Sartre, Jean-Paul

From New World Encyclopedia
m (Sartre, Jean-Paul moved to Jean-Paul Sartre)
 
(32 intermediate revisions by 11 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{epname}}
+
{{Edboard}}{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Copyedited}}
'''Jean-Paul Charles Aymard Sartre''' ([[June 21]], [[1905]] – [[April 15]], [[1980]]) was a [[France|French]] [[existentialism|existentialist]] [[philosopher]], [[playwright|dramatist]], [[novelist]] and [[literary criticism|critic]].
+
{{epname|Sartre, Jean-Paul}}
  
==Early life and thought==
+
[[Image:Sartre 1967 crop.jpg|300px|thumb|right|Jean-Paul Sartre]]
Sartre was born in [[Paris]] to parents Jean-Baptiste Sartre, an [[naval officer|officer]] of the [[French Navy]], and Anne-Marie Schweitzer, cousin of [[Albert Schweitzer]]. When he was 15 months old, his father died of a [[fever]] and Anne-Marie raised him with help from her father, Charles Schweitzer, who taught Sartre [[mathematics]] and introduced him to [[Classics|classical literature]] at an early age.
 
  
As a teenager in the 1920s, Sartre became attracted to [[philosophy]] upon reading [[Henri Bergson]]'s ''Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness''. He studied in Paris at the elite [[École Normale Supérieure]], an [[higher education|institution of higher education]] which has served as the [[alma mater]] for multiple prominent French thinkers and intellectuals. Sartre was influenced by many aspects of Western philosophy, absorbing ideas from [[Immanuel Kant]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]] and [[Martin Heidegger]].
+
'''Jean-Paul Sartre''' (June 21, 1905 – April 15, 1980) was a French philosopher, playwright, novelist, and literary critic. His most famous writings include the novel ''La nausée'' ''(Nausea),'' (1938), his major philosophical work ''L'être et le néant'' ''(Being and Nothingness)'' (1943), and the play ''Huis-clos'' ''(No Exit)'' (1944). Throughout these writings Sartre describes and analyzes our most basic existential experiences, which reveal the fundamental human condition in our relation to the world and others. Although he is often associated with other existential thinkers of the twentieth century ([[Martin Heidegger]], [[Karl Jaspers]], [[Gabriel Marcel]]) Sartre, unlike these other philosophers, strongly embraced the term “[[existentialism]]and so today his name, more than these others, is equated with the school of existentialism.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
As with other philosophers of existence, Sartre held that ‘existence precedes essence’. For Sartre this meant that all existing things in the material universe are in themselves meaningless. Only through our consciousness of them do things take on value, which means that it is we who create meaning. Sartre links consciousness and our experience of anguish to freedom. It is through accepting responsibility for our [[freedom]], and the anguish that accompanies it, that we can become authentic human beings. Throughout his life Sartre was very politically active, and although he never officially joined the Communist Party, he espoused [[Marxism|Marxist]] ideas. In 1964 Sartre won the [[Nobel Prize]] in Literature, but he declined the award stating that he did not align himself with institutions.
  
In [[1929]] at the École Normale, he met fellow student [[Simone de Beauvoir]], later to become a noted thinker, writer, and [[feminism|feminist]]. The two, it is documented, became inseparable and lifelong companions, initiating a romantic relationship, though one that was not [[monogamy|monogamous]].
+
==Sartre’s Life ==
 +
===Early years===
 +
Sartre was born in Paris to parents Jean-Baptiste Sartre, an officer of the French Navy, and Anne-Marie Schweitzer, cousin of [[Albert Schweitzer]]. When he was 15 months old, his father died of a fever. Anne-Marie raised him with help from her father, Charles Schweitzer, who taught Sartre mathematics and introduced him to classical literature at an early age. As a teenager in the 1920s, Sartre became attracted to philosophy upon reading [[Henri Bergson]]'s ''Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness.'' He studied in Paris at the elite École Normale Supérieure. Sartre was influenced by many aspects of Western philosophy, particularly the ideas of the great German philosophers [[Immanuel Kant]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]], [[Friedrich Nietzsche]], and [[Martin Heidegger]].
  
Together, Sartre and Beauvoir challenged the [[culture|cultural]] and [[society|social]] assumptions and expectations of their upbringings, which they considered [[bourgeois]], in both [[lifestyle]] and [[philosophy|thought]]. The conflict between oppressive, spiritually-destructive [[conformity]] (''mauvaise foi'', literally, "[[Sartre and bad faith|bad faith]]") and an ''"[[authentic]]" state of "being"'' became the dominant theme of Sartre's work, a theme embodied in his principal philosophical work ''L'Être et le Néant'' (''[[Being and Nothingness]]'') ([[1944]]).
+
In 1929 at the École Normale, Sartre met fellow student [[Simone de Beauvoir]], who later became a noted thinker, writer, and [[feminism|feminist]]. From the start the two were inseparable and throughout their lives they continued a romantic relationship, though one that was self-consciously anti-monogamous. Together Sartre and Beauvoir challenged many cultural and social assumptions, which they considered to be “bourgeois,” both in practice and in thought. The conflict between oppressive conformity to other people or to established institutions and an authentic self-determination based on free choice would become a dominant theme in Sartre's later work.
  
Sartre's most well-known introduction to his philosophy is his work ''[[Existentialism is a Humanism]]'' ([[1946]]).  In this work, he defends [[existentialism]] against its [[critic|detractor]]s, which ultimately results in a somewhat incomplete description of his ideas.  The work has been considered a popular, if over-simplifying, point of entry for those seeking to learn more about Sartre's ideas but lacking the background in philosophy necessary to fully absorb his longer work ''Being and Nothingness''.
+
Sartre graduated from the École Normale in 1929 with a doctorate in philosophy and from 1929 to 1931 he served as a conscript in the French Army. Afterward he taught as a junior lecturer at the Lycée du Havre and began to work on his writing. Throughout the late 1930s he published his first works, such as the philosophical essays: ''Imagination: A Psychological Critique'' (1936) and ''The Transcendence of the Ego'' (1937), and the literary works: ''Nausea'' (1938) and ''The Wall'' (1939).
  
He graduated from the École Normale Supérieure in [[1929]] with a [[doctorate]] in [[philosophy]] and served as a [[conscript]] in the [[French Army]] from [[1929]] to [[1931]].
+
=== Sartre and World War II ===
  
It is reported that in 1935 Sartre tried the [[psychedelic drug]] [[mescaline]], but had a bad [[reaction]], and suffered from troublesome [[hallucination|hallucinatory effects]] for a year afterwards.
+
In 1939 Sartre was drafted into the French army, where he served as a meteorologist. German troops captured him in 1940 in Padoux and he spent nine months in prison; later he was sent to Nancy and finally to Stalag 12D, in Trier, where he wrote his first theater piece: "Barionà, fils du tonnerre." Due to poor health he was released from prison in April of 1941. Given civilian status, he then escaped to Paris where he became involved in the [[French Resistance]] and participated in the founding of the resistance group Socialisme et Liberté. It was while engaged in the resistance that he met [[Albert Camus]], a philosopher and writer who held similar existential and political convictions. The two remained friends until Camus’ move away from communism, which created a schism that would eventually divide them in 1951 following the publication of Camus' ''The Rebel.'' Also during the war Sartre published his most famous and definitive philosophical work L'être et le néant (Being and Nothingness) (1943). When the war ended he established ''Les Temps Modernes'' ''(Modern Times),'' a monthly literary and political review, and started writing full-time. It was from out of his war experiences that he would create his great trilogy of novels, ''Les Chemins de la Liberté'' ''(The Roads to Freedom)'' (1945-1949).
  
{{French literature (small)}}
+
=== Sartre and communism===
 +
While the first period of Sartre's intellectual career is better defined by the philosophical ideas presented in Being and Nothingness, the second period can be viewed more in light of his political engagement. His 1948 work ''Les Mains Sales'' ''(Dirty Hands)'' explores the problem of being both an intellectual and a political activist. Although Sartre never officially joined the French Communist party, he was committed to communist ideas and took a prominent role in the struggle against French colonialism in Algeria. Aware of the abuses of communist Stalinism, however, Sartre spent much of the remainder of his life trying to reconcile his existentialist ideas about self-determination with communist principles, which held that socio-economic forces beyond our immediate, individual control play an instrumental role in shaping our lives. His major defining work of the later period, the ''Critique de la raison dialectique'' ''(Critique of Dialectical Reason)'' appeared in 1960.
  
==''La Nausée'' and Existentialism==
+
Sartre's emphasis on the humanist values in the early work of Marx led to a famous dispute with the leading Communist intellectual in France during the 1960s, [[Louis Althusser]]. Althusser redefined Marx's work by dividing it into an early pre-Marxist period, which espoused essentialist generalizations about “Mankind,” and a more mature, scientific and authentically Marxist period, which emphasized the [[dialectical materialism]] over essentialist [[humanism]]. Sartre took issue with this interpretation, and it spurred the debate between the two thinkers. Although some say this was the only public debate Sartre ever lost, it remains a disputed issue within various philosophical circles in France.  
As a junior lecturer at the Lycée du Havre in [[1938]], Sartre wrote the novel ''[[Nausea (book)|La Nausée]]'' (''Nausea'') which serves in some ways as a [[manifesto]] of [[existentialism]] and remains one of his most famous books.  Taking a page from the [[Husserl|German]] [[phenomenology|phenomenological]] movement, he believed that our ideas are the product of experiences of real-life situations, and that novels and plays describing such fundamental experiences have as much value as do discursive essays for the elaboration of philosophical theories. With this mandate, the novel concerns a dejected researcher (Roquentin) in a town similar to [[Le Havre]] who becomes starkly conscious of the fact that inanimate objects and situations remain absolutely indifferent to his existence.   As such, they show themselves to be resistant to whatever significance human consciousness might perceive in them.  This indifference of "things in themselves" (closely linked with the later notion of
 
"being-in-itself" in his ''[[Being and Nothingness]]'') has the effect of highlighting all the more the freedom Roquentin has to perceive and act in the world; everywhere he looks, he finds situations imbued with meanings which bear the stamp of his existence.  Hence the "nausea" referred to in the title of the book; all that he encounters in his everyday life is suffused with a pervasive, even horrible, taste — specifically, his freedom.  No matter how much he longs for something other or something different, he cannot get away from this harrowing evidence of his engagement with the world.
 
  
The stories in ''Le Mur'' (''[[The Wall (Book)|The Wall]]'') emphasize the arbitrary aspects of the situations people find themselves in and the absurdity of their attempts to deal rationally with them. A whole school of [[theatre of the absurd|absurd]] literature subsequently developed.
+
===Later years===
 +
In 1964, Sartre renounced literature in a witty and sardonic account of the first six years of his life, ''Les mots'' ''(Words).'' The book is an ironic counterblast to [[Marcel Proust]], whose reputation had unexpectedly eclipsed that of [[André Gide]] (who had provided the model of ''literature engagée'' for Sartre's generation). Literature, Sartre concluded, functioned as a bourgeois substitute for real commitment in the world. Also in 1964 Sartre was awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature; he declined the honor, however, stating that he had always refused official honors and didn't wish to align himself with institutions of any sort.  
  
==Sartre and [[World War II]]==
+
Although Sartre had become a ‘household name’ (as did “existentialism” which developed into a popular movement throughout the tumultuous 1960s), he remained a simple man with few possessions. Until the end of his life he stayed actively committed to political causes, such as the student revolution strikes in Paris during the summer of 1968 and opposition to the [[Vietnam War]]. In terms of the latter, he, along with [[Bertrand Russell]] and other intellectuals, organized a tribunal intended to expose U.S. war crimes. Throughout the 1970s Sartre's physical condition deteriorated, partially due to the merciless pace he endured while writing the ''Critique'' as well as the last project of his life, a massive analytical biography of [[Gustave Flaubert]] ''(The Family Idiot),'' both of which remain unfinished. In 1975, when asked how he would like to be remembered, Sartre replied in the following way:
In [[1939]] Sartre was drafted into the French army, where he served as a [[meteorologist]]. [[Germany|German]] troops captured him in [[1940]] in [[Padoux]], and he spent nine months in [[prisoner of war|prison]] — later in [[Nancy]] and finally in [[Stalag]] 12D, [[Trier | Treves]], where he wrote his first theater piece: "[[Barionà, fils du tonnerre]]", a drama concerning [[Christmas]]. Due to poor health (he claimed that his poor eyesight affected his balance) Sartre was released in April [[1941]]. Given civilian status, he then escaped to Paris where he became involved in the [[French Resistance]], and participated in the founding of the resistance group [[Socialisme et Liberté]]. It was while engaged in the resistance that he met [[Albert Camus]], a philosopher and author who held similar beliefs, and remained friends with him until Camus turned away from communism, a schism between them that eventually divided them in 1951, after the publication of Camus' book entitled ''The Rebel''.
+
"I would like people to remember ''Nausea'', my plays ''No Exit'' and ''The Devil and the Good Lord,'' and then my two philosophical works, more particularly the second one, ''Critique of Dialectical Reason.'' Then my essay on Genet, ''Saint Genet''…. If these are remembered, that would be quite an achievement, and I don't ask for more. As a man, if a certain Jean-Paul Sartre is remembered, I would like people to remember the milieu or historical situation in which I lived, … how I lived in it, in terms of all the aspirations which I tried to gather up within myself."
When the war ended Sartre established ''[[Les Temps Modernes]]'' (''Modern Times''), a monthly literary and political [[review]], and started writing full-time as well as continuing his political activism. He would draw on his war experiences for his great trilogy of novels, ''Les Chemins de la Liberté'' (''[[The Roads to Freedom]]'') (1945–1949).
+
Sartre died April 15, 1980 in Paris from an edema of the lung. Sartre lies buried in Cimetière du Montparnasse in Paris. Approximately 50,000 people attended his funeral.
  
==Sartre and Communism==
+
==Existentialism: Philosophical Ideas==
The first period of Sartre's career, defined by ''[[Being and Nothingness]]'' (1943), gave way to a second period as a politically engaged activist and intellectual. His 1948 work ''[[Les Mains Sales]]'' (''[[Dirty Hands]]'') in particular explored the problem of being both an intellectual at the same time as becoming "engaged" politically. He embraced [[Communism | communism]], though he never officially joined the [[French Communist Party | Communist party]], and took a prominent role in the struggle against French [[colonialism]] in [[Algeria]]. He became perhaps the most eminent supporter of the [[Algerian war of independence|Algerian war of liberation]]. He had an Algerian mistress, [[Arlette Elkaïm]], who became his adopted daughter in [[1965]]. He opposed the [[Vietnam War]] and, along with [[Bertrand Russell]] and other luminaries, he organized a [[tribunal]] intended to expose U.S. [[war crimes]], which became known as the [[Russell Tribunal]].
+
Although many philosophers and writers throughout the 19th and 20th centuries have been called “existentialist” the philosophical school of “[[existentialism]]” has been mostly associated with the thought of Jean-Paul Sartre. There are two main reasons for this. First, unlike other existential thinkers of his generation ([[Heidegger]], [[Albert Camus|Camus]], [[Gabriel Marcel]]), Sartre did not distance himself from the term ‘existentialism’ but rather embraced it. Or, to put it another way, these others thinkers distanced themselves from this term precisely because Sartre embraced it; so, in philosophical circles existentialism had become almost synonymous with Sartrian ideas. Secondly, the term existential became so widespread in popular culture in the middle part of the 20th century that it came to signify, as Sartre himself said, “almost everything.” Nevertheless, Sartre held to the term and so today existentialism as a specific philosophical school continues to be aligned primarily with Sartre.
  
Not being an orthodox [[Stalinist]] [[fellow-traveller]], Sartre spent much of the rest of his life attempting to reconcile his existentialist ideas about [[self]]-determination with communist principles, which taught that socio-economic forces beyond our immediate, individual control play a critical role in shaping our lives. His major defining work of this period, the ''Critique de la raison dialectique'' (''[[Critique of Dialectical Reason]]'') appeared in 1960.
+
Sartre's most well-known introduction to his philosophy is his work ''Existentialism is a Humanism'' (1946). In this work, he defends existentialism against its critics, which ultimately results in a somewhat cursory description of his ideas. Nonetheless, the work remains a popular and accessible introduction to Sartre's main ideas. It is within his major and most influential philosophical work ''Being and Nothingness,'' however, that these themes are most closely analyzed and so brought to their full philosophical import.  
  
Sartre's emphasis on the humanist values in Marx and the emphasis on the early Marx this gave rise to, led to a famous dispute with the leading Communist intellectual in France in the [[1960s]], [[Louis Althusser]], in which Althusser attempted to redefine Marx's work into an early pre-Marxist period, with essentialist generalizations about Mankind, and a mature, scientific, authentically Marxist period (starting between the ''[[Grundrisse]]'' and ''[[Das Kapital]]''). Some say this was the only public debate Sartre ever lost, but it remains still to this day a both disputed and controversial event still discussed within some philosophical circles of France.
+
===Consciousness===
 +
Like most twentieth century existential thinkers Sartre was greatly influenced by the [[phenomenology|phenomenological]] movements of [[Edmund Husserl]]. This teaching held that all human knowledge can be traced back (reduced) to an original ‘lived experience’. This gave concrete descriptive analyses of our basic experiences priority over purely logical, abstract reasoning. Like Heidegger, Sartre appropriated the phenomenological method and applied it to the subject of ‘existence’ (although Sartre and Heidegger interpreted ‘existence’ in different ways). For Sartre this meant dividing all reality into two basic modes of being: (1) the in-itself (en-soi), which is the state of all material beings as they exist apart from our consciousness of them; and (2) the for-itself (pour-soi), which is all things as they are experienced by or for human consciousness. For Sartre consciousness has no separate existence of its own, but always needs some object to be conscious of. In other words, whenever I think, feel, believe, or will, I must always think, feel, believe, or will some thing. This means that my consciousness is dependent upon that thing or object about which I am thinking, feeling, believing, etc. Consciousness by itself, therefore, is not merely an empty receptacle but literally no-thing, that is, nothingness.
  
==Sartre and literature==
+
=== ‘Existence precedes Essence’===
During the 1940s and 1950s Sartre's ideas remained much ambiguous, and [[existentialism]] became a favoured philosophy of the [[beatnik]] generation. Sartre's views were counterposed to those of [[Albert Camus]] in the popular imagination. In 1948, the [[Catholic Church]] placed his complete works on the [[Index Librorum Prohibitorum|Index]] of prohibited books.  Most of his plays are richly symbolic and serve as a means of conveying his philosophy. The best-known, ''Huis-clos'' (''[[No Exit]]''), contains the famous line:
+
One of Sartre’s primary existential ideas is the notion that existence precedes essence. This means that the being of brute existence comes first and our understanding of it comes after. In classical philosophy the “essence” of things that exist are considered to be their ‘natures’. It is from these objective natures, which really exist “out there,” that we come to know what things are essentially. For Sartre there are no real essences or natures in the strict sense. Whatever meanings we ascribe to things are always subjective; that is, we create them out of our own nothingness or freedom.
"L'enfer, c'est les autres", usually translated as "Hell is other people".
 
  
Besides the obvious impact of ''Nausea'', Sartre's major contribution to literature was the ''Roads to Freedom'' trilogy which charts the progression of how [[World War II]] affected Sartre's ideas. In this way, ''Roads to Freedom'' presents a less theoretical and more practical approach to [[existentialism]]. The first book in the trilogy, ''L'âge de raison'' (''[[The Age of Reason (Sartre)|The Age of Reason]]'') ([[1945]]), could easily be said to be the Sartre work with the broadest appeal.
+
Sartre’s existentialism is presupposed by his acceptance of Nietzsche’s pronouncement that ‘God is dead.’ Like Nietzsche, Sartre believed that [[Enlightenment]] thinkers had rid themselves of God by turning solely to reason and science, and yet they refused to accept the full implications of this departure. Only if there is a God, can we be said to have an essence or human nature that determines what we as human beings are. Sartre uses an example of a paper-cutter to make his point. Only if someone first had an idea (essence) of a paper-cutter and then actually made it, could we say that the paper-cutter has a nature (essence). Likewise, only if there is a God or Creator who first had an idea of human beings, can we say there is a human essence or nature. But there is no God, so there is no human nature. Thus, the meanings we ascribe to ourselves are our own creations, either individually or socially/culturally. One might note that Sartre nowhere attempts to prove God’s inexistence but simply accepts it as a given.  
  
==Sartre after literature==
+
===Freedom and anguish===
In 1964, Sartre renounced literature in a witty and sardonic account of the first six years of his life, ''Les mots'' (''Words''). The book is an ironic counterblast to [[Marcel Proust]], whose reputation had unexpectedly eclipsed that of [[André Gide]] (who had provided the model of ''literature engagée'' for Sartre's generation). Literature, Sartre concluded, functioned as a bourgeois substitute for real commitment in the world. In the same year he was awarded the [[Nobel Prize]] for Literature, but he resoundingly declined it, stating that he had always refused official honors and didn't wish to align himself with institutions. This rejection hurt the prestige of the Nobel institution more than it did Sartre's. However, Sartre later tried to claim the prize money but the Nobel committee turned him down. This fact was revealed in the auto-biography of Lars Gyllensten, long time member of the Nobel Prize committee. The French philosopher in 1975 wrote a letter to the Nobel Prize committee, saying
+
Given this state of affairs, then, for Sartre we must accept the hard truths of reality. But although Sartre held to the meaninglessness of the universe or material being in itself, he believed strongly in human freedom. This freedom, however, appears as a double-edged sword. Although we are free to create ourselves, which gives us a degree of nobility as well as some flexibility in choosing our actions for ourselves, the full realization and acceptance of our freedom comes at a great price. Sartre describes this great price in terms of anguish, forlornness, and despair.  
that he had changed his mind about the prize, at least when it came to the money (approx $1M). Would it be possible to receive the prize, or the money, after 11 years? The answer was "No".
 
  
Though he was now world-famous and a household word (as was "existentialism" during the tumultuous
+
Once we realize there is no God we must also accept that there is no objective set of ethical values upon which to justify the ‘goodness’ or ‘rightness’ of our actions. In doing this, we then become aware of a kind of anguish. Anguish for Sartre marks the recognition of our own freedom. While we always fear some thing, some danger or object ‘out there’, anguish is the dread awareness of our own subjective freedom.
1960s), Sartre remained a simple man with few possessions, actively committed to causes until the end of his life, such as the [[May 1968|student revolution strikes]] in Paris during the summer of 1968.
+
Forlornness, in turn, is the recognition that we are alone. No one can help us in the solitary journey of making our own choices and so creating our own values. Sartre tells of the inefficacity of seeking advice from someone else. Since we have to choose the person to whom we seek advice, we in a certain sense already know what that person will tell us. Seek advice from a priest and he will tell you to seek God; ask a Communist and she will say join the Party. Sartre, of course, is not talking about trivial decisions but those crossroad choices through which we determine the overall course of our lives and the way we will live; or, in other words, the ultimate meaning which structures and defines our lives.  
  
In 1975, when asked how he would like to be remembered, Sartre replied: "I would like [people] to remember ''Nausea'', [my plays] ''No Exit'' and ''The Devil and the Good Lord'', and then my two philosophical works, more particularly the second one, ''Critique of Dialectical Reason''. Then my essay on Genet, ''Saint Genet''...If these are remembered, that would be quite an achievement, and I don't ask for more. As a man, if a certain Jean-Paul Sartre is remembered, I would like people to remember the milieu or historical situation in which I lived,...how I lived in it, in terms of all the aspirations which I tried to gather up within myself."
+
Finally, this process of self-realization can lead to despair. For our successes and failures, our virtues and our vices, are ultimately our own. We have no one else to praise or blame for our victories and defeats. Many critics have found Sartre’s emphasis on self-determination to be both harsh and naïve. As mentioned above, in later years Sartre tried to reconcile his existential volunteerism with a more [[Marxism|Marxist]] view that stresses social, political, and economic forces; few critics, however, have been convinced by his attempt.
  
Sartre's physical condition deteriorated, partially due to the merciless pace of work he put himself through during the writing of the ''Critique'' and the last project of his life, a massive analytical biography of [[Gustave Flaubert]] (''The Family Idiot''), both of which remain unfinished. He died April 15, 1980 in Paris from an [[edema]] of the [[lung]]. His last word is reputed to be simply, "Trix".
+
===Authenticity and 'bad faith'===
 +
Despite this negative and apparently harsh outlook, Sartre tried to put a positive spin on his philosophy in his analysis of authenticity. It is through our freedom that we accept responsibility for our actions, which in turn determines who we are. If we avoid this responsibility we fall into what Sartre calls ''mauvaise foi'' or “bad faith.” In bad faith we deceive ourselves, either by denying our freedom in claiming that we “have no choice” or else by giving into daydreams and so imagining ourselves to be what we are not. Instead we are to accept responsibility for what we are (past) as well as our freedom to choose what to become (future). In this way, then, we become authentic human beings.
 +
Moreover, when we choose ourselves, we choose all humanity. This means that to commit ourselves to a certain cause or worldview (for example, [[Christianity]] or [[Communism]]) we do not say “this is right merely for me” but rather this is right for everyone (all humanity). One could not authentically commit to something unless this notion of ‘choosing all humanity’ was implicit in the choice. Nothing justifies or grounds the ‘truth’ or value of this choice, however, except our own whole-hearted commitment to it.
  
Sartre lies buried in [[Cimetière du Montparnasse]] in [[Paris]]. His funeral was attended by some
+
==Sartre and literature==
50,000 people.
+
Like other existential-phenomenologists Sartre held that our ideas are the products of our lived experiences or real-life situations. For this reason, novels and plays, which describe our fundamental experiences of the world and others, have as much value as philosophical or theoretical essays. In his most famous novel ''Nausea,'' Sartre describes and analyzes in narrative form many of these basic existential encounters. The novel centers on a dejected researcher (Roquentin) who is living in a town similar to Le Havre. Throughout the story Roquentin becomes starkly conscious of the fact that inanimate objects and situations remain absolutely indifferent to his existence. Rather than reveal themselves as being intrinsically meaningful, they show themselves to be resistant to whatever significance human consciousness might perceive in them. This indifference of "things in themselves" (or the "being-in-itself" of ''Being and Nothingness'') reveals to Roquentin his own fundamental freedom or ‘nothingness.” Everywhere he looks, in fact, he finds situations imbued with meanings (‘nihilations’), which bear the stamp of his own existence. Hence the “nausea” that arises from this experience of his own nothingness. All that he encounters in everyday life is suffused with this all-pervasive and horrible taste, namely, his own freedom. No matter how much he longs for something other (nostalgia), he cannot escape from the harrowing evidence of his nihilating engagement with the world.
 
 
For all of his life, Sartre was an Atheist, atheism being foundational for his Existentialist Philosophy.
 
 
 
==Critiques==
 
 
 
===Munich 1972 and Israel===
 
 
 
When eleven [[Israel|Israeli]] Olympians were killed by the [[Palestinian]] organization [[Black September (group)|Black September]] in [[Munich]] [[1972]], Sartre referred to [[terrorism]] as a "terrible weapon but the oppressed poor have no others."  He also found it "perfectly scandalous that the Munich attack should be judged by the French press and a section of public opinion as an intolerable scandal." (Sartre: The Philosopher of the Twentieth Century, Bernard-Henri Lévy, p.343).
 
 
 
Although this has been understood by many as an apology to terrorism, these comments must be read together with others where he indicated that no means should be used which dehumanize its targets and disfigure its goal. He in fact identified as one of those "who affirm the sovereignty of the Israeli state and also believe the Palestinians have a right to sovereignty for the same reason..."  He was also known for his strong opposition to [[anti-semitism]].
 
  
==Works==
+
Along with ''Nausea,'' Sartre offered other major contributions to the world of literature. The stories in ''The Wall,'' for example, contributed to the [[absurdism|absurdist]] literature of the post-war period, by emphasizing the arbitrary aspects of situations in which people find themselves and the absurdity of their attempts to deal rationally with them. Also, there was the ''Roads to Freedom'' trilogy, which charts the progression of how World War II affected and developed many of Sartre's main ideas. In these novels Sartre presents a less theoretical and more practical approach to existentialism, which illustrate his notion of literature as ‘engaged’. Sartre’s plays, as well, are richly symbolic in conveying his philosophical ideas. The best-known, ''Huis-clos'' ''(No Exit),'' contains the famous line: "L'enfer, c'est les autres," usually translated as "Hell is other people." Although this line neatly captures Sartre’s skepticism of others in terms of their attempts at domination (which is also conveyed in his philosophical analysis of shame in Being and Nothingness); it nevertheless is pronounced ironically in the play, and so one should be careful about attributing that statement to Sartre’s overall position of social interaction.
(major philosophical works in bold)
 
  
* ''L'imagination'' (''[[Imagination: A Psychological Critique]]''), [[1936]]
+
==References==
* ''La transcendance de l'égo'' (''[[The Transcendence of the Ego]]'') [[1937]]
+
===Major Works by Sartre (in English)===
* ''La nausée'' (''[[Nausea (Book)|Nausea]]''), [[1938]]
+
* ''Transcendence of the Ego.'' Routledge, an imprint of Taylor & Francis Books Ltd, 2004. ISBN 978-0415320696
* ''Le mur'' (''[[The Wall (Book)|The Wall]]''), [[1939]]
+
* ''The Emotions: Outline of a Theory: Outline of a Theory.'' 2000. ISBN 978-0806509044
* ''Esquisse d'une théorie des émotions'' (''[[Sketch for a Theory of the Emotions]]''), [[1939]]
+
* ''Being and Nothingness.'' Routledge, an imprint of Taylor & Francis Books Ltd, 2003. ISBN 978-0415278485
* ''L'imaginaire'' (''[[The Imaginary]]''), [[1940]]
+
* "Existentialism Is A Humanism," in ''Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre.'' Kaufmann, Walter. Plume, 1975. ISBN 978-0452009301
* ''Les mouches'' (''[[The Flies]]''), [[1943]] - a modern version of the ''[[Oresteia]]''
+
* ''What is Literature? And Other Essays.'' Harvard University Press, 1988. ISBN 978-0674950832
* '''L'être et le néant''' ('''[[Being and Nothingness]]'''), [[1943]]
+
* ''Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. 1, Theory of Practical Ensembles,'' tr. Alan Sheridan-Smith, London: New Left Books, [1960]. ISBN 1859844855
* ''Réflexions sur la question juive'' (''[[Anti-Semite and Jew]]''; literally, ''Reflections on the Jewish Question''), [[1943]]
+
* ''The Words.'' New York: Vintage, 1981. ISBN 978-0394747095
* ''Huis-clos'' (''[[No Exit]]''), [[1944]]
+
* ''Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol Two.'' Verso, 2006. ISBN 978-1844670772
* ''Les Chemins de la liberté'' (''[[Roads to Freedom]]'') trilogy, comprising:
 
** ''L'âge de raison'' (''[[The Age of Reason (Sartre)|The Age of Reason]]''), [[1945]]
 
** ''Le sursis'' (''[[The Reprieve]]''), [[1947]]
 
** ''La mort dans l'Âme'' (''[[Iron in the Soul]]''), [[1949]]
 
* ''Morts sans sépulture'' (''The Victors'', literally, ''Deaths without burial''), [[1946]]
 
* ''L'Existentialisme est un humanisme'' (''[[Existentialism and Humanism]]''), [[1946]]
 
* ''La putain respectueuse'' (''[[The Respectful Prostitute]]'') [[1946]]
 
* ''Qu'est ce que la littérature?'' (''[[What is literature?]]''), [[1947]]
 
* ''[[Baudelaire]]'', [[1947]]
 
* ''Situations'', [[1947]]–[[1965]]
 
* ''Les mains sales'' (''[[Dirty Hands]]''), [[1948]]
 
* "Orphée Noir" (Black Orpheus), introduction to ''Anthologie de la nouvelle poésie nègre et malgache.''  edited by [[Léopold Sédar Senghor]], [[1948]]
 
* ''Le diable et le bon dieu'' (''[[The Devil and the Good Lord]]''), [[1951]]
 
* ''[[Les jeux sont faits]]'' (''[[The Game is Up]]''), [[1952]]
 
* ''Saint Genet, Actor and Martyr'', [[1952]]
 
* ''[[Existentialism and Human Emotions]]'', [[1957]]
 
* ''Les séquestrés d'Altona'' (''[[The Condemned of Altona]]''), [[1959]]
 
* '''Critique de la raison dialectique''' ('''[[Critique of Dialectical Reason]]'''), [[1960]]
 
* ''[[Search for a Method]]'' (English tr. of preface to ''Critique'', Vol. I) [[1962]]
 
* ''Les mots'' (''[[The Words]]''), [[1964]] - autobiographical
 
* "Preface" to [[Frantz Fanon]]'s ''The Wretched of the Earth''
 
* ''L'idiot de la famille'' (''The Family Idiot''), [[1971]]–[[1972]] - on [[Gustave Flaubert]]
 
* ''Cahiers pour une morale''(''[[Notebooks for an Ethics]]''), [[1983]], 1947-48 notes on ethics
 
* ''Les carnets de la drôle de guerre: Novembre 1939 - Mars 1940'' (''[[War Diaries|War Diaries: Notebooks from a Phoney War 1939-1940]]''), [[1984]], notebooks from Sartre's time in the [[Phony War]] of 1939-1940
 
  
==Quotes== <!--This data was moved from the old Infobox Philosopher template on September 9.  Please move this to Wikiquote—>
+
===Other sources===
''The For-itself, in fact, is nothing but the pure nihilation of the In-itself; it is like a hole of being at the heart of Being.''<br>-[[Being and Nothingness]], p. 617
 
  
== Further reading==
+
* Barnes, Hazel E. ''Sartre and Flaubert.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981. ISBN 0226037207
* [[Annie Cohen-Solal]], ''Sartre 1905-80'', 1985
+
* Busch, Thomas. ''The Power of Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in Sartre's Philosophy.'' Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990. ISBN 0253312833
*[[R. D. Laing]] and [[D. G. Cooper]], ''Reason and Violence: A Decade of Sartre's Philosophy 1950-1960'', New york: Pantheon, 1971.
+
* Catalano, Joseph. ''A Commentary on Jean-Paul Sartre's Being and Nothingness.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980. ISBN 0226096998
* Heiner Wittmann, ''L'esthétique de Sartre. Artistes et intellectuels'', translated from the German by N. Weitemeier and J. Yacar, Éditions L'Harmattan (Collection L'ouverture philosophique), Paris 2001.
+
* Detmer, David. ''Freedom as a Value: A Critique of the Ethical Theory of Jean-Paul Sartre.'' La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1988. ISBN 0812690834
* H. Wittmann, ''Sartre und die Kunst. Die Porträtstudien von Tintoretto bis Flaubert'', Gunter Narr Verlag, Tübingen 1996.
+
* Dobson, Andrew. ''Jean-Paul Sartre and the Politics of Reason.'' Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. ISBN 0521434491
 +
* Flynn, Thomas R. ''Sartre and Marxist Existentialism: The Test Case of Collective Responsibility.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994. ISBN 0226254666
 +
* Jeanson, Francis. ''Sartre and the Problem of Morality,'' tr. Robert Stone, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1981. ISBN 0253166039
 +
* Schilpp, Paul Arthur, ed., ''The Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre.'' La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1981. ISBN 0812691504
 +
* Schroeder, William. ''Sartre and His Predecessors.'' Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984. ISBN 0710202741
 +
* Taylor, Charles. ''The Ethics of Authenticity.'' Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991. ISBN 0674268636
  
 
== External links ==
 
== External links ==
{{wikiquote}}
+
All links retrieved May 1, 2018.
=== By Sartre ===
 
*[http://www.thenation.com/doc.mhtml?i=19471018&s=sartre Americans and Their Myths] Sartre's 1947 essay in ''[[The Nation]]''
 
*[http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/sartre/index.htm Sartre Internet Archive] on [http://www.marxists.org Marxists.org]
 
* {{fr}} [http://www.incipitblog.com/index.php/2005/11/01/jean-paul-sartre-les-mots-1964/ Audiobook (mp3) :] incipit of The Words (1964), read aloud in french by IncipitBlog.
 
  
=== On Sartre ===
+
*[http://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/sartre/index.htm Sartre Internet Archive] on ''Marxists.org''
 
*[http://home.mira.net/~andy/works/sartre.htm Sartre’s Critique of Dialectical Reason] essay by Andy Blunden  
 
*[http://home.mira.net/~andy/works/sartre.htm Sartre’s Critique of Dialectical Reason] essay by Andy Blunden  
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sartre/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Sartre]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/sartre/ Jean-Paul Sartre] Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:  
 
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/s/sartre-ex.htm Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980): Existentialism] Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
 
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/s/sartre-ex.htm Jean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980): Existentialism] Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
*[http://www.sartre.org/ Sartre.org] Articles, archives, and forum
 
*[http://enjoyment.independent.co.uk/books/features/article226073.ece "The Second Coming Of Sartre"], John Lichfield, ''[[The Independent]]'', [[17 June]] 2005
 
*[http://www.newcriterion.com/archive/extras/sartre.htm The World According to Sartre] essay by Roger Kimball
 
*[http://pubs.socialistreviewindex.org.uk/isj102/pitt.htm Reclaiming Sartre] A review of Ian Birchall, ''Sartre Against Stalinism''
 
 
*[http://www.angelfire.com/ego2/olko/binary/sartre-bio.html Short biography]
 
*[http://www.angelfire.com/ego2/olko/binary/sartre-bio.html Short biography]
*[http://www.geocities.com/stuartfernie/kean.htm Discussion of Sartre's "Kean"]
 
  
<!--Interwiki—>
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
[[Category:1905 births|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
[[Category:1980 deaths|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
[[Category:20th century philosophers|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
[[Category:Continental philosophers|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]  
[[Category:Atheist philosophers|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
+
 
[[Category:List of Freudians|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:French communists|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:Marxists|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:French dramatists and playwrights|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:French novelists|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:Existentialists|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:Metaphysics writers|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:French philosophers|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:Nobel Prize in Literature winners|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:Alumni of the École Normale Supérieure|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
[[Category:Parisians|Sartre, Jean-Paul]]
 
  
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
+
{{Nobel Prize in Literature Laureates 1951-1975}}
  
 +
[[Category:Philosophers]]
 
{{Credit|29212873}}
 
{{Credit|29212873}}

Latest revision as of 17:11, 2 April 2024

Jean-Paul Sartre

Jean-Paul Sartre (June 21, 1905 – April 15, 1980) was a French philosopher, playwright, novelist, and literary critic. His most famous writings include the novel La nausée (Nausea), (1938), his major philosophical work L'être et le néant (Being and Nothingness) (1943), and the play Huis-clos (No Exit) (1944). Throughout these writings Sartre describes and analyzes our most basic existential experiences, which reveal the fundamental human condition in our relation to the world and others. Although he is often associated with other existential thinkers of the twentieth century (Martin Heidegger, Karl Jaspers, Gabriel Marcel) Sartre, unlike these other philosophers, strongly embraced the term “existentialism” and so today his name, more than these others, is equated with the school of existentialism.

As with other philosophers of existence, Sartre held that ‘existence precedes essence’. For Sartre this meant that all existing things in the material universe are in themselves meaningless. Only through our consciousness of them do things take on value, which means that it is we who create meaning. Sartre links consciousness and our experience of anguish to freedom. It is through accepting responsibility for our freedom, and the anguish that accompanies it, that we can become authentic human beings. Throughout his life Sartre was very politically active, and although he never officially joined the Communist Party, he espoused Marxist ideas. In 1964 Sartre won the Nobel Prize in Literature, but he declined the award stating that he did not align himself with institutions.

Sartre’s Life

Early years

Sartre was born in Paris to parents Jean-Baptiste Sartre, an officer of the French Navy, and Anne-Marie Schweitzer, cousin of Albert Schweitzer. When he was 15 months old, his father died of a fever. Anne-Marie raised him with help from her father, Charles Schweitzer, who taught Sartre mathematics and introduced him to classical literature at an early age. As a teenager in the 1920s, Sartre became attracted to philosophy upon reading Henri Bergson's Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness. He studied in Paris at the elite École Normale Supérieure. Sartre was influenced by many aspects of Western philosophy, particularly the ideas of the great German philosophers Immanuel Kant, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, Friedrich Nietzsche, and Martin Heidegger.

In 1929 at the École Normale, Sartre met fellow student Simone de Beauvoir, who later became a noted thinker, writer, and feminist. From the start the two were inseparable and throughout their lives they continued a romantic relationship, though one that was self-consciously anti-monogamous. Together Sartre and Beauvoir challenged many cultural and social assumptions, which they considered to be “bourgeois,” both in practice and in thought. The conflict between oppressive conformity to other people or to established institutions and an authentic self-determination based on free choice would become a dominant theme in Sartre's later work.

Sartre graduated from the École Normale in 1929 with a doctorate in philosophy and from 1929 to 1931 he served as a conscript in the French Army. Afterward he taught as a junior lecturer at the Lycée du Havre and began to work on his writing. Throughout the late 1930s he published his first works, such as the philosophical essays: Imagination: A Psychological Critique (1936) and The Transcendence of the Ego (1937), and the literary works: Nausea (1938) and The Wall (1939).

Sartre and World War II

In 1939 Sartre was drafted into the French army, where he served as a meteorologist. German troops captured him in 1940 in Padoux and he spent nine months in prison; later he was sent to Nancy and finally to Stalag 12D, in Trier, where he wrote his first theater piece: "Barionà, fils du tonnerre." Due to poor health he was released from prison in April of 1941. Given civilian status, he then escaped to Paris where he became involved in the French Resistance and participated in the founding of the resistance group Socialisme et Liberté. It was while engaged in the resistance that he met Albert Camus, a philosopher and writer who held similar existential and political convictions. The two remained friends until Camus’ move away from communism, which created a schism that would eventually divide them in 1951 following the publication of Camus' The Rebel. Also during the war Sartre published his most famous and definitive philosophical work L'être et le néant (Being and Nothingness) (1943). When the war ended he established Les Temps Modernes (Modern Times), a monthly literary and political review, and started writing full-time. It was from out of his war experiences that he would create his great trilogy of novels, Les Chemins de la Liberté (The Roads to Freedom) (1945-1949).

Sartre and communism

While the first period of Sartre's intellectual career is better defined by the philosophical ideas presented in Being and Nothingness, the second period can be viewed more in light of his political engagement. His 1948 work Les Mains Sales (Dirty Hands) explores the problem of being both an intellectual and a political activist. Although Sartre never officially joined the French Communist party, he was committed to communist ideas and took a prominent role in the struggle against French colonialism in Algeria. Aware of the abuses of communist Stalinism, however, Sartre spent much of the remainder of his life trying to reconcile his existentialist ideas about self-determination with communist principles, which held that socio-economic forces beyond our immediate, individual control play an instrumental role in shaping our lives. His major defining work of the later period, the Critique de la raison dialectique (Critique of Dialectical Reason) appeared in 1960.

Sartre's emphasis on the humanist values in the early work of Marx led to a famous dispute with the leading Communist intellectual in France during the 1960s, Louis Althusser. Althusser redefined Marx's work by dividing it into an early pre-Marxist period, which espoused essentialist generalizations about “Mankind,” and a more mature, scientific and authentically Marxist period, which emphasized the dialectical materialism over essentialist humanism. Sartre took issue with this interpretation, and it spurred the debate between the two thinkers. Although some say this was the only public debate Sartre ever lost, it remains a disputed issue within various philosophical circles in France.

Later years

In 1964, Sartre renounced literature in a witty and sardonic account of the first six years of his life, Les mots (Words). The book is an ironic counterblast to Marcel Proust, whose reputation had unexpectedly eclipsed that of André Gide (who had provided the model of literature engagée for Sartre's generation). Literature, Sartre concluded, functioned as a bourgeois substitute for real commitment in the world. Also in 1964 Sartre was awarded the Nobel Prize for Literature; he declined the honor, however, stating that he had always refused official honors and didn't wish to align himself with institutions of any sort.

Although Sartre had become a ‘household name’ (as did “existentialism” which developed into a popular movement throughout the tumultuous 1960s), he remained a simple man with few possessions. Until the end of his life he stayed actively committed to political causes, such as the student revolution strikes in Paris during the summer of 1968 and opposition to the Vietnam War. In terms of the latter, he, along with Bertrand Russell and other intellectuals, organized a tribunal intended to expose U.S. war crimes. Throughout the 1970s Sartre's physical condition deteriorated, partially due to the merciless pace he endured while writing the Critique as well as the last project of his life, a massive analytical biography of Gustave Flaubert (The Family Idiot), both of which remain unfinished. In 1975, when asked how he would like to be remembered, Sartre replied in the following way: "I would like people to remember Nausea, my plays No Exit and The Devil and the Good Lord, and then my two philosophical works, more particularly the second one, Critique of Dialectical Reason. Then my essay on Genet, Saint Genet…. If these are remembered, that would be quite an achievement, and I don't ask for more. As a man, if a certain Jean-Paul Sartre is remembered, I would like people to remember the milieu or historical situation in which I lived, … how I lived in it, in terms of all the aspirations which I tried to gather up within myself." Sartre died April 15, 1980 in Paris from an edema of the lung. Sartre lies buried in Cimetière du Montparnasse in Paris. Approximately 50,000 people attended his funeral.

Existentialism: Philosophical Ideas

Although many philosophers and writers throughout the 19th and 20th centuries have been called “existentialist” the philosophical school of “existentialism” has been mostly associated with the thought of Jean-Paul Sartre. There are two main reasons for this. First, unlike other existential thinkers of his generation (Heidegger, Camus, Gabriel Marcel), Sartre did not distance himself from the term ‘existentialism’ but rather embraced it. Or, to put it another way, these others thinkers distanced themselves from this term precisely because Sartre embraced it; so, in philosophical circles existentialism had become almost synonymous with Sartrian ideas. Secondly, the term existential became so widespread in popular culture in the middle part of the 20th century that it came to signify, as Sartre himself said, “almost everything.” Nevertheless, Sartre held to the term and so today existentialism as a specific philosophical school continues to be aligned primarily with Sartre.

Sartre's most well-known introduction to his philosophy is his work Existentialism is a Humanism (1946). In this work, he defends existentialism against its critics, which ultimately results in a somewhat cursory description of his ideas. Nonetheless, the work remains a popular and accessible introduction to Sartre's main ideas. It is within his major and most influential philosophical work Being and Nothingness, however, that these themes are most closely analyzed and so brought to their full philosophical import.

Consciousness

Like most twentieth century existential thinkers Sartre was greatly influenced by the phenomenological movements of Edmund Husserl. This teaching held that all human knowledge can be traced back (reduced) to an original ‘lived experience’. This gave concrete descriptive analyses of our basic experiences priority over purely logical, abstract reasoning. Like Heidegger, Sartre appropriated the phenomenological method and applied it to the subject of ‘existence’ (although Sartre and Heidegger interpreted ‘existence’ in different ways). For Sartre this meant dividing all reality into two basic modes of being: (1) the in-itself (en-soi), which is the state of all material beings as they exist apart from our consciousness of them; and (2) the for-itself (pour-soi), which is all things as they are experienced by or for human consciousness. For Sartre consciousness has no separate existence of its own, but always needs some object to be conscious of. In other words, whenever I think, feel, believe, or will, I must always think, feel, believe, or will some thing. This means that my consciousness is dependent upon that thing or object about which I am thinking, feeling, believing, etc. Consciousness by itself, therefore, is not merely an empty receptacle but literally no-thing, that is, nothingness.

‘Existence precedes Essence’

One of Sartre’s primary existential ideas is the notion that existence precedes essence. This means that the being of brute existence comes first and our understanding of it comes after. In classical philosophy the “essence” of things that exist are considered to be their ‘natures’. It is from these objective natures, which really exist “out there,” that we come to know what things are essentially. For Sartre there are no real essences or natures in the strict sense. Whatever meanings we ascribe to things are always subjective; that is, we create them out of our own nothingness or freedom.

Sartre’s existentialism is presupposed by his acceptance of Nietzsche’s pronouncement that ‘God is dead.’ Like Nietzsche, Sartre believed that Enlightenment thinkers had rid themselves of God by turning solely to reason and science, and yet they refused to accept the full implications of this departure. Only if there is a God, can we be said to have an essence or human nature that determines what we as human beings are. Sartre uses an example of a paper-cutter to make his point. Only if someone first had an idea (essence) of a paper-cutter and then actually made it, could we say that the paper-cutter has a nature (essence). Likewise, only if there is a God or Creator who first had an idea of human beings, can we say there is a human essence or nature. But there is no God, so there is no human nature. Thus, the meanings we ascribe to ourselves are our own creations, either individually or socially/culturally. One might note that Sartre nowhere attempts to prove God’s inexistence but simply accepts it as a given.

Freedom and anguish

Given this state of affairs, then, for Sartre we must accept the hard truths of reality. But although Sartre held to the meaninglessness of the universe or material being in itself, he believed strongly in human freedom. This freedom, however, appears as a double-edged sword. Although we are free to create ourselves, which gives us a degree of nobility as well as some flexibility in choosing our actions for ourselves, the full realization and acceptance of our freedom comes at a great price. Sartre describes this great price in terms of anguish, forlornness, and despair.

Once we realize there is no God we must also accept that there is no objective set of ethical values upon which to justify the ‘goodness’ or ‘rightness’ of our actions. In doing this, we then become aware of a kind of anguish. Anguish for Sartre marks the recognition of our own freedom. While we always fear some thing, some danger or object ‘out there’, anguish is the dread awareness of our own subjective freedom. Forlornness, in turn, is the recognition that we are alone. No one can help us in the solitary journey of making our own choices and so creating our own values. Sartre tells of the inefficacity of seeking advice from someone else. Since we have to choose the person to whom we seek advice, we in a certain sense already know what that person will tell us. Seek advice from a priest and he will tell you to seek God; ask a Communist and she will say join the Party. Sartre, of course, is not talking about trivial decisions but those crossroad choices through which we determine the overall course of our lives and the way we will live; or, in other words, the ultimate meaning which structures and defines our lives.

Finally, this process of self-realization can lead to despair. For our successes and failures, our virtues and our vices, are ultimately our own. We have no one else to praise or blame for our victories and defeats. Many critics have found Sartre’s emphasis on self-determination to be both harsh and naïve. As mentioned above, in later years Sartre tried to reconcile his existential volunteerism with a more Marxist view that stresses social, political, and economic forces; few critics, however, have been convinced by his attempt.

Authenticity and 'bad faith'

Despite this negative and apparently harsh outlook, Sartre tried to put a positive spin on his philosophy in his analysis of authenticity. It is through our freedom that we accept responsibility for our actions, which in turn determines who we are. If we avoid this responsibility we fall into what Sartre calls mauvaise foi or “bad faith.” In bad faith we deceive ourselves, either by denying our freedom in claiming that we “have no choice” or else by giving into daydreams and so imagining ourselves to be what we are not. Instead we are to accept responsibility for what we are (past) as well as our freedom to choose what to become (future). In this way, then, we become authentic human beings. Moreover, when we choose ourselves, we choose all humanity. This means that to commit ourselves to a certain cause or worldview (for example, Christianity or Communism) we do not say “this is right merely for me” but rather this is right for everyone (all humanity). One could not authentically commit to something unless this notion of ‘choosing all humanity’ was implicit in the choice. Nothing justifies or grounds the ‘truth’ or value of this choice, however, except our own whole-hearted commitment to it.

Sartre and literature

Like other existential-phenomenologists Sartre held that our ideas are the products of our lived experiences or real-life situations. For this reason, novels and plays, which describe our fundamental experiences of the world and others, have as much value as philosophical or theoretical essays. In his most famous novel Nausea, Sartre describes and analyzes in narrative form many of these basic existential encounters. The novel centers on a dejected researcher (Roquentin) who is living in a town similar to Le Havre. Throughout the story Roquentin becomes starkly conscious of the fact that inanimate objects and situations remain absolutely indifferent to his existence. Rather than reveal themselves as being intrinsically meaningful, they show themselves to be resistant to whatever significance human consciousness might perceive in them. This indifference of "things in themselves" (or the "being-in-itself" of Being and Nothingness) reveals to Roquentin his own fundamental freedom or ‘nothingness.” Everywhere he looks, in fact, he finds situations imbued with meanings (‘nihilations’), which bear the stamp of his own existence. Hence the “nausea” that arises from this experience of his own nothingness. All that he encounters in everyday life is suffused with this all-pervasive and horrible taste, namely, his own freedom. No matter how much he longs for something other (nostalgia), he cannot escape from the harrowing evidence of his nihilating engagement with the world.

Along with Nausea, Sartre offered other major contributions to the world of literature. The stories in The Wall, for example, contributed to the absurdist literature of the post-war period, by emphasizing the arbitrary aspects of situations in which people find themselves and the absurdity of their attempts to deal rationally with them. Also, there was the Roads to Freedom trilogy, which charts the progression of how World War II affected and developed many of Sartre's main ideas. In these novels Sartre presents a less theoretical and more practical approach to existentialism, which illustrate his notion of literature as ‘engaged’. Sartre’s plays, as well, are richly symbolic in conveying his philosophical ideas. The best-known, Huis-clos (No Exit), contains the famous line: "L'enfer, c'est les autres," usually translated as "Hell is other people." Although this line neatly captures Sartre’s skepticism of others in terms of their attempts at domination (which is also conveyed in his philosophical analysis of shame in Being and Nothingness); it nevertheless is pronounced ironically in the play, and so one should be careful about attributing that statement to Sartre’s overall position of social interaction.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

Major Works by Sartre (in English)

  • Transcendence of the Ego. Routledge, an imprint of Taylor & Francis Books Ltd, 2004. ISBN 978-0415320696
  • The Emotions: Outline of a Theory: Outline of a Theory. 2000. ISBN 978-0806509044
  • Being and Nothingness. Routledge, an imprint of Taylor & Francis Books Ltd, 2003. ISBN 978-0415278485
  • "Existentialism Is A Humanism," in Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre. Kaufmann, Walter. Plume, 1975. ISBN 978-0452009301
  • What is Literature? And Other Essays. Harvard University Press, 1988. ISBN 978-0674950832
  • Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol. 1, Theory of Practical Ensembles, tr. Alan Sheridan-Smith, London: New Left Books, [1960]. ISBN 1859844855
  • The Words. New York: Vintage, 1981. ISBN 978-0394747095
  • Critique of Dialectical Reason, vol Two. Verso, 2006. ISBN 978-1844670772

Other sources

  • Barnes, Hazel E. Sartre and Flaubert. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981. ISBN 0226037207
  • Busch, Thomas. The Power of Consciousness and the Force of Circumstances in Sartre's Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990. ISBN 0253312833
  • Catalano, Joseph. A Commentary on Jean-Paul Sartre's Being and Nothingness. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980. ISBN 0226096998
  • Detmer, David. Freedom as a Value: A Critique of the Ethical Theory of Jean-Paul Sartre. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1988. ISBN 0812690834
  • Dobson, Andrew. Jean-Paul Sartre and the Politics of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. ISBN 0521434491
  • Flynn, Thomas R. Sartre and Marxist Existentialism: The Test Case of Collective Responsibility. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994. ISBN 0226254666
  • Jeanson, Francis. Sartre and the Problem of Morality, tr. Robert Stone, Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1981. ISBN 0253166039
  • Schilpp, Paul Arthur, ed., The Philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre. La Salle, IL: Open Court, 1981. ISBN 0812691504
  • Schroeder, William. Sartre and His Predecessors. Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1984. ISBN 0710202741
  • Taylor, Charles. The Ethics of Authenticity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991. ISBN 0674268636

External links

All links retrieved May 1, 2018.

General Philosophy Sources


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.