Difference between revisions of "Syadvada" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 153: Line 153:
  
 
*{{cite book | last =Jacobi | first =Hermann | editor =(ed.) Max Müller | title =Jaina Sutras, Part II : Sūtrakrtanga | publisher =The Clarendon Press | date =1895 | location =Oxford | url =http://www.sacred-texts.com/jai/sbe45/index.htm | series =Sacred Books of the East, Vol. 45}}  
 
*{{cite book | last =Jacobi | first =Hermann | editor =(ed.) Max Müller | title =Jaina Sutras, Part II : Sūtrakrtanga | publisher =The Clarendon Press | date =1895 | location =Oxford | url =http://www.sacred-texts.com/jai/sbe45/index.htm | series =Sacred Books of the East, Vol. 45}}  
 
*{{cite book | last =Jain | first =J. P. | title =The Art and Science of Self Realisation: Purusathasiddhiupaya of Ācārya Amrtacandra | publisher =Radiant Publishers | date =2006 | location =Delhi | language =Sanskrit-English }}
 
  
 
*{{cite book | last =Jaini | first =Padmanabh | title =The Jaina Path of Purification | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass | date =1998 | location =New Delhi | isbn =81-208-1578-5 }}
 
*{{cite book | last =Jaini | first =Padmanabh | title =The Jaina Path of Purification | publisher =Motilal Banarsidass | date =1998 | location =New Delhi | isbn =81-208-1578-5 }}

Revision as of 17:58, 17 August 2008

Mahavira employed Anekanta extensively to explain the Jain philosophical concepts

Syādvāda (Devanagari: स्यादवाद) is the Doctrine of Postulation of Jainism. In other words, Syādvāda provides the body of teachings or instruction which one uses to derive a postulate or axiom. The starting assumption or postulate is given as saptabhanginaya, from which other statements are logically derived. By using saptabhanginaya the theory of relativity encompasses the truths about one system or thought which are the same in one system as in another system in uniform motion relative to it. It is henceforth impossible to determine the truth of a system within its own thought structure, and such development or furtherance of various claims of truth can be observed only in relation to other systems in uniform motion resulting in a qualified prediction as shown in the theory of Manifold Predictions.[1] Therefore each truth is valid within its one system, various truths are synthesized and are mutually exclusive. Amongst several truths about a particular thing, one or the other or both may in fact be valid.

Etymology

The etymology of syadvada comes from two roots. Syat means "may be" Whereas vada means "assertion". Placed together syādvāda becomes the assertion of what may be, the assertion of possibilities.[2]

Relativity in Jain Philosophy

According to McEvilley, the Jain theory of knowledge is not a phenomenalism but a realistic correspondence view.[3] The Jain doctrine lays a strong emphasis on samyaktva, that is, rationality and logic.[4] Jains suggest that the ultimate principle should always be logical and no principle can be devoid of logic or reason.[4] Thus one finds in the Jain texts, deliberative exhortations on any subject in all its facts.[5] In the process, the Jains came out with three doctrines of relativity[6] used for logic and reasoning –

  • Anekāntavāda - the theory of relative pluralism or manifoldness;
  • Syādvāda – the theory of conditioned predication and;
  • Nayavāda – The theory of partial standpoints.

These Jain philosophical concepts made very significant contributions to the ancient Indian philosophy, especially in the areas of skepticism and relativity.[3]

Syādavāda

Syādvāda is the theory of conditioned predication which provides an expression to anekānta by recommending that epithet Syād be attached to every expression.[7] Syādvāda is not only an extension of Anekānta ontology, but a separate system of logic capable of standing on its own force. The Sanskrit etymological root of the term Syād is "perhaps" or "maybe", but in context of syādvāda, it means "in some ways" or "from a perspective." As reality is complex, no single proposition can express the nature of reality fully. Thus the term "syāt" should be prefixed before each proposition giving it a conditional point of view and thus removing any dogmatism in the statement.[8] Since it ensures that each statement is expressed from seven different conditional and relative view points or propositions, it is know as theory of conditioned predication. These seven propositions also known as saptabhangi are:[9]

  1. Syād-asti – "in some ways it is",
  2. syād-nāsti - "in some ways it is not",
  3. syād-asti-nāsti - "in some ways it is and it is not",
  4. syād-asti-avaktavyaḥ - "in some ways it is and it is indescribable",
  5. syād-nāsti-avaktavyaḥ - "in some ways it is not and it is indescribable",
  6. syād-asti-nāsti-avaktavyaḥ - "in some ways it is, it is not and it is indescribable",
  7. syād-avaktavyaḥ- "in some ways it is indescribable"

Another way of expressing this sevenfold predication in English is as follows:

  1. syadasti = Perhaps or maybe, ... it is.
  2. syatnasti = Perhaps or maybe, ... it is not.
  3. syadasti nasti ca = Perhaps or maybe, ... it is, it is not.
  4. syadavaktavyah = Perhaps or maybe, ... it is indeterminate or indescribable.
  5. syadasti ca avaktavya sca = Perhaps or maybe, ... it is and also indeterminate or indescribable.
  6. syatnasti ca avaktavyasca = Perhaps or maybe, ... it is not and also indeterminate or indescribable.
  7. syadasti nasti ca avaktav-yasca = Perhaps or maybe, ... it is and it is not and also indeterminate or indescribable.[2]

Each of these seven propositions examines the complex and multifaceted reality from a relative point of view of time, space, substance and mode.[9] To ignore the complexity of the objects is to commit the fallacy of dogmatism.

Nayavāda

Nayavāda is the theory of partial stand-points or view-points. Nayavāda is a compound to two Sanskrit words – Naya "partial view point" and vāda "school of thought or debate".[10] Nayavāda is used to arrive at a certain inference from a point of view. An object has infinite aspects to it; but in practice when we describe an object, we speak of only relevant aspects, ignoring the other irrelevant aspects.[10] This does not deny the other attributes, qualities, modes and other aspects; they are currently not relevant from a particular perspective. For instance, when we talk of a "Blue BMW" we are simply considering the color and make of a car; but our statement does not imply that the car is devoid of other attributes like engine type, cylinders, speed, price and like. This particular view point is called "naya" or a partial view-point. As a type of critical philosophy, the nayavāda holds that all philosophical disputes arise out of confusion of stand points, and the standpoints we adopt are, though we may not realize it, "the outcome of purposes that we may pursue".[11] While operating within the limits of language and seeing the complex nature of reality, Māhavīra used the language of nayas. Naya, being a partial expression of truth, enables us to comprehend reality part by part.[12]

Anekantavada

Anekāntavāda (Devanagari: अनेकान्तवाद), meaning "non-absolutism", is one of the basic principles of Jainism that encourages acceptance of relativism and pluralism. According to this doctrine, truth and reality are perceived differently from different points of view, and no single point of view is the complete truth.[13] [14]

The word anekāntavāda is a compound of two Sanskrit words: anekānta "manifoldness" and vāda "school of thought".[15] The term anekānta consists of the Sanskrit negative prefix an, the number one eka and the word for "attribute", anta — "not of solitary attribute".[15]

Jain doctrine states that objects have infinite modes of existence and qualities so they cannot be completely grasped in all aspects and manifestations by finite human perception. Only the Kevalins - the omniscient beings - can comprehend objects in all aspects and manifestations; others are capable of only partial knowledge.[16] Consequently, no specific human view can claim to represent the absolute truth.

Anekāntavāda is literally the doctrine of "non-onesidedness" or "manifoldness"; it is often translated as "non-absolutism". As opposed to it, ekānta (eka+anta "solitary attribute") is one-sidedness. Jains compare all attempts to proclaim absolute truth with adhgajanyāyah or the "maxim of the blind men and elephant". In this story, one man felt the trunk, another the ears and another the tail. All the blind men claimed to explain the true appearance of the elephant, but could only partly succeed, due to their narrow perspectives.[17]

Anekāntavāda encourages its adherents to consider the views and beliefs of their rivals and opposing parties. Proponents of anekantvāda apply this principle to religion and philosophy, reminding themselves that any religion or philosophy, even Jainism, which clings too dogmatically to its own tenets, is committing an error based on its limited point of view.[18] In this application, anekantvāda resembles the Western principles of cultural and moral relativism. The principle of anekāntavāda also influenced Mahatma Gandhi's principles of religious tolerance, ahimsa and satyagraha.[19]

The Blind Men and an Elephant

The Jain concepts of Anekantvāda and Syādvāda are often explained with the parable of Blind men and Elephant. It is also known as andhgajanyāyah which is translated as "the maxim of blind (men) and elephant." The following parable (and many of its variants) is used by the Jain authors to explain the multifold nature of truth:

"A group of blind men heard that a strange animal, called an elephant, had been brought to the town, but none of them were aware its shape and form. Out of curiosity, they said: "We must inspect and know it by touch of which we are capable." So, they sought it out, and when they found it they groped about it. In the case of the first one person, whose hand landed on the trunk, said "This being is like a drain pipe." For another one whose hand reached its ear, it seemed like a kind of fan. As for another person, whose hand was upon its leg, said, "I perceive the shape of the elephant to be like a pillar". And in the case of the one who placed his hand upon its back said "Indeed, this elephant is like a throne" Now, each of these presented a true aspect when he related what he had gained from experiencing the elephant. None of them had strayed from the true description of the elephant. Yet they fell short of fathoming the true appearance of the elephant."[17]

Intellectual ahimsā and religious tolerance

The concepts of anekānta and syādvāda allows the Jains to accept the truth in other philosophies from their perspective and thus inculcating a tolerance for other viewpoints. Anekantvāda is non-absolutist and stands firmly against all dogmatisms, even including any assertion that only Jainism is the right religious path.[20] It is thus an intellectual Ahimsā or Ahimsā of mind. [21][22]

Māhavīra encouraged his followers to study and understand the rival traditions as evidenced in Acaranga Sutra[23] :

"Comprehend one philosophical view through the comprehensive study of another one" - 5.113

In Anekantvāda, there is no "battle of ideas", because this is considered to be a form of intellectual himsa or damage, leading quite logically to physical violence and war. In today's world, the limitations of the adversarial, "either with us or against us " form of argument are increasingly apparent leading to political, religious and social conflicts.

Sutrakritanga, the second oldest canon of Jainism, provides a solution by stating[24]:

"Those who praise their own doctrines and ideology and disparage the doctrine of others distort the truth and will be confined to the cycle of birth and death." 1.1.50

This ecumenic and irenic attitude, engendered by Anekānta, allowed modern Jain monks like Vijayadharma suri to declare:

"..He is neither Jain nor Buddhist, Vaisnava nor Saiva, Hindu nor Muslim, but a traveler on the path of peace shown by the supreme soul, the God who is free from passion."[25]

Even the mounting ecological crisis is linked to adversarialism, because it arises from a false division between humanity and "the rest" of nature. The modern judicial systems, democracy, freedom of speech, secularism, all implicitly reflect an attitude of Anekānta. Many authors like Kamala Jain, have advanced that the Jaina tradition with its emphasis on Ahimsā and Anekānta is capable of providing a solution to a host of problems facing the world: Religious intolerance, terrorism, wars, depletion of natural resources, environmental degradation and like.[26]

Influence on Mahatma Gandhi

Gandhi was deeply influenced by Jainism.

Since childhood, Gandhi was exposed to the actual practice of non-violence, non-possession and anekāntavāda. [27] He grew up in an area with a continued Jain population and one of his good friend was a Jain. According to his biographers like Uma Majumdar, Rajmohan Gandhi and Stephen Hay,[19] these early childhood impressions and felt experiences contributed to Gandhi’s character formation and further moral and spiritual development. Mahatma Gandhi, in his writings, attributed his seemingly contradictory positions over a period of time to his learning process, experiments with truth and his belief in anekāntavāda.[28] He proclaimed that the duty of every individual is to determine what is personally true and act on that relative perception of truth. According to Gandhi, while duty bound to act according to his relative truth, a satyagrahi is equally bound to learn from truth held by his opponent. [29] In response to a friends query on religious tolerance, he responded in Journal "Young India - 21 Jan 1926":

"I am an Advaitist and yet I can support Dvaitism (dualism). The world is changing every moment, and is therefore unreal, it has no permanent existence. But though it is constantly changing, it has a something about it which persists and it is therefore to that extent real. I have therefore no objection to calling it real and unreal, and thus being called an Anekāntavadi or a Syādvadi. But my Syādvāda is not the Syādvāda of the learned, it is peculiarly my own. I cannot engage in a debate with them. It has been my experience that I am always true from my point of view, and am often wrong from the point of view of my honest critics. I know that we are both right from our respective points of view. And this knowledge saves me from attributing motives to my opponents or critics. The seven blind men who gave seven different descriptions of the elephant were all right from their respective points of view, and wrong from the point of view of one another, and right and wrong from the point of view of the man who knew the elephant. I very much like this doctrine of the manyness (sic) of reality. It is this doctrine that has taught me to judge a Musulman (sic) from his standpoint and a Christian from his. Formerly I used to resent the ignorance of my opponents. Today I can love them because I am gifted with the eye to see myself as others see me and vice versa. I want to take the whole world in the embrace of my love. My Anekāntavāda is the result of the twin doctrine of Satyagraha and Ahimsa."[30]

Criticisms

The interrelated doctrines of Anekānta and Syādavāda are often criticised on grounds that they engender a degree of hesitancy and uncertainty and may compound problems rather than solve them. It is also pointed out that Jain epistemology gains assertibility for its own doctrine, but at the cost of being unable to deny contradictory doctrines. Furthermore, it is also argued that this doctrine becomes self-defeating when it is argued that if reality is complex and nothing can describe it completely, then this doctrine itself is incomplete and hence an ekantvadi. [31] This criticism seems to have been anticipated by Ācārya Samantabhadra when he says:

"From the point of view of pramana (means of knowledege) it is anekānta (multi-sided), but from a point of view of naya (partial view) it is ekanta (one-sided)."[32]

In its defense, Jains also point out that anekānta manages to reconcile the opposing view points rather than simply refute them and helps in avoidance of one-sided errors and confusion that the ekantvadins tend to make.

File:Adi Shankara recoloured.jpg
Adi Sankarācārya, the Advaita philosopher, 9th Century C.E., criticised the doctrine of anekāntavāda

The doctrine of anekāntavāda had also received criticism from the Vedantists, especially from Adi Sankarācārya. Sankara attempted to refute some of the tenets of Jainism in his commentary on the Brahmasutra (2-2-33 to 36), wherein he shows considerable disdain for the doctrine of Anekantavāda:

"It is impossible that contradictory attributes such as being and non-being should at the same time belong to one and the same thing; just as observation teaches us that a thing cannot be hot and cold at the same moment. The third alternative expressed in the words -they either are such or not such - results in cognition of indefinite nature, which is no more a source of true knowledge than doubt is. Thus the means of knowledge, the object of knowledge, the knowing subject, and the act of knowledge become all alike indefinite. How can his followers act on a doctrine, the matter of which is altogether indeterminate? The result of your efforts is perfect knowledge and is not perfect knowledge. Observation shows that, only when a course of action is known to have a definite result, people set about it without hesitation. Hence a man who proclaims a doctrine of altogether indefinite contents does not deserve to be listened anymore than a drunken or a mad man."[33]

However, Sankara failed to take the real position of Anekānta into account by identifying syādavāda as sansayavāda, that is, "agnosticism" which was once articulated by Sanjaya Belatthiputta.[34] He failed to take into consideration that the affirmation of the existence of an object is in respect to the object itself and its negation is in respect to what the object is not, giving an object positive and negative attributes at the same time without any contradictions.

Another Buddhist logician Dharmakirti ridiculed Anekānta in Pramānavarttikakārika:

"With the differentiation removed, all things have dual nature.
Then, if somebody is implored to eat curd, then why does not eat camel?"[34]

The insinuation is obvious: if curd exists from nature of curd and does not exist from nature of camel, then one is justified in eating camel, as by eating camel, he is merely eating the negation of curd. Ācārya Akalanka, while agreeing that Dharmakirti may be right from a view point, took it upon himself to issue a rejoinder:

"The person, who criticises without understanding the prima facie view, is acting like a jester and not a critic.
The Buddha was born a deer and deer was born as Buddha; but Buddha is adorable and deer is only a food.
Similarly, due to strength of an entity, with its difference and similarities specified, nobody would eat camel if implored to eat curd."[34]

Role in ensuring survival of Jainism

Anekāntavāda played a pivotal role in the survival of Jainism in ancient India during the onslaught from Shaivas, Vaishnavas, Buddhists, Muslims, Christians at various points of time. According to Christopher Key Chapple, Anekāntavāda allowed Jains to survive during the most hostile and unfavourable moments in history.[35] According to John Koller, Anekāntavāda allowed the Jain thinkers to maintain the validity of doctrine, while at the same time respectfully criticize the views of the opponents.[35] Anekāntavāda was effectively used by Ācārya Hemacandra to convert king Kumarapala of Gujarat to Jainism.[36] Certain Brahmins who were jealous of Hemacandras rising popularity with King complained that Hemacandra was a very egoistic person and he did not respect Hindu Gods and refuses to bow to lord Shiva. When called upon to visit Siva temple with the King, Hemacandra readily bowed before the idol of Siva, but by saying:[36]

"I am bowing down only to that god, who has destroyed the passions like attachment (raga) and hatred (dvesa) which are the cause of worldly life, whether he is Brahma, Visnu, or Jina."

At one stroke he ensured that he remained true to tenets of Jainism, namely, a Jain should bow down only to a passionless and detached God (i.e. a Jina) and at the same time managed to please the King. Ultimately, the king became a devoted follower of Hemacandra a great champion of Jainism.[36]

See also

Notes

  1. ELEPHANT AND THE BLIND MEN. Jain Stories. JainWorld.com. Retrieved Retrieved August 9, 2008..
  2. 2.0 2.1 P.C. Mahalanobis, The Indian-Jaina Dialectic of Syadvad in Relation to Probability (I). Retrieved Retrieved August 9, 2008. 
  3. 3.0 3.1 McEvilley, Thomas (2002) p. 335
  4. 4.0 4.1 Duli Chandra Jain (ed.) (1997) p.21
  5. Hughes, Marilynn (2005) P. 590
  6. Griffin, David Ray (2005) p. 145
  7. Chatterjea, Tara (2001) p.77-87
  8. Koller, John M. (July, 2000). Syādvāda as the epistemological key to the Jaina middle way metaphysics of Anekāntavāda. Philosophy East and West. vol. 50 (3): Pp. 400-8.
  9. 9.0 9.1 Grimes, John (1996) p. 312 Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; name "grimes" defined multiple times with different content
  10. 10.0 10.1 Grimes, John (1996) p.202-3
  11. McEvilley, Thomas (2002) p.335-7
  12. Shah, Natubhai (1998) p.80
  13. Dundas (2002) p.231
  14. Koller, John M. (July, 2000) pp.400-7
  15. 15.0 15.1 Grimes, John (1996) p.34
  16. Jaini, Padmanabh (1998) p.91
  17. 17.0 17.1 Hughes, Marilynn (2005) p.590-1 Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; name "hughes" defined multiple times with different content
  18. Huntington, Ronald. Jainism and Ethics. Retrieved Retrieved August 9, 2008..
  19. 19.0 19.1 Hay, Stephen N. (1970) pp.14-23 Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; name "hay" defined multiple times with different content
  20. Huntington, Ronald. Jainism and Ethics. Retrieved Retrieved August 9, 2008..
  21. Rankin, Adian. (2006)
  22. Matilal, p.61
  23. Jacobi, Hermann (1884) 5.113
  24. Jacobi, Hermann (1895) 1.1.50
  25. Dundas (2002) p. 227
  26. Sethia, Tara (2004) p. 113
  27. Majmudar, Uma (2005) p.44
  28. Griffin, David Ray (2005) p. 145
  29. Sonnleitner, Michael (1985). p.14
  30. Gandhi, Mahatma (1955)
  31. Webb, Mark Owen. The Jain Philosophy. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved Retrieved August 9, 2008..
  32. Pandya, V. (2001) p. 5210
  33. Nakamura, Hajim (1992): 169-70
  34. 34.0 34.1 34.2 Pandya, V. (2001) p. 5209-10 Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; name "Pandya" defined multiple times with different content Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; name "Pandya" defined multiple times with different content
  35. 35.0 35.1 Sethia, Tara (2004) Pp.7-8 Cite error: Invalid <ref> tag; name "tara" defined multiple times with different content
  36. 36.0 36.1 36.2 Hemacandra. Jain World. Retrieved Retrieved August 9, 2008..

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Acarya Siddhasena Divakara. in (ed.) Bhadrankar Vijaya Gani: Vardhamana Dvatrimsika. Jaipur: Prakrit Bharti Academy. 
  • Chatterjea, Tara (2001). Knowledge and Freedom in Indian Philosophy. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books. ISBN 739106929. 
  • Dasgupta, S. N. (1932). History of Indian Philosophy, Vol. II. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 
  • Duli Chandra Jain (ed.) (1997). Studies in Jainism: Reader 2. New York: Jain Study Circle Inc.. ISBN 0-9626105-2-6. 
  • Dundas, Paul and John Hinnels ed. (2002). The Jains. London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-26606-8. 
  • Gandhi, Mahatma (1955). in (ed.) Jitendra Thakorbhai Desai, (comp.) R.K. Prabhu: Truth is God: Gleanings from the Writings of Mahatma Gandhi Bearing on God, God-Realization and the Godly Way. Ahmedabad: Navajivan Publishing House. 
  • Griffin, David Ray (2005). Deep Religious Pluralism. Louisville, KY: Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 066422914X. 
  • Grimes, John (1996). A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English. New York: SUNY Press. ISBN 0791430677. 
  • Hay, Stephen N. (1970). "Jain Influences on Gandhi's Early Thought", in (ed.) Sibnarayan Ray: Gandhi India and the World. Bombay: Nachiketa Publishers, pp. 14-23. 
  • Hughes, Marilynn (2005). The voice of Prophets, Volume 2 of 12. Morrisville, North Carolina: Lulu.com. ISBN 1411651219. 
  • Humphreys, Christmas (1969). The Buddhist Way of Life. London: Unwin Books. 
  • Jaini, Padmanabh (1998). The Jaina Path of Purification. New Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 81-208-1578-5. 
  • Majmudar, Uma (2005). Gandhi's Pilgrimage of Faith: From Darkness to Light. New york: SUNY Press. ISBN 0791464059. 
  • Matilal, B.K. (1981). The Central Philosophy of Jainism (Anekantavada), L.D. Series 79. Ahmedabad. 
  • McEvilley, Thomas (2002). The Shape of Ancient Thought: Comparative Studies in Greek and Indian Philosophies. New York: Allworth Communications , Inc. ISBN 1581152035. 
  • Nakamura, Hajim (1992). Comparative History of Ideas. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Pub. ISBN 812081004X. 
  • Pandya, V. (2001). "Refutation of Jaina Darsana by Sankaracarya", in (ed.) Nagendra Kr. Singh: Encyclopedia of Jainism. New Delhi: Anmol Publications. ISBN 8126106913. 
  • Sethia, Tara (2004). Ahimsā, Anekānta, and Jaininsm. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass Publ. ISBN 81-208-2036-3. 
  • Shah, Natubhai (1998). Jainism: The World of Conquerors, Volume I and II. Sussex: Sussex Academy Press. ISBN 1898723303. 
  • Sharma, Arvind (2001). Jaina Perspective on the Philosophy of Religion. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 8120817605. 
  • Sonnleitner, Michael W (1985). Gandhian Nonviolence: Levels of Satyagraha. India: Abhinav publications. ISBN 8170172055. 
  • Webb, Mark Owen. The Jain Philosophy. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2008-03-18.

External links

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.