uncontroversial) was consistent. Hilbert's goals of creating a system of mathematics that is both complete and consistent was dealt a fatal blow by the second of Gödel's incompleteness theorems, which states that sufficiently expressive consistent axiom systems can never prove their own consistency. Since any such axiom system would contain the finitary arithmetic as a subsystem, Gödel's theorem implied that it would be impossible to prove the system's consistency relative to that (since it would then prove its own consistency, which Gödel had shown was impossible). Thus, in order to show that any axiomatic system of mathematics is in fact consistent, one needs to first assume the consistency of a system of mathematics that is in a sense stronger than the system to be proven consistent.

Intuitionism and constructivism

In mathematics, intuitionism is a program of methodological reform whose motto is that "there are no non-experienced mathematical truths" (L.E.J. Brouwer). From this springboard, intuitionists seek to reconstruct what they consider to be the corrigible portion of mathematics in accordance with Kantian concepts of being, becoming, intuition, and knowledge. Brouwer, the founder of the movement, held that mathematical objects arise from the a priori forms of the volitions that inform the perception of empirical objects. (CDP, 542)

Leopold Kronecker said: "The natural numbers come from God, everything else is man's work." A major force behind Intuitionism was L.E.J. Brouwer]], who rejected the usefulness of formalized logic of any sort for mathematics. His student Arend Heyting, postulated an intuitionistic logic, different from the classical Aristotelian logic; this logic does not contain the law of the excluded middle and therefore frowns upon proofs by contradiction. The axiom of choice is also rejected in most intuitionistic set theories, though in some versions it is accepted. Important work was later done by Errett Bishop, who managed to prove versions of the most important theorems in real analysis within this framework.

In intuitionism, the term "explicit construction" is not cleanly defined, and that has led to criticisms. Attempts have been made to use the concepts of Turing machine or computable function to fill this gap, leading to the claim that only questions regarding the behavior of finite algorithms are meaningful and should be investigated in mathematics. This has led to the study of the computable numbers, first introduced by Alan Turing. Not surprisingly, then, this approach to mathematics is sometimes associated with theoretical computer science.

Like intuitionism, constructivism involves the regulative principle that only mathematical entities which can be explicitly constructed in a certain sense should be admitted to mathematical discourse. In this view, mathematics is an exercise of the human intuition, not a game played with meaningless symbols. Instead, it is about entities that we can create directly through mental activity. In addition, some adherents of these schools reject non-constructive proofs, such as a proof by contradiction.

Fictionalism

Fictionalism was introduced in 1980 when Hartry Field published Science Without Numbers, which rejected and in fact reversed Quine's indispensability argument. Where Quine suggested that mathematics was indispensable for our best scientific theories, and therefore should be accepted as a body of truths talking about independently existing entities, Field suggested that mathematics was dispensable, and therefore should be considered as a body of falsehoods not talking about anything real. He did this by giving a complete axiomatization of Newtonian mechanics that didn't reference numbers or functions at all. He started with the "betweenness" axioms of Hilbert geometry to characterize space without coordinatizing it, and then added extra relations between points to do the work formerly done by vector fields. Hilbert's geometry is mathematical, because it talks about abstract points, but in Field's theory, these points are the concrete points of physical space, so no special mathematical objects at all are needed.

Having shown how to do science without using mathematics, he proceeded to rehabilitate mathematics as a kind of useful fiction. He showed that mathematical physics is a conservative extension of his non-mathematical physics (that is, every physical fact provable in mathematical physics is already provable from his system), so that the mathematics is a reliable process whose physical applications are all true, even though its own statements are false. Thus, when doing mathematics, we can see ourselves as telling a sort of story, talking as if numbers existed. For Field, a statement like "2+2=4" is just as false as "Sherlock Holmes lived at 22b Baker Street" - but both are true according to the relevant fictions.

Embodied mind theories

Embodied mind theories hold that mathematical thought is a natural outgrowth of the human cognitive apparatus which finds itself in our physical universe. For example, the abstract concept of number springs from the experience of counting discrete objects. It is held that mathematics is not universal and does not exist in any real sense, other than in human brains. Humans construct, but do not discover, mathematics.

With this view, the physical universe can thus be seen as the ultimate foundation of mathematics: it guided the evolution of the brain and later determined which questions this brain would find worthy of investigation. However, the human mind has no special claim on reality or approaches to it built out of math. If such constructs as Euler's identity are true then they are true as a map of the human mind and cognition.

Embodied mind theorists thus explain the effectiveness of mathematics—mathematics was constructed by the brain in order to be effective in this universe.

Social constructivism or social realism

Social constructivism or social realism theories see mathematics primarily as a social construct, as a product of culture, subject to correction and change. Like the other sciences, mathematics is viewed as an empirical endeavor whose results are constantly evaluated and may be discarded. However, while on an empiricist view the evaluation is some sort of comparison with 'reality', social constructivists emphasize that the direction of mathematical research is dictated by the fashions of the social group performing it or by the needs of the society financing it. However, although such external forces may change the direction of some mathematical research, there are strong internal constraints- the mathematical traditions, methods, problems, meanings and values into which mathematicians are enculturated- that work to conserve the historically defined discipline.

This runs counter to the traditional beliefs of working mathematicians that mathematics is somehow pure or objective. But social constructivists argue that mathematics is in fact grounded by much uncertainty: as mathematical practice evolves, the status of previous mathematics is cast into doubt, and is corrected to the degree it is required or desired by the current mathematical community. This can be seen in the development of analysis from reexamination of the calculus of Leibniz and Newton. They argue further that finished mathematics is often accorded too much status, and folk mathematics not enough, due to an over-emphasis on axiomatic proof and peer review as practices.

Aesthetics

Many practising mathematicians have been drawn to their subject because of a sense of beauty they perceive in it. One sometimes hears the sentiment that mathematicians would like to leave philosophy to the philosophers and get back to mathematics- where, presumably, the beauty lies.

In his work on the divine proportion, H. E. Huntley relates the feeling of reading and understanding someone else's proof of a theorem of mathematics to that of a viewer of a masterpiece of art - the reader of a proof has a similar sense of exhilaration at understanding as the original author of the proof, much as, he argues, the viewer of a masterpiece has a sense of exhilaration similar to the original painter or sculptor. Indeed, one can study mathematical and scientific writings as literature.

Philip Davis and Reuben Hersh have commented that the sense of mathematical beauty is universal amongst practicing mathematicians. By way of example, they provide two proofs of the irrationality of the √2. The first is the traditional proof by contradiction, ascribed to Euclid; the second is a more direct proof involving the fundamental theorem of arithmetic that, they argue, gets to the heart of the issue. Davis and Hersh argue that mathematicians find the second proof more aesthetically appealing because it gets closer to the nature of the problem.

Paul Erdős was well-known for his notion of a hypothetical "Book" containing the most elegant or beautiful mathematical proofs. Gregory Chaitin rejected Erdős's book. By way of example, he provided three separate proofs of the infinitude of primes. The first was Euclid's, the second was based on the Euler zeta function, and the third was Chaitin's own, derived from algorithmic information theory. Chaitin then argued that each one was as beautiful as the others, because all three reveal different aspects of the same problem.

Philosophers have sometimes criticized mathematicians' sense of beauty or elegance as being, at best, vaguely stated. By the same token, however, philosophers of mathematics have sought to characterize what makes one proof more desirable than another when both are logically sound.

Another aspect of aesthetics concerning mathematics is mathematicians' views towards the possible uses of mathematics for purposes deemed unethical or inappropriate. The best-known exposition of this view occurs in G.H. Hardy's book A Mathematician's Apology, in which Hardy argues that pure mathematics is superior in beauty to applied mathematics precisely because it cannot be used for war and similar ends. Some later mathematicians have characterized Hardy's views as mildly dated, with the applicability of number theory to modern-day cryptography. While this would force Hardy to change his primary example if he were writing today, many practicing mathematicians still subscribe to Hardy's general sentiments.

See also

Related topics

  • Axiomatic set theory
  • Axiomatic system
  • Category theory
  • Formal language
  • Formal system
  • Foundations of mathematics
  • Golden ratio
  • History of mathematics
  • Intuitionistic logic
  • Logic

  • Mathematical beauty
  • Mathematical constructivism
  • Mathematical logic
  • Mathematical proof
  • Metamathematics
  • Model theory
  • Naive set theory
  • Non-standard analysis
  • Philosophy of language
  • Philosophy of science

  • Philosophy of probability
  • Proof theory
  • Rule of inference
  • Science studies
  • Scientific method
  • Set theory
  • Truth
  • The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences

Notes

  1. For example, when Edward Maziars proposes in a 1969 book review "to distinguish philosophical mathematics (which is primarily a specialized task for a mathematician) from mathematical philosophy (which ordinarily may be the philosopher's metier)," he uses the term mathematical philosophy as being synonymous with philosophy of mathematics. Edward A. Maziars, "Problems in the Philosophy of Mathematics." (Book Review) Philosophy of Science 36 (3)(1969): 325)
  2. S.C. Kleene. Introduction to Metamathematics. (New York: Van Nostrand, 1952), 55
  3. Saunders Mac Lane. Categories for the Working Mathematician, second ed. (Graduate Texts in Mathematics) (New York: Springer-Verlag, 1998)
  4. Hilary Putnam, "Mathematics Without Foundations." Journal of Philosophy 64 (1): 169–170
  5. Rudolf Carnap, "Die logizistische Grundlegung der Mathematik" Erkenntnis 2: 91–121. Republished, "The Logicist Foundations of Mathematics." E. Putnam and G.J. Massey (trans.) Benacerraf and Putnam, 1931/1883, 41

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Aristotle. "Prior Analytics." Hugh Tredennick (trans.), 181–531 in Aristotle, Vol. 1. Loeb Classical Library, London, UK: William Heinemann, 1938.
  • Audi, Robert. The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995. ISBN 0521402247
  • Benacerraf, Paul; Hilary Putnam. Philosophy of Mathematics, Selected Readings, second ed. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice–Hall, [1964]. 1983.
  • Berkeley, George. The Analyst; or, a Discourse Addressed to an Infidel Mathematician. Wherein It is examined whether the Object, Principles, and Inferences of the modern Analysis are more distinctly conceived, or more evidently deduced, than Religious Mysteries and Points of Faith. London & Dublin: Online text, David R. Wilkins (ed.). Retrieved July 10, 2007.
  • Bourbaki, N. Elements of the History of Mathematics. Berlin; New York: Springer-Verlag, 1994. ISBN 0387193766
  • Carnap, Rudolf. "Die logizistische Grundlegung der Mathematik" Erkenntnis 2: 91–121. Republished, "The Logicist Foundations of Mathematics." E. Putnam and G.J. Massey (trans.) Benacerraf and Putnam, [1964] 1983, 41–52
  • Chandrasekhar, Subrahmanyan. Truth and Beauty. Aesthetics and Motivations in Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987. ISBN 0226100863
  • Field, Hartry. Science Without Numbers: A Defence of Nominalism. Princeton Univ. Press, 1980. ISBN 0691072604
  • Frege, Gottlob. The Basic Laws of Arithmetic, translated and edited by Montgomery Furth. Berkeley: University of California Press, [1965] 1982. ISBN 0520047613
  • Hadamard, Jacques. The Psychology of Invention in the Mathematical Field. New York: Dover, 1954. ISBN 0486201074
  • Hardy, G. H. and C. P. Snow. A Mathematician's Apology. London: Cambridge U.P., 1967.
  • Hart, W.D. The Philosophy of Mathematics. (Oxford Readings in Philosophy) Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press, 1996. ISBN 0198751192
  • Hendricks, Vincent F. and Hannes Leitgeb (eds.) Philosophy of Mathematics: 5 Questions. New York: Automatic Press, 2006. ISBN 8799101351
  • Huntley, H.E. The Divine Proportion: A Study in Mathematical Beauty. New York: Dover Publications, 1970. ISBN 0486222543
  • Kleene, S.C. Introduction to Metamathematics. New York: Van Nostrand, 1952.
  • Klein, Jacob. Greek Mathematical Thought and the Origin of Algebra. New York: Dover Publ.; Toronto, Ont.: General Publ. Co.; London : Constable, 1992. ISBN 0486272893 ISBN 9780486272894
  • Kline, Morris (1959), Mathematics and the Physical World, Thomas Y. Crowell Company, New York, NY, 1959. Reprinted, Mineola, NY: Dover Publications, 1981.
  • Kline, Morris. Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times. New York: Oxford University Press, 1972. ISBN 0195014960
  • König, Julius (Gyula). "Über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre und das Kontinuumproblem." Mathematische Annalen 61: 156–160. Reprinted, "On the Foundations of Set Theory and the Continuum Problem," Stefan Bauer-Mengelberg (trans.), 145–149 in Jean van Heijenoort (ed.), 1967.
  • Leibniz; G. H. R. Parkinson. Logical Papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2005. ISBN 0198243065
  • Mac Lane, Saunders. Categories for the Working Mathematician, second ed. (Graduate Texts in Mathematics) New York: Springer-Verlag, [1971] 1998. ISBN 0387984038
  • Maddy, Penelope. Realism in Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Prress, 1990. ISBN 0198244525
  • Maddy, Penelope. Naturalism in Mathematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press, 1997. ISBN 0198235739
  • Maziarz, Edward A., and Thomas Greenwood. Greek Mathematical Philosophy. New York: Ungar, 1968.
  • Peirce, Benjamin. Linear Associative Algebra. New York: Van Nostrand, 1882. § 1. See American Journal of Mathematics 4 (1881).
  • Peirce, Charles S.; Charles Hartshorne; Paul Weiss; Arthur W Burks. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1931–1935, 1958.
  • Plato. The Republic, Volume 1, Paul Shorey (trans.), 1–535 in Plato, Volume 5. Loeb Classical Library, London, UK: William Heinemann, 1930.
  • Plato. The Republic, Volume 2 Paul Shorey (trans.), 1–521 in Plato, Volume 6. Loeb Classical Library, London, UK: William Heinemann, 1935.
  • Putnam, Hilary. "Mathematics Without Foundations." Journal of Philosophy 64(1): 5–22. Reprinted, pp. 168–184 in W.D. Hart (ed.), The Philosophy of Mathematics. 1996.
  • Robinson, Gilbert de B. The Foundations of Geometry. Toronto: Univ. of Toronto Press, 1959. ISBN 0802011039
  • Russell, Bertrand. Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy. London: G. Allen & Unwin; New York, The Macmillan Co., 1919.
  • Smullyan, Raymond M. Recursion Theory for Metamathematics. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993. ISBN 019508232X
  • Strohmeier, John; Peter Westbrook. Divine Harmony, The Life and Teachings of Pythagoras. Berkeley, CA: Berkeley Hills Books, 1999. ISBN 0965377458
  • Styazhkin, N.I. History of Mathematical Logic from Leibniz to Peano. Cambridge, MA: M.I.T. Press, 1969. ISBN 0262190575
  • Tait, W.W. "Truth and Proof: The Platonism of Mathematics" Synthese 69 (1986): 341–370. Reprinted, in W.D. Hart (ed., 1996), 142–167
  • Tarski, A. Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics: Papers from 1923 to 1938. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1956.
  • Tymoczko, Thomas. New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics. Boston: Birkhäuser, 1986. ISBN 0817631631
  • Stanislaw M Ulam; A. R. Bednarek; Francoise Ulam. Analogies Between Analogies: The Mathematical Reports of S.M. Ulam and His Los Alamos Collaborators. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990. ISBN 0520052900
  • Van Heijenoort, Jean. From Frege To Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1967.
  • Wigner, Eugene. "The Unreasonable Effectiveness of Mathematics in the Natural Sciences." Communications in Pure and Applied Mathematics 13.

External links

All links retrieved November 23, 2022.

General Philosophy Sources


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.