Difference between revisions of "Omnipotence" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 17: Line 17:
  
 
===Able to do whatever is not intrinsically impossible===
 
===Able to do whatever is not intrinsically impossible===
[[Thomas Aquinas]] acknowledged difficulty in comprehending God's power. Aquinas wrote that "All confess that God is omnipotent; but it seems difficult to explain in what His omnipotence precisely consists."<ref>Christian Classics Ethereal Library, [http://www.ccel.org/a/aquinas/summa/FP/FP025.html#FPQ25A3THEP1 ''Summa Theologica'', first part, question 25, article 3.] Retrieved October 27, 2007.</ref> In the scholastic understanding, omnipotence is generally understood to be compatible with certain limitations upon God's power, as opposed to implying infinite abilities. There are certain things that even an omnipotent God cannot do. Medieval theologians drew attention to some fairly trivial examples of restrictions upon the power of God. The statement "God can do anything" is only sensible with an assumed suppressed clause, "that implies the perfection of true power." This standard scholastic answer allows that creaturely acts, such as walking, can be performed by humans but not by God. Rather than an advantage in power, human acts such as walking, sitting or giving birth were possible only because of a ''defect'' in human power. The ability to [[sin]], for example, is not a power, but a defect or an infirmity. In response to questions of God performing impossibilities (such as making square circles) Aquinas says that "Nothing which implies contradiction falls under the omnipotence of God."<ref>St. Thomas Aquinas. [http://www.ccel.org/a/aquinas/summa/FP/FP025.html#FPQ25A3THEP1 Whether God is omnipotent?] Retrieved November 27, 2007.</ref>
+
This second position has been developed since the Middle Ages and is accepted by most Christians. In the scholastic understanding, omnipotence is generally understood to be compatible with certain limitations upon God's power, as opposed to implying infinite abilities. There are certain things that even an omnipotent God cannot do. They are "intrinsically impossible" things. According to Thomas Aquinas, "whatever implies contradiction does not come within the scope of divine omnipotence, because it cannot have the aspect of possibility."<ref>Christian Classics Ethereal Library, [http://www.ccel.org/a/aquinas/summa/FP/FP025.html#FPQ25A3THEP1 ''Summa Theologica'', I, 25, 3.] Retrieved June 24, 2008.</ref> First of all, God cannot do anything which would contradict his nature. For example, God cannot sin, since to sin is repugnant to God's nature. To sin is repugnant to omnipotence anyway: "To sin is to fall short of a perfect action; hence to be able to sin is to be able to fall short in action, which is repugnant to omnipotence."<ref>Ibid.</ref> Second, God cannot do anything which would be logically impossible. For example, God cannot make a man who is at the same time a donkey, for in the statement that a man is a donkey "the predicate is altogether incompatible with the subject."<ref>Ibid.</ref>
  
In recent times, [[C.S. Lewis]] has adopted a scholastic position in the course of his work, ''[[The Problem of Pain]].'' Lewis follows Aquinas' view on contradiction:<blockquote>
+
In recent times, [[C.S. Lewis]] has adopted a scholastic position in the course of his work, ''The Problem of Pain]''. Lewis follows Aquinas' view on contradiction:
His Omnipotence means power to do all that is intrinsically possible, not to do the intrinsically impossible. You may attribute miracles to Him, but not nonsense. This is no limit to His power. If you choose to say "God can give a creature free will and at the same time withhold free will from it," you have not succeeded in saying ''anything'' about God: Meaningless combinations of words do not suddenly acquire meaning simply because we prefix to them the two other words "God can."… It is no more possible for God than for the weakest of His creatures to carry out both of two mutually exclusive alternatives; not because His power meets an obstacle, but because nonsense remains nonsense even when we talk it about God (Lewis, 18).</blockquote>
+
 
 +
<blockquote>His Omnipotence means power to do all that is intrinsically possible, not to do the intrinsically impossible. You may attribute miracles to Him, but not nonsense. This is no limit to His power. If you choose to say "God can give a creature free will and at the same time withhold free will from it," you have not succeeded in saying ''anything'' about God: Meaningless combinations of words do not suddenly acquire meaning simply because we prefix to them the two other words "God can."… It is no more possible for God than for the weakest of His creatures to carry out both of two mutually exclusive alternatives; not because His power meets an obstacle, but because nonsense remains nonsense even when we talk it about God (Lewis, 18).</blockquote>
 +
 
 +
Medieval theologians drew attention to some fairly trivial examples of restrictions upon the power of God. The statement "God can do anything" is only sensible with an assumed suppressed clause, "that implies the perfection of true power." This standard scholastic answer allows that creaturely acts, such as walking, can be performed by humans but not by God. Rather than an advantage in power, human acts such as walking, sitting or giving birth were possible only because of a ''defect'' in human power. The ability to [[sin]], for example, is not a power, but a defect or an infirmity. In response to questions of God performing impossibilities (such as making square circles)
  
 
== Rejection or limitation of omnipotence ==
 
== Rejection or limitation of omnipotence ==

Revision as of 16:36, 24 June 2008

Omnipotence (literally, "all power") is power without limits. Monotheistic religions generally attribute omnipotence only to God. In the philosophy of most Western monotheistic religions, omnipotence is listed as one of God's characteristics among many, including omniscience, omnipresence, and benevolence.

Theodicy is the study of the question regarding the coexistence of evil and an omnipotent God in the philosophy of religion.

Different Views of Omnipotence

Between people of different faiths, or indeed even between people of the same faith, the term, "omnipotent," has been used to connote a few different positions. These positions include, but are not limited to, the following:

  1. God is literally able to do anything; that is, the answer to "Can God do x?" is always "yes," regardless of what x may be.
  2. God is able to do whatever is not "intrinsically impossible."[1] "Intrinsically impossible" things include: 1) things which would not be in accord with God's nature (e.g., sinning or lying); and 2) things which would be logically impossible, connoting mutually repellent elements simultaneously (e.g., a squire circle).
  3. It is part of God's nature to be consistent, and it would be inconsistent for him to go against his own laws unless there were a reason to do so.[2]

However, on all understandings of Omnipotence, it is generally held that God is able to intervene in the world by superseding the laws of physics, since they are not part of his nature, but the principles upon which he created the physical world. However, many modern scholars (such as John Polkinghorne) hold that it is part of God's nature to be consistent and that it would be inconsistent for God to go against His own laws unless there were an overwhelming reason to do so.

Literally able to do anything

For some thists such as René Descartes, omnipotence means that God is literally able to do anything. God is not only able to perform such biblical miracles as parting the Read Sea and stilling the Sun in the sky, but is also able to perform feats that seem to be intrinsically impossible such as making a square circle, making 2+2=5, and even doing things against his nature. This, of course, leads to obvious contradictions and is not a widely held view by philosophically aware theologians, but those who adhere to it usually argue that to try and rationalize God's omnipotent power is a vain undertaking since one cannot ever really understand God's power, and it is perhaps better to take it on faith. Descartes indicated his idea in his Meditations on First Philosophy that trying to develop a theory to explain, assign, or reject omnipotence on grounds of logic has little merit, since being omnipotent would mean that the omnipotent being is above logic. Similarly, according to Hindu philosophy, the essence of God or Brahman can never be understood or known, since Brahman is beyond both existence and non-existence, transcending and including time, causation, and space, and thus can never be known in the same material sense as one traditionally "understands" a given concept or object.[3]

Able to do whatever is not intrinsically impossible

This second position has been developed since the Middle Ages and is accepted by most Christians. In the scholastic understanding, omnipotence is generally understood to be compatible with certain limitations upon God's power, as opposed to implying infinite abilities. There are certain things that even an omnipotent God cannot do. They are "intrinsically impossible" things. According to Thomas Aquinas, "whatever implies contradiction does not come within the scope of divine omnipotence, because it cannot have the aspect of possibility."[4] First of all, God cannot do anything which would contradict his nature. For example, God cannot sin, since to sin is repugnant to God's nature. To sin is repugnant to omnipotence anyway: "To sin is to fall short of a perfect action; hence to be able to sin is to be able to fall short in action, which is repugnant to omnipotence."[5] Second, God cannot do anything which would be logically impossible. For example, God cannot make a man who is at the same time a donkey, for in the statement that a man is a donkey "the predicate is altogether incompatible with the subject."[6]

In recent times, C.S. Lewis has adopted a scholastic position in the course of his work, The Problem of Pain]. Lewis follows Aquinas' view on contradiction:

His Omnipotence means power to do all that is intrinsically possible, not to do the intrinsically impossible. You may attribute miracles to Him, but not nonsense. This is no limit to His power. If you choose to say "God can give a creature free will and at the same time withhold free will from it," you have not succeeded in saying anything about God: Meaningless combinations of words do not suddenly acquire meaning simply because we prefix to them the two other words "God can."… It is no more possible for God than for the weakest of His creatures to carry out both of two mutually exclusive alternatives; not because His power meets an obstacle, but because nonsense remains nonsense even when we talk it about God (Lewis, 18).

Medieval theologians drew attention to some fairly trivial examples of restrictions upon the power of God. The statement "God can do anything" is only sensible with an assumed suppressed clause, "that implies the perfection of true power." This standard scholastic answer allows that creaturely acts, such as walking, can be performed by humans but not by God. Rather than an advantage in power, human acts such as walking, sitting or giving birth were possible only because of a defect in human power. The ability to sin, for example, is not a power, but a defect or an infirmity. In response to questions of God performing impossibilities (such as making square circles)

Rejection or limitation of omnipotence

Some monotheists reject the view that God is or could be omnipotent, or take the view that, by choosing to create creatures with freewill, God has chosen to limit divine omnipotence. In Conservative and Reform Judaism, and some movements within Protestant Christianity, including process theology and open theism, God is said to act in the world through persuasion, and not by coercion (for open theism, this is a matter of choice—God could act miraculously, and perhaps on occasion does so—while for process theism it is a matter of necessity—creatures have inherent powers that God cannot, even in principle, override). God is manifest in the world through inspiration and the creation of possibility, not necessarily by miracles or violations of the laws of nature.

The rejection of omnipotence often follows from either philosophical or scriptural considerations, discussed below.

Philosophical grounds

Process theology rejects unlimited omnipotence on a philosophical basis, arguing that omnipotence as classically understood would be less than perfect, and is therefore incompatible with the idea of a perfect God.

The idea is grounded in Plato's oft-overlooked statement that "Being is power."

My notion would be, that anything which possesses any sort of power to affect another, or to be affected by another, if only for a single moment, however trifling the cause and however slight the effect, has real existence; and I hold that the definition of being is simply power.[7]

From this premise, Charles Hartshorne argues further that:

Power is influence, and perfect power is perfect influence … power must be exercised upon something, at least if by power we mean influence, control; but the something controlled cannot be absolutely inert, since the merely passive, that which has no active tendency of its own, is nothing; yet if the something acted upon is itself partly active, then there must be some resistance, however slight, to the "absolute" power, and how can power which is resisted be absolute (Hartshorne, 89).

The argument can be stated as follows:

1) If a being exists, then it must have some active tendency
2) If beings have some active tendency, then they have some power to resist God
3) If beings have the power to resist God, then God does not have absolute power

Thus, if God does not have absolute power, God must therefore embody some of the characteristics of power, and some of the characteristics of persuasion. This view is known as dipolar theism.

The most popular works espousing this point are from Harold Kushner (in Judaism). The need for a modified view of omnipotence was also articulated by Alfred North Whitehead in the early twentieth century and expanded upon by the aforementioned philosopher Charles Hartshorne. Hartshorne proceeded within the context of the theological system known as process theology.

Scriptural grounds

In the King James version of the Bible, as well as several other versions, in Revelations 19:6 it is stated "…the Lord God omnipotent reigneth." However, much of the narrative of the Old Testament describes God as interacting with creation primarily through persuasion, and only occasionally through force. A primary New Testament text used to assert the limit of God's power is Paul's assertion that God cannot tell a lie.[8] Thus, it is argued, there is no scriptural reason to adhere to omnipotence, and the adoption of the doctrine is merely a result of the synthesis of Hellenic philosophy and early Christian thought.

Many other verses in the Bible do assert God's omnipotence without actually using the word itself. There are several times in the Bible when God is called simply, "Almighty," showing that the Bible supports the belief in an omnipotent God. Some such verses are listed below:

Psalms 33:8-9: Let all the earth fear the Lord: Let all the inhabitants of the world stand in awe of him. For he spoke, and it was done; he commanded, and it stood fast.

Genesis 17:1: And when Abram was ninety years old and nine, the Lord appeared to Abram, and said unto him, I am the Almighty God; walk before me, and be thou perfect.

Jeremiah 32:27: Behold, I am the Lord, the God of all flesh: is there any thing too hard for me?

Psalm 107:25: At his command a storm arose and covered the sea.

Paradoxes of omnipotence

The belief that God can do absolutely anything can be thought to yield certain logical paradoxes. A simple example is as follows: Can God create a rock so heavy that even he cannot lift it? If he can, then the rock is now unliftable, limiting God's power. But if he cannot, then he is still not omnipotent. This question cannot be answered using formal logic due to its self-referential nature. This problem led, in the High Middle Ages, to the development of the concept of mathematical infinity, and laid the basis for infinitesimal calculus. Combining omnipotence with omniscience can yield the difficulty of whether or not God can pose a question to which he would not know the answer.

Augustine, in his The City of God, argued that God could not do anything that would make God non-omnipotent:

For He is called omnipotent on account of His doing what He wills, not on account of His suffering what He wills not; for if that should befall Him, He would by no means be omnipotent. Wherefore, He cannot do some things for the very reason that He is omnipotent.[9]

Thus, Augustine argued that God could not do anything or create any situation that would in effect make God not God.

Others have argued that (alluding to C.S. Lewis' argument above) when talking about omnipotence, referencing "a rock so heavy that God cannot lift it" is nonsense just as much as referencing "a square circle." So asking "Can God create a rock so heavy that even he cannot lift it?" is just as much nonsense as asking "Can God draw a square circle?" Therefore the question (and therefore the perceived paradox) is meaningless.


Notes

  1. Catholic Encyclopedia, s.v. "Omnipotence." Retrieved June 24, 2008.
  2. J.C. Polkinghorne, Science and Religion (Philadelphia: Trinity Press International, 1995).
  3. Bhagavad Gita 14.27.
  4. Christian Classics Ethereal Library, Summa Theologica, I, 25, 3. Retrieved June 24, 2008.
  5. Ibid.
  6. Ibid.
  7. Benjamin Jowett, SOPHIST. Retrieved November 27, 2007.
  8. New American Standard Bible, Titus 1:2. Retrieved November 27, 2007.
  9. Christian Classics Ethereal Library, City of God, Book 5, Chapter 10. Retrieved October 27, 2007.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Christian Classics Ethereal Library. Latin Christianity: Its Founder, Tertullian. Retrieved October 27, 2007.
  • Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologica. Christian Classics Ethereal Library. Retrieved October 27, 2007.
  • Flew, Antony and Alasdair C. MacIntyre. New Essays in Philosophical Theology. London: SCM Press, 1955.
  • Hartshorne, Charles. 1964. Man's Vision of God. Hamden, CT: Archon.
  • Jowett, Benjamin, trans. Plato: Sophist. Philosophy on the EServer. Retrieved October 27, 2007.
  • Lewis, C.S. 2001. The Problem of Pain. San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco. ISBN 0060652969
  • Oppy, Graham. 2005. "Omnipotence." Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 71, no. 1: 58.
  • Pike, Nelson. God and Evil; Readings on the Theological Problem of Evil. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1964.
  • Polkinghorne, J.C. Serious Talk: Science and Religion in Dialogue. Philadelphia: Trinity Press International, 1995. ISBN 1563381095
  • Schaff, Philip. 1890. St. Augustin's City of God and Christian Doctrine. New York: The Christian Literature Publishing Co. Retrieved December 16, 2007.
  • Urban, Linwood and Douglas N. Walton. The Power of God Readings on Omnipotence and Evil. New York: Oxford University Press, 1978. ISBN 0195022017

External links

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.