Hutcheson, Francis

From New World Encyclopedia
m
 
(23 intermediate revisions by 9 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Contracted}}
+
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{copyedited}}
[[image:Francis_Hutcheson.gif|right|]]
+
{{epname|Hutcheson, Francis}}
'''Francis Hutcheson''' (August 8, 1694–August 8, 1746) was an [[Ireland|Irish]] [[philosopher]] and one of the founding fathers of the Scottish Enlightenment.
 
  
 +
[[image:Francis Hutcheson b1694.jpg|right|thumb|Francis Hutcheson]]
 +
 +
'''Francis Hutcheson''' (August 8, 1694 – August 8, 1746) was an [[Ireland|Irish]] [[philosopher]] and one of the founding fathers of the Scottish [[Enlightenment]]. Although his philosophy covers a wide range of subjects, he is known primarily for his [[ethics|moral theory]] and his study of [[aesthetics]]. His ideas include the concepts of the "moral sense" and the "benevolent theory" of morals, the latter for which he stood in sharp opposition to [[Thomas Hobbes]] and other [[egoism|egoists]]. He anticipates the [[utilitarianism]] of [[Jeremy Bentham]] in his use of the phrase "the greatest happiness for the greatest number," and his influence can be traced through his students, which include [[David Hume]] and [[Adam Smith]].
 +
{{toc}}
 
==Beginnings==
 
==Beginnings==
  
He is thought to have been born at Drumalig, in the parish of Saintfield, County Down, Northern Ireland. He spent six years at the University of Glasgow at first in the study of philosophy, classics and general literature, and afterwards in the study of [[theology]].
+
Hutcheson is thought to have been born at Drumalig, in the parish of Saintfield, County Down, Northern Ireland, to a Presbyterian minister. He spent six years at the University of Glasgow, first in the study of philosophy, classics, and general literature, and afterwards in the study of [[theology]].
  
On leaving university, he returned to Northern Ireland, and received a license to preach. When, however, he was about to enter upon the pastorate of a small dissenting congregation he changed his plans on the advice of a friend and opened a private academy in Dublin. In Dublin his literary attainments gained him the friendship of many prominent inhabitants. Among these was Archbishop of Dublin, William King, who refused to prosecute Hutcheson in the archbishop's court for keeping a school without the episcopal licence. Hutcheson's relations with the clergy of the Established Church, especially with King and with Hugh Boulter (the archbishop of Armagh) seem to have been cordial, and his biographer, speaking of "the inclination of his friends to serve him, the schemes proposed to him for obtaining promotion," etc., probably refers to some offers of preferment, on condition of his accepting episcopal ordination.  
+
On leaving university, he returned to Northern Ireland, and received a license to preach. When, however, he was about to enter upon the pastorate of a small, dissenting congregation, he changed his plans on the advice of a friend and opened a private academy in Dublin. While residing in [[Dublin]], Hutcheson published anonymously the four essays by which he is best known: the ''Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony and Design,'' the ''Inquiry Concerning Moral Good and Evil,'' in 1725, and the ''Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections and Illustrations upon the Moral Sense,'' in 1728. The alterations and additions made in the second edition of these essays were published in a separate form in 1726. To the period of his Dublin residence are also to be referred the ''Thoughts on Laughter'' (a criticism of [[Thomas Hobbes]]) and the ''Observations on the Fable of the Bees,'' being in all six letters contributed to ''Hibernicus' Letters,'' a periodical which appeared in Dublin (1725-1727, 2nd ed. 1734). At the end of the same period occurred the controversy in the ''London Journal'' with Gilbert Burnet; on the "True Foundation of Virtue or Moral Goodness." All these letters were collected in one volume (Glasgow, 1772).
  
While residing in [[Dublin]], Hutcheson published anonymously the four essays by which he is best known: the ''Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony and Design'', the ''Inquiry concerning Moral Good and Evil'', in 1725, the ''Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections and Illustrations upon the Moral Sense'', in 1728. The alterations and additions made in the second edition of these Essays were published in a separate form in 1726. To the period of his Dublin residence are also to be referred the ''Thoughts on Laughter'' (a criticism of [[Thomas Hobbes]]) and the ''Observations on the Fable of the Bees'', being in all six letters contributed to ''Hibernicus' Letters'', a periodical which appeared in Dublin (1725-1727, 2nd ed. 1734). At the end of the same period occurred the controversy in the ''London Journal'' with Gilbert Burnet (probably the second son of Dr Gilbert Burnet, bishop of Salisbury); on the "True Foundation of Virtue or Moral Goodness." All these letters were collected in one volume (Glasgow, 1772).
+
In 1729, Hutcheson succeeded his old master, Gershom Carmichael, in the chair of moral philosophy at the University of Glasgow. Yet the works on which Hutcheson's reputation rests had already been published.
  
In 1729, Hutcheson succeeded his old master, Gershom Carmichael, in the chair of moral philosophy at the University of Glasgow, being the first professor there to lecture in English instead of Latin. It is curious that up to this time all his essays and letters had been published anonymously, though their authorship appears to have been well known. In 1730 he entered on the duties of his office, delivering an inaugural lecture (afterwards published), ''De naturali hominum socialitate'' (About the natural fellowhip of mankind). He appreciated having leisure for his favourite studies; "''non levi igitur laetitia commovebar cum almam matrem Academiam me, suum olim alumnum, in libertatem asseruisse audiveram''." (I was, therefore, moved by no means frivolous pleasure when I had heard that my alma mater had delivered me, its one time alumnus, into freedom). Yet the works on which Hutcheson's reputation rests had already been published.
+
==Philosophy==
  
==Other works==
+
Hutcheson dealt with [[metaphysics]], [[logic]], and [[ethics]], but he is primarily known for his contributions to moral theory and the field of [[aesthetics]]. His works expound on various ideas including the relationship between beauty and virtue, the functions assigned to the moral sense, and the position that the benevolent feelings form an original and irreducible part of our nature.  
In addition to the works named, the following were published during Hutcheson's lifetime: a pamphlet entitled ''Considerations on Patronage'' (1735); ''Philosophiae moralis institutio compendiaria, ethices et jurisprudentiae naturalis elementa continens'', lib. iii. (Glasgow, 1742); ''Metaphysicae synopsis ontologiam et pneumatologiam campleciens'' (Glasgow, 1742). The last work was published anonymously. After his death, his son, Francis Hutcheson published much the longest, though by no means the most interesting, of his works, ''A System of Moral Philosophy, in Three Books'' (2 vois.. London, 1755). To this is prefixed a life of the author, by Dr William Leechman, professor of divinity in the University of Glasgow. The only remaining work assigned to Hutcheson is a small treatise on Logic (Glasgow, 1764). This compendium, together with the ''Compendium of Metaphysics'', was republished at Strassburg in 1722.
 
 
 
Thus Hutcheson dealt with [[metaphysics]], [[logic]] and [[ethics]]. His importance is, however, due almost entirely to his ethical writings, and among these primarily to the four essays and the letters published during his time in Dublin. He is in strong opposition to [[Thomas Hobbes]] and [[Bernard de Mandeville|Mandeville]], and in fundamental agreement with Shaftesbury, whose name he rightly coupled with his own on the title page of the first two essays. The analogy drawn between beauty and virtue, the functions assigned to the moral sense, the position that the benevolent feelings form an original and irreducible part of our nature, and the unhesitating adoption of the principle that the test of virtuous action is its tendency to promote the general welfare are obvious and fundamental points of agreement between the two authors.
 
  
 
===Ethics===
 
===Ethics===
  
According to Hutcheson, man has a variety of senses, internal as well as external, reflex as well as direct, the general definition of a sense being" any determination of our minds to receive ideas independently on our will, and to have perceptions of pleasure and pain" (Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions, sect. 1). He does not attempt to give an exhaustive enumeration of these "senses," but, in various parts of his works, he specifies, besides the five external senses commonly recognized (which, he rightly hints, might be added to):
+
According to Hutcheson, humans have a variety of senses, internal as well as external, reflex as well as direct, the general definition of a sense being "any determination of our minds to receive ideas independently on our will, and to have perceptions of pleasure and pain" (''Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions,'' sect. 1). He does not attempt to give an exhaustive enumeration of these "senses," but, in various parts of his works, he specifies, besides the five external senses commonly recognized (which, he rightly hints, might be added to):
#consciousness, by which each man has a perception of himself and of all that is going on in his own mind (''Metaph. Syn. pars'' i. cap. 2)
 
#the sense of beauty (sometimes called specifically "an internal sense")
 
#a public sense, or ''sensus communis'', "a determination to be pleased with the happiness of others and to be uneasy at their misery"
 
#the moral sense, or "moral sense of beauty in actions and affections, by which we perceive virtue or vice, in ourselves or others"
 
#a sense of honour, or praise and blame, "which makes the approbation or gratitude of others the necessary occasion of pleasure, and their dislike, condemnation or resentment of injuries done by us the occasion of that uneasy sensation called shame"
 
#a sense of the ridiculous. It is plain, as the author confesses, that there may be "other perceptions, distinct from all these classes," and, in fact, there seems to be no limit to the number of "senses" in which a psychological division of this kind might result.
 
  
Of these "senses" that which plays the most important part in Hutcheson's ethical system is the "moral sense." It is this which pronounces immediately on the character of actions and affections, approving those which are virtuous, and disapproving those which are vicious. "His principal design," he says in the preface to the two first treatises, "is to show that human nature was not left quite indifferent in the affair of virtue, to form to itself observations concerning the advantage or disadvantage of actions, and accordingly to regulate its conduct. The weakness of our reason, and the avocations arising from the infirmity and necessities of our nature, are so great that very few men could ever have formed those long deductions of reasons which show some actions to be in the whole advantageous to the agent, and their contraries pernicious. The Author of nature has much better furnished us for a virtuous conduct than our moralists seem to imagine, by almost as quick and powerful instructions as we have for the preservation of our bodies. He has made virtue a lovely form, to excite our pursuit of it, and has given us strong affections to be the springs of each virtuous action."
+
#[[consciousness]], by which each human has a perception of himself and of all that is going on in his own mind (''Metaph. Syn. pars'' i. cap. 2)
 +
#the sense of [[beauty]] (sometimes called specifically "an internal sense")
 +
#a public sense, or ''sensus communism,'' "a determination to be pleased with the [[happiness]] of others and to be uneasy at their misery"
 +
#the moral sense, or "moral sense of beauty in actions and affections, by which we perceive [[virtue]] or vice, in ourselves or others"
 +
#a sense of honor, or praise and blame, "which makes the approbation or gratitude of others the necessary occasion of pleasure, and their dislike, condemnation or resentment of injuries done by us the occasion of that uneasy sensation called shame"
  
Though Hutcheson usually describes the moral faculty as acting instinctively and immediately, he does not, like Butler, confound the moral faculty with the moral standard. The test or criterion of right action is with Hutcheson, as with Shaftesbury, its tendency to promote the general welfare of mankind. He thus anticipates the utilitarianism of [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]]—and not only in principle, but even in the use of the phrase "the greatest happiness for the greatest number" (''Inquiry concerning Moral Good and Evil'', sect. 3).  Hutcheson does not seem to have seen an inconsistency between this external criterion with his fundamental ethical principle. Intuition has no possible connection with an empirical calculation of results, and Hutcheson in adopting such a criterion practically denies his fundamental assumption.  Connected with Hutcheson's virtual adoption of the utilitarian standard is a kind of moral algebra, proposed for the purpose of "computing the morality of actions." This calculus occurs in the ''Inquiry concerning Moral Good and Evil'', sect. 3.
+
It is plain, as the author confesses, that there may be "other perceptions, distinct from all these classes," and, in fact, there seems to be no limit to the number of "senses" in which a psychological division of this kind might result.
  
Hutcheson's other distinctive ethical doctrine is what has been called the "benevolent theory" of morals. Hobbes had maintained that all other actions, however disguised under apparent sympathy, have their roots in [[self-love]]. Hutcheson not only maintains that benevolence is the sole and direct source of many of our actions, but, by a not unnatural recoil, that it is the only source of those actions of which, on reflection, we approve. Consistently with this position, actions which flow from self-love only are pronounced to be morally indifferent. But surely, by the common consent of civilized men, prudence, temperance, cleanliness, industry, self-respect and, in general, the personal virtues," are regarded, and rightly regarded, as fitting objects of moral approbation. This consideration could hardly escape any author, however wedded to his own system, and Hutcheson attempts to extricate himself from the difficulty by laying down the position that a man may justly regard himself as a part of the rational system, and may thus be, in part, an object of his own benevolence (Ibid),—a curious abuse of terms, which really concedes the question at issue. Moreover, he acknowledges that, though self-love does not merit approbation, neither, except in its extreme forms, did it merit condemnation, indeed the satisfaction of the dictates of self love is one of the very conditions of the preservation of society. To press home the inconsistencies involved in these various statement would be a superfluous task.
+
Of these "senses," that which plays the most important part in Hutcheson's [[ethics|ethical]] system is the "moral sense." It is this which pronounces immediately on the character of actions and affections, approving those which are virtuous, and disapproving those which are vicious. "His principal design," he says in the preface to the two first treatises:
  
The vexed question of liberty and necessity appears to be carefully avoided in Hutcheson's professedly ethical works. But, in the ''Synopsis metaphysicae'', he touches on it in three places, briefly stating both sides of the question, but evidently inclining to that which he designates as the opinion of the Stoics in opposition to what he designates as the opinion of the Peripatetics. This is substantially the same as the doctrine propounded by Hobbes and [[John Locke|Locke]] (to the latter of whom Hutcheson refers in a note), namely that our will is determined by motives in conjunction with our general character and habit of mind, and that the only true liberty is the liberty of acting as we will, not the liberty of willing as we will. Though, however, his leaning is clear, he carefully avoids dogmatising, and deprecates the angry controversies to which the speculation on this subject had given rise.
+
<blockquote>is to show that human nature was not left quite indifferent in the affair of virtue, to form to itself observations concerning the advantage or disadvantage of actions, and accordingly to regulate its conduct. The weakness of our reason, and the avocations arising from the infirmity and necessities of our nature, are so great that very few men could ever have formed those long deductions of reasons which show some actions to be in the whole advantageous to the agent, and their contraries pernicious. The Author of nature has much better furnished us for a virtuous conduct than our moralists seem to imagine, by almost as quick and powerful instructions as we have for the preservation of our bodies. He has made virtue a lovely form, to excite our pursuit of it, and has given us strong affections to be the springs of each virtuous action.
 +
</blockquote>
 +
Though Hutcheson usually describes the moral faculty as acting instinctively and immediately, he does not confound the moral faculty with the moral standard. The test or criterion of right action is with Hutcheson its tendency to promote the general welfare of mankind. He thus anticipates the utilitarianism of [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]]—and not only in principle, but even in Hutcheson’s use of the phrase "the greatest happiness for the greatest number" (''Inquiry Concerning Moral Good and Evil'', sect. 3). Hutcheson does not seem to have seen an inconsistency between this external criterion with his fundamental ethical principle. Intuition has no possible connection with an empirical calculation of results, and Hutcheson in adopting such a criterion practically denies his fundamental assumption. Connected with Hutcheson's virtual adoption of the utilitarian standard is a kind of moral [[algebra]], proposed for the purpose of "computing the morality of actions." This calculus occurs in the ''Inquiry concerning Moral Good and Evil,'' sect. 3.
  
It is easy to trace the influence of Hutcheson's ethical theories on the systems of Hume and [[Adam Smith]]. The prominence given to these writers to the analysis of moral action and moral approbation with the attempt to discriminate the respective provinces of the reason and the emotions in these processes, is undoubtedly due to the influence of Hutcheson. To a study of the writings of Shaftesbury and Hutcheson we might, probably, in large measure, attribute the unequivocal adoption of the utilitarian standard by Hume, and, if this be the case, the name of Hutcheson connects itself, through Hume, with the names of [[Joseph Priestley|Priestley]], [[William Paley|Paley]] and Bentham. [[Joseph Butler|Butler]]'s ''Sermons'' appeared in 1726, the year after the publication of Hutcheson's two first essays, and the parallelism between the "conscience" of the one writer and the "moral sense" of the other is, at least, worthy of remark.
+
Hutcheson's other distinctive ethical doctrine is what has been called the "benevolent theory" of morals. In this theory, he stands in sharp opposition to the philosophy of [[Thomas Hobbes]] and other egoists. Hobbes had maintained that all other actions, however disguised under apparent sympathy, have their roots in selfishness. Hutcheson not only maintains that benevolence is the sole and direct source of many actions, but, by a natural recoil that it is the only source of those actions of which, on reflection, people approve. Consistently with this position, actions which flow from self-love only are pronounced to be morally indifferent. But surely, by the common consent of civilized men, prudence, temperance, cleanliness, industry, self-respect and, in general, the personal virtues, are regarded, and rightly regarded, as fitting objects of moral approbation. This consideration could hardly escape any author, however wedded to his own system, and Hutcheson attempts to extricate himself from the difficulty by laying down the position that a man may justly regard himself as a part of the rational system, and may thus be, in part, an object of his own benevolence (Ibid)—a curious abuse of terms, which really concedes the question at issue. Moreover, he acknowledges that, though self-love does not merit approbation, neither, except in its extreme forms, did it merit condemnation, indeed the satisfaction of the dictates of self love is one of the very conditions of the preservation of society. To press home the inconsistencies involved in these various statements would be a superfluous task.
  
===Mental Philosophy===
+
===Aesthetics===
  
In the sphere of mental philosophy and logic Hutcheson's contributions are by no means so important or original as in that of moral philosophy. They are interesting mainly as a link between Locke and the Scottish school. In the former subject the influence of Locke is apparent throughout. All the main outlines of Locke's philosophy seem, at first sight, to be accepted as a matter of course. Thus, in stating his theory of the moral sense, Hutcheson is peculiarly careful to repudiate the doctrine of innate ideas (see, for instance, ''Inquiry concerning Moral Good and Evil'', sect. I ad fin., and sect. 4; and compare ''Synopsis Metaphysicae'', pars i. cap. 2). At the same time he shows more discrimination than does Locke in distinguishing between the two uses of this expression, and between the legitimate and illegitimate form of the doctrine (''Syn. Metaph.'' pars i. cap. 2).
+
Hutcheson may further be regarded as one of the earliest modern writers on aesthetics. His speculations on this subject are contained in the ''Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony and Design,'' the first of the two treatises published in 1725. He maintains that humans are endowed with a special sense by which they perceive beauty, harmony, and proportion. This is a reflex sense, because it presupposes the action of the external senses of sight and hearing. It may be called an internal sense, both in order to distinguish its perceptions from the mere perceptions of sight and hearing, and because "in some other affairs, where our external senses are not much concerned, we discern a sort of beauty, very like in many respects to that observed in sensible objects, and accompanied with like pleasure" (''Inquiry'', etc., sect. 1). The latter reason leads him to call attention to the beauty perceived in universal truths, in the operations of general causes and in moral principles and actions.  
  
All our ideas are, as by Locke, referred to external or internal sense, or, in other words, to sensation and reflection. It is, however, a most important modification of Locke's doctrine, and one which connects Hutcheson's mental philosophy with that of [[Thomas Reid|Reid]], when he states that the ideas of extension, figure, motion and rest "are more properly ideas accompanying the sensations of sight and touch than the sensations of either of these senses"; that the idea of self accompanies every thought, and that the ideas of number, duration and existence accompany every other idea whatsoever (see ''Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions'', sect. i. art. I; ''Syn. Metaph''. pars i. cap. 1, pars ii. cap. I; Hamilton on Reid, p. 124, note). Other important points in which Hutcheson follows the lead of Locke are his depreciation of the importance of the so-called laws of thought, his distinction between the primary and secondary qualities of bodies, the position that we cannot know the inmost essences of things ("''intimae rerum naturae sive essentiae''"), though they excite various ideas in us, and the assumption that external things are known only through the medium of ideas (''Syn. Metaph''. pars i. cap. I), though, at the same time, we are assured of the existence of an external world corresponding to these ideas.
+
Hutcheson's writings naturally gave rise to much controversy. To say nothing of minor opponents, such as "Philaretus" (Gilbert Burnet, already alluded to), Dr John Balguy (1686-1748), prebendary of Salisbury, the author of two tracts on "The Foundation of Moral Goodness," and Dr John Taylor (1694-1761) of Norwich, a minister of considerable reputation in his time (author of ''An Examination of the Scheme of Amorality Advanced by Dr Hutcheson''), the essays appear to have suggested, by antagonism, at least two works which hold a permanent place in the literature of English ethics—Butler's ''Dissertation on the Nature of Virtue,'' and [[Richard Price]]'s ''Treatise of Moral Good and Evil'' (1757). In this latter work, the author maintains, in opposition to Hutcheson, that actions are in themselves right or wrong, that right and wrong are simple ideas incapable of analysis, and that these ideas are perceived immediately by the understanding.  
  
Hutcheson attempts to account for our assurance of the reality of an external world by referring it to a natural instinct (''Syn. Metaph''. pars i. cap. 1). Of the correspondence or similitude between our ideas of the primary qualities of things and the things themselves God alone can be assigned as the cause. This similitude has been effected by Him through a law of nature. "''Haec prima qualitatum primariarum perceptio, sive mentis actio quaedam sive passio dicatur, non alia similitudinis aut convenientiae inter ejusmodi ideas et res ipsas causa assignari posse videtur, quam ipse Deus, qui certa naturae lege hoc efilcit, Ut notiones, quae rebus praesentibus excitantur, sint ipsis similes, aut saltem earum habitudines, si non veras quantitates, depingant''" (pars ii. cap. I). Locke does speak of God "annexing" certain ideas to certain motions of bodies; but nowhere does he propound a theory so definite as that here propounded by Hutcheson, which reminds us at least as much of the speculations of [[Nicolas Malebranche]] as of those of Locke.
+
==Other works==
  
Amongst the more important points in which Hutcheson diverges from Locke is his account of the idea of personal identity, which he appears to have regarded as made known to us directly by consciousness. The distinction between body and mind, ''corpus'' or ''materia'' and ''res cogitans'', is more emphatically accentuated by Hutcheson than by Locke. Generally, he speaks as if we had a direct consciousness of mind as distinct from body, though, in the posthumous work on ''Moral Philosophy'', he expressly states that we know mind as we know body" by qualities immediately perceived though the substance of both be unknown (bk. i. ch. 1). The distinction between perception proper and sensation proper, which occurs by implication though it is not explicitly worked out (see Hamilton's Lectures on Metaphysics, - Lect. 24).
+
In addition to the works named, the following were published during Hutcheson's lifetime: A pamphlet entitled ''Considerations on Patronage'' (1735); ''Philosophiae moralis institutio compendiaria, ethices et jurisprudentiae naturalis elementa continens,'' lib. iii. (Glasgow, 1742); and ''Metaphysicae synopsis ontologiam et pneumatologiam campleciens'' (Glasgow, 1742). The last work was published anonymously. After his death, his son, Francis Hutcheson published the longest of his works, ''A System of Moral Philosophy, in Three Books'' (2 vols. London, 1755). The only remaining work assigned to Hutcheson is a small treatise on Logic (Glasgow, 1764). This compendium, together with the ''Compendium of Metaphysics,'' was republished at Strassburg in 1722.
  
Hamilton's edition of [[Dugald Stewart]]'s Works, v. 420),—the imperfection of the ordinary division of the external senses into two classes, the limitation of consciousness to a special mental facult) (severely criticized in Sir W Hamilton's ''Lectures on Metaphysics'' Lect. xii.) and the disposition to refer on disputed questions of philosophy not so much to formal arguments as to the testimony of consciousness and our natural instincts are also amongst the points in which Hutcheson supplemented or departed from the philosophy of Locke. The last point can hardly fail to suggest the "common-sense philosophy" of Reid.
+
Notices of Hutcheson occur in histories, both of general philosophy and of moral philosophy, as, for instance, in pt. vii. of Adam Smith's ''Theory of Moral Sentiments;'' Mackintosh's ''Progress of Ethical Philosophy;'' [[Victor Cousin|Cousin]], ''Cours d'histoire de la philosophie morale du XVIII' siècle;'' Whewell's ''Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy in England;'' [[Alexander Bain|A Bain]]'s ''Mental and Moral Science;'' [[Noah Porter]]'s Appendix to the English translation of [[Ueberweg]]'s ''History of Philosophy;'' Sir Leslie Stephen's ''History of English Thought in the Eighteenth Gentury,'' etc.  
 
 
Thus, in estimating Hutcheson's position, we find that in particular questions he stands nearer to Locke, but in the general spirit of his philosophy he seems to approach more closely to his Scottish successors.
 
 
 
The short ''Compendium of Logic'', which is more original than such works usually are, is remarkable chiefly for the large proportion of psychological matter which it contains. In these parts of the book Hutcheson mainly follows Locke. The technicalities of the subject are passed lightly over, and the book is readable. It may be specially noticed that he distinguishes between the mental result and its verbal expression judgment-proposition, that he constantly employs the word "idea," and that he defines logical truth as "''convenientia signorum cum rebus significatis''" (or "''propositionis convenientia cum rebus ipsis''," ''Syn. Metaph.'' pars i. cap 3), thus implicitly repudiating a merely formal view of logic.
 
 
 
===Aesthetics===
 
  
Hutcheson may further be regarded as one of the earliest modern writers on aesthetics. His speculations on this subject are contained in the ''Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony and Design'', the first of the two treatises published in 1725. He maintains that we are endowed with a special sense by which we perceive beauty, harmony and proportion. This is a reflex sense, because it presupposes the action of the external senses of sight and hearing. It may be called an internal sense, both in order to distinguish its perceptions from the mere perceptions of sight and hearing, and because "in some other affairs, where our external senses are not much concerned, we discern a sort of beauty, very like in many respects to that observed in sensible objects, and accompanied with like pleasure" (''Inquiry'', etc., sect. 1). The latter reason leads him to call attention to the beauty perceived in universal truths, in the operations of general causes and in moral principles and actions. Thus, the analogy between beauty and virtue, which was so favourite a topic with Shaftesbury, is prominent in the writings of Hutcheson also. Scattered up and down the treatise there are many important and interesting observations which our limits prevent us from noticing. But to the student of mental philosophy it may be specially interesting to remark that Hutcheson both applies the principle of association to explain our ideas of beauty and also sets limits to its application, insisting on there being "a natural power of perception or sense of beauty in objects, antecedent to all custom, education or example" (see Inquiry, etc., sects. 6, 7; Hamilton's ''Lectures on Metaphysics'', Lect. 44 C.E. fin.).
+
==References==
 +
*Aschenbrenner, Karl and Arnold Isenberg. ''Aesthetic Theories: Studies in the Philosophy of Art.'' Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1965.
 +
*Blackstone, William T. ''Francis Hutcheson and Contemporary Ethical Theory.'' Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1965.
 +
*Brown, Michael. ''Francis Hutcheson in Dublin, 1719-30: The Crucible of His Thought.'' Dublin: Four Courts Press, 2002. ISBN 1851826378
 +
*Carey, Daniel. ''Locke, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson: Contesting Diversity in the Enlightenment and Beyond.'' Cambridge University Press, 2006. ISBN 0521845025
 +
*Fowler, Thomas. ''Shaftesbury and Hutcheson.'' Adamant Media Corporation, 2005. ISBN 1402197144
 +
*Hutcheson, Francis and Wolfgang Leidhold. ''An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises.'' Indianapolis, Ind: Liberty Fund, 2004. ISBN 0865974284
 +
*Hutcheson, Francis, et al. ''Francis Hutcheson: An Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design.'' Archives internationales d'histoire des idées. Series minor, 9. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973. ISBN 9789024715459
 +
*Hutcheson, Francis, et al. ''Logic, Metaphysics, and the Natural Sociability of Mankind.'' Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2006. ISBN 0865974462
 +
*Hutcheson, Francis. ''An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections; With Illustrations on the Moral Sense.'' Gainesville, Fla: Scholars' Facsimiles & Reprints, 1969. ISBN 0820110582
 +
*Kivy, Peter. ''The Seventh Sense: Francis Hutcheson and Eighteenth-Century British Aesthetics.'' Oxford University Press, 2003. ISBN 0199260028
 +
*Scott, William Robert. ''Francis Hutcheson: His Life, Teaching And Position In The History Of Philosophy.'' Kessinger Publishing, LLC, 2006. ISBN 1428614796
 +
*{{1911}}
  
Hutcheson's writings naturally gave rise to much controversy. To say nothing of minor opponents, such as "Philaretus" (Gilbert Burnet, already alluded to), Dr John Balguy (1686-1748), prebendary of Salisbury, the author of two tracts on "The Foundation of Moral Goodness, and Dr John Taylor (1694-1761) of Norwich, a minister of considerable reputation in his time (author of ''An Examination of the Scheme of Amorality advanced by Dr Hutcheson''), the essays appear to have suggested, by antagonism, at least two works which hold a permanent place in the literature of English ethics—Butler's ''Dissertation on the Nature of Virtue'', and [[Richard Price]]'s ''Treatise of Moral Good and Evil'' (1757). In this latter work the author maintains, in opposition to Hutcheson, that actions are -in themselves right or wrong, that right and wrong are simple ideas incapable of analysis, and that these ideas are perceived immediately by the understanding. We thus see that, not only directly but also through the replies which it called forth, the system of Hutcheson, or at least the system of Hutcheson combined with that of Shaftesbury, contributed, in large measure, to the formation and development of some of the most important of the modern schools of ethics.
+
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved April 9, 2024.
  
===Authorities===
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scottish-18th/ Scottish philosophy in the 18th Century]. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/emotions-17th18th/LD7Hutcheson.html Francis Hutcheson on the Emotions]. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
 +
*[http://socserv.mcmaster.ca/econ/ugcm/3ll3/hutcheson/remarks.htm Remarks upon the Fable of the Bees]. by Frances Hutcheson 1750.
  
Notices of Hutcheson occur in histories, both of general philosophy and of moral philosophy, as, for instance, in pt. vii. of Adam Smith's ''Theory of Moral Sentiments''; Mackintosh's ''Progress of Ethical Philosophy''; [[Victor Cousin|Cousin]], ''Cours d'histoire de la philosophie morale du XVIII' siècle''; Whewell's ''Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy in England''; [[Alexander Bain|A Bain]]'s ''Mental and Moral Science''; [[Noah Porter]]'s Appendix to the English translation of [[Ueberweg]]'s ''History of Philosophy''; Sir Leslie Stephen's ''History of English Thought in the Eighteenth Gentury'', etc. See also Martineau, ''Types of Ethical Theory'' (London, 1902); WR Scott, ''Francis Hutcheson'' (Cambridge, 1900); Albee, ''History of English Utilitarianism'' (London, 1902); T Fowler, ''Shaftesbury and Hutcheson'' (London, 1882); James McCosh, ''Scottish Philosophy'' (New York, 1874). Of Dr Leechman's Biography of Hutcheson we have already spoken. Veitch gives an interesting account of his professorial work in Glasgow, ''Mind'', ii. 209-212.
+
===General philosophy sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].  
  
{{1911}}
 
  
[[Category:18th century philosophers|Hutcheson]]
+
[[Category:philosophers]]  
[[Category:Early modern philosophers|Hutcheson]]
 
[[Category:Empiricists|Hutcheson]]
 
[[Category:Enlightenment philosophers|Hutcheson]]
 
[[Category:Theologians|Hutcheson]]
 
  
 
{{credit|70264159}}
 
{{credit|70264159}}

Latest revision as of 04:50, 9 April 2024

Francis Hutcheson

Francis Hutcheson (August 8, 1694 – August 8, 1746) was an Irish philosopher and one of the founding fathers of the Scottish Enlightenment. Although his philosophy covers a wide range of subjects, he is known primarily for his moral theory and his study of aesthetics. His ideas include the concepts of the "moral sense" and the "benevolent theory" of morals, the latter for which he stood in sharp opposition to Thomas Hobbes and other egoists. He anticipates the utilitarianism of Jeremy Bentham in his use of the phrase "the greatest happiness for the greatest number," and his influence can be traced through his students, which include David Hume and Adam Smith.

Beginnings

Hutcheson is thought to have been born at Drumalig, in the parish of Saintfield, County Down, Northern Ireland, to a Presbyterian minister. He spent six years at the University of Glasgow, first in the study of philosophy, classics, and general literature, and afterwards in the study of theology.

On leaving university, he returned to Northern Ireland, and received a license to preach. When, however, he was about to enter upon the pastorate of a small, dissenting congregation, he changed his plans on the advice of a friend and opened a private academy in Dublin. While residing in Dublin, Hutcheson published anonymously the four essays by which he is best known: the Inquiry concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony and Design, the Inquiry Concerning Moral Good and Evil, in 1725, and the Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections and Illustrations upon the Moral Sense, in 1728. The alterations and additions made in the second edition of these essays were published in a separate form in 1726. To the period of his Dublin residence are also to be referred the Thoughts on Laughter (a criticism of Thomas Hobbes) and the Observations on the Fable of the Bees, being in all six letters contributed to Hibernicus' Letters, a periodical which appeared in Dublin (1725-1727, 2nd ed. 1734). At the end of the same period occurred the controversy in the London Journal with Gilbert Burnet; on the "True Foundation of Virtue or Moral Goodness." All these letters were collected in one volume (Glasgow, 1772).

In 1729, Hutcheson succeeded his old master, Gershom Carmichael, in the chair of moral philosophy at the University of Glasgow. Yet the works on which Hutcheson's reputation rests had already been published.

Philosophy

Hutcheson dealt with metaphysics, logic, and ethics, but he is primarily known for his contributions to moral theory and the field of aesthetics. His works expound on various ideas including the relationship between beauty and virtue, the functions assigned to the moral sense, and the position that the benevolent feelings form an original and irreducible part of our nature.

Ethics

According to Hutcheson, humans have a variety of senses, internal as well as external, reflex as well as direct, the general definition of a sense being "any determination of our minds to receive ideas independently on our will, and to have perceptions of pleasure and pain" (Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions, sect. 1). He does not attempt to give an exhaustive enumeration of these "senses," but, in various parts of his works, he specifies, besides the five external senses commonly recognized (which, he rightly hints, might be added to):

  1. consciousness, by which each human has a perception of himself and of all that is going on in his own mind (Metaph. Syn. pars i. cap. 2)
  2. the sense of beauty (sometimes called specifically "an internal sense")
  3. a public sense, or sensus communism, "a determination to be pleased with the happiness of others and to be uneasy at their misery"
  4. the moral sense, or "moral sense of beauty in actions and affections, by which we perceive virtue or vice, in ourselves or others"
  5. a sense of honor, or praise and blame, "which makes the approbation or gratitude of others the necessary occasion of pleasure, and their dislike, condemnation or resentment of injuries done by us the occasion of that uneasy sensation called shame"

It is plain, as the author confesses, that there may be "other perceptions, distinct from all these classes," and, in fact, there seems to be no limit to the number of "senses" in which a psychological division of this kind might result.

Of these "senses," that which plays the most important part in Hutcheson's ethical system is the "moral sense." It is this which pronounces immediately on the character of actions and affections, approving those which are virtuous, and disapproving those which are vicious. "His principal design," he says in the preface to the two first treatises:

is to show that human nature was not left quite indifferent in the affair of virtue, to form to itself observations concerning the advantage or disadvantage of actions, and accordingly to regulate its conduct. The weakness of our reason, and the avocations arising from the infirmity and necessities of our nature, are so great that very few men could ever have formed those long deductions of reasons which show some actions to be in the whole advantageous to the agent, and their contraries pernicious. The Author of nature has much better furnished us for a virtuous conduct than our moralists seem to imagine, by almost as quick and powerful instructions as we have for the preservation of our bodies. He has made virtue a lovely form, to excite our pursuit of it, and has given us strong affections to be the springs of each virtuous action.

Though Hutcheson usually describes the moral faculty as acting instinctively and immediately, he does not confound the moral faculty with the moral standard. The test or criterion of right action is with Hutcheson its tendency to promote the general welfare of mankind. He thus anticipates the utilitarianism of Bentham—and not only in principle, but even in Hutcheson’s use of the phrase "the greatest happiness for the greatest number" (Inquiry Concerning Moral Good and Evil, sect. 3). Hutcheson does not seem to have seen an inconsistency between this external criterion with his fundamental ethical principle. Intuition has no possible connection with an empirical calculation of results, and Hutcheson in adopting such a criterion practically denies his fundamental assumption. Connected with Hutcheson's virtual adoption of the utilitarian standard is a kind of moral algebra, proposed for the purpose of "computing the morality of actions." This calculus occurs in the Inquiry concerning Moral Good and Evil, sect. 3.

Hutcheson's other distinctive ethical doctrine is what has been called the "benevolent theory" of morals. In this theory, he stands in sharp opposition to the philosophy of Thomas Hobbes and other egoists. Hobbes had maintained that all other actions, however disguised under apparent sympathy, have their roots in selfishness. Hutcheson not only maintains that benevolence is the sole and direct source of many actions, but, by a natural recoil that it is the only source of those actions of which, on reflection, people approve. Consistently with this position, actions which flow from self-love only are pronounced to be morally indifferent. But surely, by the common consent of civilized men, prudence, temperance, cleanliness, industry, self-respect and, in general, the personal virtues, are regarded, and rightly regarded, as fitting objects of moral approbation. This consideration could hardly escape any author, however wedded to his own system, and Hutcheson attempts to extricate himself from the difficulty by laying down the position that a man may justly regard himself as a part of the rational system, and may thus be, in part, an object of his own benevolence (Ibid)—a curious abuse of terms, which really concedes the question at issue. Moreover, he acknowledges that, though self-love does not merit approbation, neither, except in its extreme forms, did it merit condemnation, indeed the satisfaction of the dictates of self love is one of the very conditions of the preservation of society. To press home the inconsistencies involved in these various statements would be a superfluous task.

Aesthetics

Hutcheson may further be regarded as one of the earliest modern writers on aesthetics. His speculations on this subject are contained in the Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony and Design, the first of the two treatises published in 1725. He maintains that humans are endowed with a special sense by which they perceive beauty, harmony, and proportion. This is a reflex sense, because it presupposes the action of the external senses of sight and hearing. It may be called an internal sense, both in order to distinguish its perceptions from the mere perceptions of sight and hearing, and because "in some other affairs, where our external senses are not much concerned, we discern a sort of beauty, very like in many respects to that observed in sensible objects, and accompanied with like pleasure" (Inquiry, etc., sect. 1). The latter reason leads him to call attention to the beauty perceived in universal truths, in the operations of general causes and in moral principles and actions.

Hutcheson's writings naturally gave rise to much controversy. To say nothing of minor opponents, such as "Philaretus" (Gilbert Burnet, already alluded to), Dr John Balguy (1686-1748), prebendary of Salisbury, the author of two tracts on "The Foundation of Moral Goodness," and Dr John Taylor (1694-1761) of Norwich, a minister of considerable reputation in his time (author of An Examination of the Scheme of Amorality Advanced by Dr Hutcheson), the essays appear to have suggested, by antagonism, at least two works which hold a permanent place in the literature of English ethics—Butler's Dissertation on the Nature of Virtue, and Richard Price's Treatise of Moral Good and Evil (1757). In this latter work, the author maintains, in opposition to Hutcheson, that actions are in themselves right or wrong, that right and wrong are simple ideas incapable of analysis, and that these ideas are perceived immediately by the understanding.

Other works

In addition to the works named, the following were published during Hutcheson's lifetime: A pamphlet entitled Considerations on Patronage (1735); Philosophiae moralis institutio compendiaria, ethices et jurisprudentiae naturalis elementa continens, lib. iii. (Glasgow, 1742); and Metaphysicae synopsis ontologiam et pneumatologiam campleciens (Glasgow, 1742). The last work was published anonymously. After his death, his son, Francis Hutcheson published the longest of his works, A System of Moral Philosophy, in Three Books (2 vols. London, 1755). The only remaining work assigned to Hutcheson is a small treatise on Logic (Glasgow, 1764). This compendium, together with the Compendium of Metaphysics, was republished at Strassburg in 1722.

Notices of Hutcheson occur in histories, both of general philosophy and of moral philosophy, as, for instance, in pt. vii. of Adam Smith's Theory of Moral Sentiments; Mackintosh's Progress of Ethical Philosophy; Cousin, Cours d'histoire de la philosophie morale du XVIII' siècle; Whewell's Lectures on the History of Moral Philosophy in England; A Bain's Mental and Moral Science; Noah Porter's Appendix to the English translation of Ueberweg's History of Philosophy; Sir Leslie Stephen's History of English Thought in the Eighteenth Gentury, etc.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Aschenbrenner, Karl and Arnold Isenberg. Aesthetic Theories: Studies in the Philosophy of Art. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1965.
  • Blackstone, William T. Francis Hutcheson and Contemporary Ethical Theory. Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1965.
  • Brown, Michael. Francis Hutcheson in Dublin, 1719-30: The Crucible of His Thought. Dublin: Four Courts Press, 2002. ISBN 1851826378
  • Carey, Daniel. Locke, Shaftesbury, and Hutcheson: Contesting Diversity in the Enlightenment and Beyond. Cambridge University Press, 2006. ISBN 0521845025
  • Fowler, Thomas. Shaftesbury and Hutcheson. Adamant Media Corporation, 2005. ISBN 1402197144
  • Hutcheson, Francis and Wolfgang Leidhold. An Inquiry into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue: In Two Treatises. Indianapolis, Ind: Liberty Fund, 2004. ISBN 0865974284
  • Hutcheson, Francis, et al. Francis Hutcheson: An Inquiry Concerning Beauty, Order, Harmony, Design. Archives internationales d'histoire des idées. Series minor, 9. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1973. ISBN 9789024715459
  • Hutcheson, Francis, et al. Logic, Metaphysics, and the Natural Sociability of Mankind. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 2006. ISBN 0865974462
  • Hutcheson, Francis. An Essay on the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections; With Illustrations on the Moral Sense. Gainesville, Fla: Scholars' Facsimiles & Reprints, 1969. ISBN 0820110582
  • Kivy, Peter. The Seventh Sense: Francis Hutcheson and Eighteenth-Century British Aesthetics. Oxford University Press, 2003. ISBN 0199260028
  • Scott, William Robert. Francis Hutcheson: His Life, Teaching And Position In The History Of Philosophy. Kessinger Publishing, LLC, 2006. ISBN 1428614796
  • This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.

External links

All links retrieved April 9, 2024.

General philosophy sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.