Scheler, Max

From New World Encyclopedia
 
(12 intermediate revisions by 7 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Max Scheler''' (August 22, 1874, Munich - May 19, 1928, Frankfurt am Main) was a [[Germany|German]] [[philosopher]] known for his work in [[phenomenology]], [[ethics]], and [[philosophical anthropology]]. Scheler applied phenomenology, developed by [[Edmund Husserl]], to the field of ethics and established phenomenological ethics. Scheler was called by [[José Ortega y Gasset|Jose Ortega y Gasset]] "the first man of the philosophical paradise."  Scheler argued that the human “heart,” or seat of love, accounted for the essence of human existence, rather than ego, reason, will or the ability to receive sensory data. Like [[Blaise Pascal]], Scheler declared that feelings and love have their own form of [[logic]], different from the logic of reason. The reality of values preceded knowing. Values could only be felt, just as color can only be seen, and not thought. Reason could only organize values in a hierarchy after they had been experienced. Scheler developed a [[axiology|theory of value]], in which values were ranked in a five-tier hierarchy. [[Ethics]] were based on a person’s pre-rational inclination towards certain values.  Whenever a person preferred a value of a lower rank to a higher rank, or a disvalue to a value, the result was a “disorder of the heart.”  
+
{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{copyedited}}
 
+
{{epname|Scheler, Max}}
In 1954 Karol Wojtyla, later Pope John Paul II, defended his doctoral thesis on "''An Evaluation of the Possibility of Constructing a Christian Ethics on the Basis of the system of Max Scheler''."
+
'''Max Scheler''' (August 22, 1874 - May 19, 1928) was a [[Germany|German]] [[philosopher]] known for his work in [[phenomenology]], [[ethics]], and [[philosophical anthropology]]. Scheler applied phenomenology, developed by [[Edmund Husserl]], to the field of ethics and established phenomenological ethics. Scheler was called by [[José Ortega y Gasset|Jose Ortega y Gasset]] "the first man of the philosophical paradise."  Scheler argued that the human “heart,” or seat of love, accounted for the essence of human existence, rather than ego, reason, will, or the ability to receive sensory data. Like [[Blaise Pascal]], Scheler declared that feelings and love have their own form of [[logic]], different from the logic of reason. The reality of values preceded knowing. Values could only be felt, just as color can only be seen, and not thought. Reason could only organize values in a hierarchy after they had been experienced. Scheler developed a [[axiology|theory of value]], in which values were ranked in a five-tier hierarchy. Ethics were based on a person’s pre-rational inclination towards certain values.  Whenever a person preferred a value of a lower rank to a higher rank, or a disvalue to a value, the result was a “disorder of the heart.”  
 +
{{toc}}
 +
In 1954, Karol Wojtyla, later [[Pope John Paul II]], defended his doctoral thesis, titled ''An Evaluation of the Possibility of Constructing a Christian Ethics on the Basis of the System of Max Scheler.''
 
== Life ==
 
== Life ==
Max Scheler was born in [[Munich]], [[Germany]], on August 22, 1874 to a [[Lutheranism|Lutheran]] father and an orthodox [[Judaism|Jewish]] mother. As an adolescent, he turned to [[Roman Catholicism|Catholicism]], probably because of its conception of love; during his forties he became increasingly non-committal.   
+
Max Scheler was born in [[Munich]], [[Germany]], on August 22, 1874, to a [[Lutheranism|Lutheran]] father and an orthodox [[Judaism|Jewish]] mother. As an adolescent, he turned to [[Roman Catholicism|Catholicism]], probably because of its conception of love; during his forties he became increasingly non-committal.   
  
Scheler studied [[medicine]] in Munich and [[Berlin]], and [[philosophy]] and [[sociology]] under [[Wilhelm Dilthey|Dilthey]] and [[Georg Simmel]] in 1895. He received his doctorate in 1897, and his associate professorship (habilitation-thesis) in 1899 at the University of Jena. His advisor was Rudolf Eucken, a 1908 Nobel Prize winner for Literature and a correspondent of [[William James]]. Throughout his life, Scheler retained a strong interest in the philosophy of American Pragmatism.
+
Scheler studied [[medicine]] in Munich and [[Berlin]], and [[philosophy]] and [[sociology]] under [[Wilhelm Dilthey|Dilthey]] and [[Georg Simmel]] in 1895. He received his doctorate in 1897, and his associate professorship (habilitation-thesis) in 1899, at the University of Jena. His adviser was Rudolf Eucken, a 1908 [[Nobel Prize]] winner for literature and a correspondent of [[William James]]. Throughout his life, Scheler retained a strong interest in the philosophy of [[American Pragmatism]].
  
From 1900 to 1906 Scheler taught at the University of Jena.  In 1902 he met the renowned phenomenologist E. [[Husserl]] for the first time in Halle. Scheler was never a student of Husserl's, and their relationship remained strained, but he was influenced by Husserl’s ideas. Later Scheler was in contact with several of Husserl's disciples during his years (1907–10) as a professor at Munich. Scheler was somewhat critical of Husserl’s ''Logical Investigations'' (1900/01) and ''Ideas I'' (1913), and he also harbored reservations about ''Being and Time'', by [[Heidegger]], whom he also met at various times.   
+
From 1900 to 1906, Scheler taught at the University of Jena.  In 1902, he met the renowned phenomenologist E. [[Husserl]] for the first time in Halle. Scheler was never a student of Husserl's, and their relationship remained strained, but he was influenced by Husserl’s ideas. Later, Scheler was in contact with several of Husserl's disciples during his years (1907–10) as a professor at Munich. Scheler was somewhat critical of Husserl’s ''Logical Investigations'' (1900) and ''Ideas I'' (1913), and he also harbored reservations about ''Being and Time,'' by [[Heidegger]], whom he also met at various times.   
  
From 1907-1910 Scheler taught at the University of Munich. There he joined the Phenomenological Circle which had formed around M. Beck, Th. Conrad, J. Daubert, M. Geiger, D. v. Hildebrand, Th. Lipps, and A. Pfaender. A personal matter put him in an unfair position between the predominantly Catholic university and the local socialist media, and resulted in the loss of his Munich teaching position in 1910.
+
From 1907-1910, Scheler taught at the University of Munich. There he joined the Phenomenological Circle which had formed around M. Beck, Th. Conrad, J. Daubert, M. Geiger, D. v. Hildebrand, Th. Lipps, and A. Pfaender. A personal matter put him in an unfair position between the predominantly Catholic university and the local socialist media, and resulted in the loss of his Munich teaching position in 1910.
  
From 1910 to 1911 Scheler lectured at the Philosophical Society of Goettingen, and  made other and renewed acquaintances here with Th. Conrad, H. Conrad-Martius, M. Geiger, J. Hering, [[Roman Ingarden|R. Ingarden]], D. von Hildebrand, E. Husserl, A. Koyre, and H. Reinach. Edith Stein was one of his students.  Scheler unwittingly influenced Catholic thinkers to this day, including Stein and Pope John Paul II who wrote his ''Habilitation'' and many articles on Scheler's philosophy.
+
From 1910 to 1911, Scheler lectured at the Philosophical Society of Goettingen, and  made other and renewed acquaintances there with Th. Conrad, H. Conrad-Martius, M. Geiger, J. Hering, [[Roman Ingarden|R. Ingarden]], D. von Hildebrand, E. Husserl, A. Koyre, and H. Reinach. [[Edith Stein]] was one of his students.  Scheler unwittingly influenced Catholic thinkers to this day, including Stein and Pope John Paul II, who wrote his ''Habilitation'' and many articles on Scheler's philosophy.
  
After his first marriage had ended in divorce, in 1912 Scheler married Märit Furtwaengler, the sister of the noted conductor. During [[World War I]] (1914-1918) Scheler was drafted, but discharged because of astigmia of the eyes.  In 1919 he became professor of [[philosophy]] and sociology at the University of Cologne, where he stayed there until 1928. Early that year, he accepted a new position at the University of Frankfurt, and looked forward to meeting [[Ernst Cassirer]], [[Karl Mannheim]], [[Rudolf Otto]] and R. Wilhelm, to whom he sometimes referred in his writings. In 1927, at a conference arranged by Graf Keyserling in Darmstadt, near Frankfurt,  Scheler delivered a lengthy lecture, entitled "''Man's Particular Place''" (''Die Sonderstellung des Menschen''), published later in a much abbreviated form as ''Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos'' ("''Man's Situation in the Cosmos''"). His well known oratory style and delivery captivated his audience for almost four hours.  Toward the end of his life, many invitations were extended to him, including some from [[China]], [[India]], [[Japan]], [[Russia]], and the [[United States]]. On the advice of his physician, however, he had to cancel reservations he had already made for his journey on the Star Line.
+
After his first marriage had ended in divorce, Scheler married [[Märit Furtwaengler]], the sister of the noted conductor, in 1912. During [[World War I]] (1914-1918) Scheler was drafted, but discharged because of [[astigmatism]] of the eyes.  In 1919, he became professor of [[philosophy]] and sociology at the University of Cologne, where he stayed until 1928. Early that year, he accepted a new position at the University of Frankfurt, and looked forward to meeting [[Ernst Cassirer]], [[Karl Mannheim]], [[Rudolf Otto]], and R. Wilhelm, to whom he sometimes referred in his writings. In 1927, at a conference arranged by Graf Keyserling in Darmstadt, near Frankfurt,  Scheler delivered a lengthy lecture, entitled ''Man's Particular Place'' ''(Die Sonderstellung des Menschen)'', published later in a much abbreviated form as ''Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos'' ''(Man's Situation in the Cosmos)''. His well known oratory style and delivery captivated his audience for almost four hours.  Toward the end of his life, many invitations were extended to him, including some from [[China]], [[India]], [[Japan]], [[Russia]], and the [[United States]]. His health kept him landlocked, however, as his doctor advised him against travel, and he had to cancel his reservations on the Star Line.
  
At that time Scheler increasingly focused on political development. He had met the Russian emigrant-philosopher N. Berdyaev in Berlin in 1923. Scheler was the only scholar of rank in the German intelligentsia who warned in public speeches, as early as 1927 about the dangers of the growing [[Nazi]]-movement and [[Marxism]]. "''Politics and Morals''" and "''The Idea of Eternal Peace and Pacifism''" were subjects of talks he delivered in Berlin 1927. His analysis of capitalism revealed it to be a calculating, globally expanding "mind-set," rather than an economic system. While economic capitalism may have had some roots in ascetic [[Calvinism]], Scheler detected its real motivation as a modern, sub-conscious insecurity expressed in an increasing need for financial and personal security, protection, safety and rational manageability of all entities. Max Scheler denounced the subordination of the value of the individual to this global tendency, and predicted a new era of culture and values, which he called "''The World-Era of Adjustment''."
+
At that time Scheler increasingly focused on political development. He had met the Russian emigrant-philosopher N. Berdyaev in Berlin, in 1923. Scheler was the only scholar of rank in the German intelligentsia who warned in public speeches, as early as 1927, about the dangers of the both Marxism and the growing [[Nazi]] movement. ''Politics and Morals'' and ''The Idea of Eternal Peace and Pacifism'' were subjects of talks he delivered in Berlin during 1927. His analysis of [[capitalism]] revealed it to be a calculating, globally expanding "mind-set," rather than an economic system. While economic capitalism may have had some roots in ascetic [[Calvinism]], Scheler detected its real motivation as a modern, sub-conscious insecurity expressed in an increasing need for financial and personal security, protection, safety, and rational manageability of all entities. Max Scheler denounced the subordination of the value of the individual to this global tendency, and predicted a new era of culture and values, which he called "The World-Era of Adjustment."
  
Scheler also advocated the establishment of an international university in Switzerland. He was supportive of programs such as "continuing education," and of what he seems to have first called a "United States of Europe." He deplored the gap existing in Germany between political power and mind, a gap which he considered to be the source of an impending dictatorship, and the greatest obstacle toward establishing a German democracy. Five years after his demise, the Nazi dictatorship (1933-1945) suppressed Scheler's work.
+
Scheler also advocated the establishment of an international university in Switzerland. He was supportive of programs such as "continuing education," and of what he seems to have first called a "United States of Europe." He deplored the gap existing in Germany between political power and mind, a gap which he considered to be the source of an impending dictatorship, and the greatest obstacle toward establishing a German democracy. Five years after his death, the Nazi dictatorship (1933-1945) suppressed Scheler's work.
  
After Scheler's demise in 1928, Heidegger noted, as did Ortega y Gasset, that all philosophers of the century were indebted to Scheler. Many considered Scheler's sudden death to be an irreplaceable loss to European thought.
+
After Scheler's death in 1928, Heidegger and Ortega y Gasset both noted that all philosophers of the century were indebted to Scheler. Many considered Scheler's sudden death to be an irreplaceable loss to European thought.
  
== Thought and Works ==  
+
== Thought and works ==  
Max Scheler’s thought is usually divided into two periods of development.  The first period, covered by Volumes 1 through 7 of his ''Collected Works'', covers the years between his dissertation (1897) and the writing of ''On the Eternal in Man'' (1920 - 1922).  During this time, Scheler applied his understanding of [[phenomenology]] to value-ethics, feelings, religion, politics and related topics.  During the second period, from 1920 through 1928, Scheler rejected the notion of a creator-God, and posited instead a process of a universal, cosmic becoming in absolute time, through increasingly interpenetrating  interaction between an uncreated vital energy, or “Impulsion;” and “Spirit,” which formed impulse into existence.
+
Max Scheler’s thought is usually divided into two periods of development.  The first period, covered by Volumes 1 through 7 of his ''Collected Works,'' covers the years between his dissertation (1897) and the writing of ''On the Eternal in Man'' (1920-1922).  During this time, Scheler applied his understanding of [[phenomenology]] to value-ethics, feelings, religion, politics, and related topics.  During the second period, from 1920 through 1928, Scheler rejected the notion of a creator-God, and posited instead a process of a universal, cosmic becoming in absolute time, through increasingly inter-penetrating interaction between an uncreated vital energy, or “Impulsion,” and “Spirit,” which formed impulse into existence.
  
===Value and Morality===
+
===Value and morality===
Scheler’s first two major works, ''The Nature of Sympathy'' and ''Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values'', dealt with human feelings, love, and the nature of the person.  He demonstrated that the [[ego]], [[reason]] and consciousness were all attributes of the human person and that there could be no pure ego, pure reason or pure consciousness outside a human context.  The human “heart”, or seat of love, accounted for the essence of human existence, rather than ego, reason, will or the ability to receive sensory data.  The human being was essentially a loving being  (ens amans).  Scheler described many types of feelings and showed that love was at their center.  Like Blaise Pascal, Scheler declared that feelings and love have their own form of logic, different from the logic of reason.
+
Scheler’s first two major works, ''The Nature of Sympathy'' and ''Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values,'' dealt with human feelings, love, and the nature of the person.  He demonstrated that the [[ego]], [[reason]], and consciousness were all attributes of the human person and that there could be no pure ego, pure reason, or pure consciousness outside a human context.  The human “heart,or seat of love, accounted for the essence of human existence, rather than ego, reason, will, or the ability to receive sensory data.  The human being was essentially a loving being  (ens amans).  Scheler described many types of feelings and showed that love was at their center.  Like [[Blaise Pascal]], Scheler declared that feelings and love have their own forms of logic, different from the logic of reason.
  
The center of Scheler's thought was his [[value theory|theory of value]]. According to Scheler, the value-being of an object preceded perception; the [[axiology|axiological]] reality of values was prior to knowing.   Values could only be felt, just as color can only be seen. Reason could not think values; the mind could only organize values in a hierarchy after they had been experienced. Values were independent of the things that caused them to be felt; a particular value could be experienced with a variety of objects.  ''Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values'' contended that there were also moral values of good and evil that related directly to the person, and never to objects.  The countless varieties of value experiences had a hidden order of their own, an order based on love ("''ordo amoris''"), quite different from an order created by reasoning.  Scheler argued that values were objective, unchanging , a priori , and non-formal, and ranked them, and their opposites (“disvalues”), in a hierarchy of five levels:
+
The center of Scheler's thought was his [[value theory|theory of value]]. According to Scheler, the value-being of an object preceded perception; the [[axiology|axiological]] reality of values exists prior to knowing. Values could only be felt, just as color can only be seen. Reason could not think values; the mind could only organize values in a hierarchy after they had been experienced. Values were independent of the things that caused them to be felt; a particular value could be experienced with a variety of objects.  ''Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values'' contended that there were also moral values of good and evil that related directly to the person, and never to objects.  The countless varieties of value experiences had a hidden order of their own, an order based on love ("''ordo amoris''"), quite different from an order created by reasoning.  Scheler argued that values were objective, unchanging , a priori, and non-formal, and ranked them, and their opposites (“disvalues”), in a hierarchy of five levels:
  
#Values of pleasure vs. disvalues of displeasure: namely pleasure pain (values of sensible feeling),
+
#Values of pleasure vs. disvalues of displeasure: Namely pleasure to pain (values of sensible feeling).
#Values of vitality and of the noble vs. disvalues of the ignoble: namely noble vulgar ( values of vital feeling)
+
#Values of vitality and of the noble vs. disvalues of the ignoble: Namely noble to vulgar (values of vital feeling).
#Values of the mind (truth, beauty, justice vs. disvalues of their opposites): namely beautiful ugly , just unjust , pure knowledge of truth ( spiritual values)
+
#Values of the mind (truth, beauty, justice vs. disvalues of their opposites): Namely beautiful to ugly, just to unjust, pure knowledge of truth (spiritual values).
#Values of the holy vs. disvalues of the unholy: namely holy unholy (religious values)
+
#Values of the holy vs. disvalues of the unholy: Namely holy to unholy (religious values).
#Values of utility vs. disvalues of the useless
+
#Values of utility vs. disvalues of the useless.
  
 
Scheler’s ethics was based on what he called “pre-rational preferring,” or the person’s initial inclination towards certain values.  A “disorder of the heart" occurred whenever a person preferred a value of a lower rank to a higher rank, or a disvalue to a value.
 
Scheler’s ethics was based on what he called “pre-rational preferring,” or the person’s initial inclination towards certain values.  A “disorder of the heart" occurred whenever a person preferred a value of a lower rank to a higher rank, or a disvalue to a value.
  
Since emotions and feelings can sometimes be insincere, inconsistent or subject to deception, Scheler wrote a number of studies on value deceptions, including ''Ordo Amoris, The Idols of Self-Knowledge, Repentance and Re-Birth'', and ''Ressentiment''.
+
Since emotions and feelings can sometimes be insincere, inconsistent, or subject to deception, Scheler wrote a number of studies on value deceptions, including ''Ordo Amoris, The Idols of Self-Knowledge, Repentance and Re-Birth,'' and ''Ressentiment.''
Every person was both and individual and a part of a community with which he shared a common experience of value.  Many people did not have to capacity to “feel” higher values and therefore could not participate in the types of community devoted to those values, but everyone should be allowed access to what they did value.  Scheler believed that values could be better advanced by an aristocracy rather than a democracy.
+
Every person was both an individual and a part of a community with which he shared a common experience of value.  Many people did not have the capacity to “feel” higher values and therefore could not participate in the types of community devoted to those values, but everyone should be allowed access to what they did value.  Scheler believed that values could be better advanced by an [[aristocracy]] rather than a [[democracy]].
===Second Period===
+
 
''On the Eternal in Man'' marked the bridge to his second period, during which Scheler turned towards metaphysics and the philosophy of science.  Scheler defied the notion of a creator-God and instead suggested that Deity, Man, and World form one “becoming” process of unification, taking place in absolute time. Absolute time was a function of self-generating life and was inherent in all processes of self-regeneration, aging, self-modification. The process of a universal, cosmic becoming took place through increasingly interpenetrating  interaction between an uncreated vital energy, or “Impulsion,” and “Spirit,” which directed impulse into existence and ideas. Both God and humanity were continually evolving towards completion and total unity.
+
===Second period===
 +
''On the Eternal in Man'' marked the bridge to his second period, during which Scheler turned towards metaphysics and the philosophy of science.  Scheler defied the notion of a creator-God and instead suggested that Deity, Man, and World form one “becoming” process of unification, taking place in absolute time. [[Absolute time]] was a function of self-generating life and was inherent in all processes of self-regeneration, aging, and self-modification. The process of a universal, cosmic becoming took place through increasingly inter-penetrating interaction between an uncreated vital energy, or “Impulsion,” and “Spirit,” which directed impulse into existence and ideas. Both God and humanity were continually evolving towards completion and total unity.
 +
 
 
==References==
 
==References==
 
===Primary sources (English translations)===
 
===Primary sources (English translations)===
* Scheler, Max; Haac, Oscar (translator). ''Philosophical Perspectives''. Boston, Beacon Press, 1958. (German  : ''Philosophische Weltanschauung'')
+
* Scheler, Max. 1958. Translated by Oscar Haac. ''Philosophical Perspectives.'' Boston: Beacon Press.
* Scheler, Max; Noble, Bernard (translator). ''On the Eternal in Man''. London, SCM Press, 1960.  
+
* Scheler, Max. 1960. Translated by Bernard Noble. ''On the Eternal in Man.'' London: SCM Press.  
* Scheler, Max; Meyerhoff, Hans (translator). ''Man's Place in Nature''. New York, The Noonday Press, 1961    SBN 374-5-0252-8.
+
* Scheler, Max. 1961. Translated by Hans Meyerhoff. ''Man's Place in Nature.'' New York: The Noonday Press. ISBN 374-5-0252-8  
*Scheler, Max; Heath, Peter (translator). ''The Nature of Sympathy''. New York, Archion Books, 1970.  ISBN 0-208-01401-2.
+
* Scheler, Max. 1970. Translated by Peter Heath. ''The Nature of Sympathy.'' New York: Archion Books.  ISBN 0-208-01401-2
* Scheler, Max; Cosner, Lewis A. (editor); Holdheim, William W. (translator). ''Ressentiment''. New York, Schocken, 1972. ISBN 0-8052-0370-2.
+
* Scheler, Max. 1972. Translated by William W. Holdheim. ''Ressentiment.'' New York: Schocken. ISBN 0-8052-0370-2  
*Scheler, Max; Lachterman, David R. (translator). ''Selected Philosophical Essays.'' Evanston, IL, Northwestern University Press, 1973.  ISBN 0-8101-0379-6.
+
* Scheler, Max. 1973. Translated by David R. Lachterman. ''Selected Philosophical Essays.'' Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.  ISBN 0-8101-0379-6
*Scheler, Max;  Frings, Manfred S. and Funk, Roger L. (editors and translators). ''Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A new attempt toward the foundation of an ethical personalism.'' Evanston, IL, Northwestern University Press, 1973  ISBN 0-8101-0415-6. (Original German edition: ''Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik'', 1913-16)
+
* Scheler, Max. 1973. Translated and edited by Manfred S. Frings and Roger L. Funk. ''Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt Toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism.'' Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 0-8101-0415-6  
*Scheler, Max;  Frings, Manfred S. (editor and translator).''Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge''. London, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1980.  ISBN 0-7100-0302-1.
+
* Scheler, Max. 1980. Translated and edited by Manfred S. Frings. ''Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge.'' London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.  ISBN 0-7100-0302-1
*Scheler, Max;  Frings, Manfred S. (editor and translator).''Person and Self-value: three essays''. Boston, Nijhoff, 1987. ISBN 9-0247-3380-4.
+
* Scheler, Max. 1987. Translated and edited by Manfred S. Frings. ''Person and Self-value: Three Essays.'' Boston: Nijhoff. ISBN 9-0247-3380-4
* Scheler, Max; Bershady, Harold J. (editor and translator). ''On Feeling, Knowing, and Valuing. Selected Writings''. Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1992. ISBN 0-2267-3671-7.
+
* Scheler, Max. 1992. Translated and edited by Harold J. Bershady. ''On Feeling, Knowing, and Valuing. Selected Writings.'' Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-2267-3671-7
  
 
===Secondary sources===
 
===Secondary sources===
* Deeken, Alfons. ''Process and Permanence in Ethics: Max Scheler's Moral Philosophy''. Paulist Press, 1974. ISBN 978-0809118007  
+
* Deeken, Alfons. 1974. ''Process and Permanence in Ethics: Max Scheler's Moral Philosophy.'' Paulist Press. ISBN 978-0809118007  
*Frings, Manfred S..''Max Scheler: A concise introduction to the world of a great thinker.'' Marquette University Press, 1995. ISBN 978-0874626056  
+
* Frings, Manfred S. 1995. ''Max Scheler: A Concise Introduction to the World of a Great Thinker.'' Marquette University Press. ISBN 978-0874626056  
* Frings, Manfred S..''Max Scheler (1874-1928) : centennial essays''. Springer, 1974. ISBN 978-9024716081   
+
* Frings, Manfred S. 1974. ''Max Scheler (1874-1928): Centennial Essays.'' Springer. ISBN 978-9024716081   
*Frings, Manfred S.. ''The Mind of Max Scheler: The First comprehensive guide based on the complete works.'' Marquette University Press, 1997. ISBN 978-0874626131   
+
* Frings, Manfred S. 1997. ''The Mind of Max Scheler: The First Comprehensive Guide Based on the Complete Works.'' Marquette University Press. ISBN 978-0874626131   
* Kelly, Eugene. ''Max Scheler''. Twaynes Pub, 1977. ISBN 978-0805777079  
+
* Kelly, Eugene. 1977. ''Max Scheler.'' Twaynes Pub. ISBN 978-0805777079  
* Nota, John H. ''Max Scheler: The Man and His Work''. Franciscan Press, 1984. ISBN 978-0819908520 (Original Dutch  : ''Max Scheler: De man en zijn werk'')
+
* Nota, John H. 1984. ''Max Scheler: The Man and His Work.'' Franciscan Press. ISBN 978-0819908520  
* Staude, John Raphael. ''Max Scheler 1874-1928: An intellectual portrait''. Free Pr., 1967. ISBN 978-0029307700
+
* Staude, John Raphael. 1967. ''Max Scheler 1874-1928: An Intellectual Portrait.'' Free Pr. ISBN 978-0029307700
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
*[http://www.maxscheler.com Prof. Frings' Max Scheler Website]
+
All links retrieved November 8, 2022.
*[http://www.lrc.edu/rel/blosser/Max_Scheler_Society.htm Max Scheler Society of North America, includes links]
+
 
 
===General Philosophy Sources===
 
===General Philosophy Sources===
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].  
*[http://www.epistemelinks.com/  Philosophy Sources on Internet EpistemeLinks]
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
*[http://www.earlham.edu/~peters/gpi/index.htm Guide to Philosophy on the Internet]
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]  
 
  
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
+
[[Category:Philosophers]]
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 
[[Category:German philosophers|Scheler, Max]]
 
  
 
{{Credit|76006587}}
 
{{Credit|76006587}}

Latest revision as of 00:58, 9 November 2022

Max Scheler (August 22, 1874 - May 19, 1928) was a German philosopher known for his work in phenomenology, ethics, and philosophical anthropology. Scheler applied phenomenology, developed by Edmund Husserl, to the field of ethics and established phenomenological ethics. Scheler was called by Jose Ortega y Gasset "the first man of the philosophical paradise." Scheler argued that the human “heart,” or seat of love, accounted for the essence of human existence, rather than ego, reason, will, or the ability to receive sensory data. Like Blaise Pascal, Scheler declared that feelings and love have their own form of logic, different from the logic of reason. The reality of values preceded knowing. Values could only be felt, just as color can only be seen, and not thought. Reason could only organize values in a hierarchy after they had been experienced. Scheler developed a theory of value, in which values were ranked in a five-tier hierarchy. Ethics were based on a person’s pre-rational inclination towards certain values. Whenever a person preferred a value of a lower rank to a higher rank, or a disvalue to a value, the result was a “disorder of the heart.”

In 1954, Karol Wojtyla, later Pope John Paul II, defended his doctoral thesis, titled An Evaluation of the Possibility of Constructing a Christian Ethics on the Basis of the System of Max Scheler.

Life

Max Scheler was born in Munich, Germany, on August 22, 1874, to a Lutheran father and an orthodox Jewish mother. As an adolescent, he turned to Catholicism, probably because of its conception of love; during his forties he became increasingly non-committal.

Scheler studied medicine in Munich and Berlin, and philosophy and sociology under Dilthey and Georg Simmel in 1895. He received his doctorate in 1897, and his associate professorship (habilitation-thesis) in 1899, at the University of Jena. His adviser was Rudolf Eucken, a 1908 Nobel Prize winner for literature and a correspondent of William James. Throughout his life, Scheler retained a strong interest in the philosophy of American Pragmatism.

From 1900 to 1906, Scheler taught at the University of Jena. In 1902, he met the renowned phenomenologist E. Husserl for the first time in Halle. Scheler was never a student of Husserl's, and their relationship remained strained, but he was influenced by Husserl’s ideas. Later, Scheler was in contact with several of Husserl's disciples during his years (1907–10) as a professor at Munich. Scheler was somewhat critical of Husserl’s Logical Investigations (1900) and Ideas I (1913), and he also harbored reservations about Being and Time, by Heidegger, whom he also met at various times.

From 1907-1910, Scheler taught at the University of Munich. There he joined the Phenomenological Circle which had formed around M. Beck, Th. Conrad, J. Daubert, M. Geiger, D. v. Hildebrand, Th. Lipps, and A. Pfaender. A personal matter put him in an unfair position between the predominantly Catholic university and the local socialist media, and resulted in the loss of his Munich teaching position in 1910.

From 1910 to 1911, Scheler lectured at the Philosophical Society of Goettingen, and made other and renewed acquaintances there with Th. Conrad, H. Conrad-Martius, M. Geiger, J. Hering, R. Ingarden, D. von Hildebrand, E. Husserl, A. Koyre, and H. Reinach. Edith Stein was one of his students. Scheler unwittingly influenced Catholic thinkers to this day, including Stein and Pope John Paul II, who wrote his Habilitation and many articles on Scheler's philosophy.

After his first marriage had ended in divorce, Scheler married Märit Furtwaengler, the sister of the noted conductor, in 1912. During World War I (1914-1918) Scheler was drafted, but discharged because of astigmatism of the eyes. In 1919, he became professor of philosophy and sociology at the University of Cologne, where he stayed until 1928. Early that year, he accepted a new position at the University of Frankfurt, and looked forward to meeting Ernst Cassirer, Karl Mannheim, Rudolf Otto, and R. Wilhelm, to whom he sometimes referred in his writings. In 1927, at a conference arranged by Graf Keyserling in Darmstadt, near Frankfurt, Scheler delivered a lengthy lecture, entitled Man's Particular Place (Die Sonderstellung des Menschen), published later in a much abbreviated form as Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos (Man's Situation in the Cosmos). His well known oratory style and delivery captivated his audience for almost four hours. Toward the end of his life, many invitations were extended to him, including some from China, India, Japan, Russia, and the United States. His health kept him landlocked, however, as his doctor advised him against travel, and he had to cancel his reservations on the Star Line.

At that time Scheler increasingly focused on political development. He had met the Russian emigrant-philosopher N. Berdyaev in Berlin, in 1923. Scheler was the only scholar of rank in the German intelligentsia who warned in public speeches, as early as 1927, about the dangers of the both Marxism and the growing Nazi movement. Politics and Morals and The Idea of Eternal Peace and Pacifism were subjects of talks he delivered in Berlin during 1927. His analysis of capitalism revealed it to be a calculating, globally expanding "mind-set," rather than an economic system. While economic capitalism may have had some roots in ascetic Calvinism, Scheler detected its real motivation as a modern, sub-conscious insecurity expressed in an increasing need for financial and personal security, protection, safety, and rational manageability of all entities. Max Scheler denounced the subordination of the value of the individual to this global tendency, and predicted a new era of culture and values, which he called "The World-Era of Adjustment."

Scheler also advocated the establishment of an international university in Switzerland. He was supportive of programs such as "continuing education," and of what he seems to have first called a "United States of Europe." He deplored the gap existing in Germany between political power and mind, a gap which he considered to be the source of an impending dictatorship, and the greatest obstacle toward establishing a German democracy. Five years after his death, the Nazi dictatorship (1933-1945) suppressed Scheler's work.

After Scheler's death in 1928, Heidegger and Ortega y Gasset both noted that all philosophers of the century were indebted to Scheler. Many considered Scheler's sudden death to be an irreplaceable loss to European thought.

Thought and works

Max Scheler’s thought is usually divided into two periods of development. The first period, covered by Volumes 1 through 7 of his Collected Works, covers the years between his dissertation (1897) and the writing of On the Eternal in Man (1920-1922). During this time, Scheler applied his understanding of phenomenology to value-ethics, feelings, religion, politics, and related topics. During the second period, from 1920 through 1928, Scheler rejected the notion of a creator-God, and posited instead a process of a universal, cosmic becoming in absolute time, through increasingly inter-penetrating interaction between an uncreated vital energy, or “Impulsion,” and “Spirit,” which formed impulse into existence.

Value and morality

Scheler’s first two major works, The Nature of Sympathy and Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values, dealt with human feelings, love, and the nature of the person. He demonstrated that the ego, reason, and consciousness were all attributes of the human person and that there could be no pure ego, pure reason, or pure consciousness outside a human context. The human “heart,” or seat of love, accounted for the essence of human existence, rather than ego, reason, will, or the ability to receive sensory data. The human being was essentially a loving being (ens amans). Scheler described many types of feelings and showed that love was at their center. Like Blaise Pascal, Scheler declared that feelings and love have their own forms of logic, different from the logic of reason.

The center of Scheler's thought was his theory of value. According to Scheler, the value-being of an object preceded perception; the axiological reality of values exists prior to knowing. Values could only be felt, just as color can only be seen. Reason could not think values; the mind could only organize values in a hierarchy after they had been experienced. Values were independent of the things that caused them to be felt; a particular value could be experienced with a variety of objects. Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values contended that there were also moral values of good and evil that related directly to the person, and never to objects. The countless varieties of value experiences had a hidden order of their own, an order based on love ("ordo amoris"), quite different from an order created by reasoning. Scheler argued that values were objective, unchanging , a priori, and non-formal, and ranked them, and their opposites (“disvalues”), in a hierarchy of five levels:

  1. Values of pleasure vs. disvalues of displeasure: Namely pleasure to pain (values of sensible feeling).
  2. Values of vitality and of the noble vs. disvalues of the ignoble: Namely noble to vulgar (values of vital feeling).
  3. Values of the mind (truth, beauty, justice vs. disvalues of their opposites): Namely beautiful to ugly, just to unjust, pure knowledge of truth (spiritual values).
  4. Values of the holy vs. disvalues of the unholy: Namely holy to unholy (religious values).
  5. Values of utility vs. disvalues of the useless.

Scheler’s ethics was based on what he called “pre-rational preferring,” or the person’s initial inclination towards certain values. A “disorder of the heart" occurred whenever a person preferred a value of a lower rank to a higher rank, or a disvalue to a value.

Since emotions and feelings can sometimes be insincere, inconsistent, or subject to deception, Scheler wrote a number of studies on value deceptions, including Ordo Amoris, The Idols of Self-Knowledge, Repentance and Re-Birth, and Ressentiment. Every person was both an individual and a part of a community with which he shared a common experience of value. Many people did not have the capacity to “feel” higher values and therefore could not participate in the types of community devoted to those values, but everyone should be allowed access to what they did value. Scheler believed that values could be better advanced by an aristocracy rather than a democracy.

Second period

On the Eternal in Man marked the bridge to his second period, during which Scheler turned towards metaphysics and the philosophy of science. Scheler defied the notion of a creator-God and instead suggested that Deity, Man, and World form one “becoming” process of unification, taking place in absolute time. Absolute time was a function of self-generating life and was inherent in all processes of self-regeneration, aging, and self-modification. The process of a universal, cosmic becoming took place through increasingly inter-penetrating interaction between an uncreated vital energy, or “Impulsion,” and “Spirit,” which directed impulse into existence and ideas. Both God and humanity were continually evolving towards completion and total unity.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

Primary sources (English translations)

  • Scheler, Max. 1958. Translated by Oscar Haac. Philosophical Perspectives. Boston: Beacon Press.
  • Scheler, Max. 1960. Translated by Bernard Noble. On the Eternal in Man. London: SCM Press.
  • Scheler, Max. 1961. Translated by Hans Meyerhoff. Man's Place in Nature. New York: The Noonday Press. ISBN 374-5-0252-8
  • Scheler, Max. 1970. Translated by Peter Heath. The Nature of Sympathy. New York: Archion Books. ISBN 0-208-01401-2
  • Scheler, Max. 1972. Translated by William W. Holdheim. Ressentiment. New York: Schocken. ISBN 0-8052-0370-2
  • Scheler, Max. 1973. Translated by David R. Lachterman. Selected Philosophical Essays. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 0-8101-0379-6
  • Scheler, Max. 1973. Translated and edited by Manfred S. Frings and Roger L. Funk. Formalism in Ethics and Non-Formal Ethics of Values: A New Attempt Toward the Foundation of an Ethical Personalism. Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press. ISBN 0-8101-0415-6
  • Scheler, Max. 1980. Translated and edited by Manfred S. Frings. Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. ISBN 0-7100-0302-1
  • Scheler, Max. 1987. Translated and edited by Manfred S. Frings. Person and Self-value: Three Essays. Boston: Nijhoff. ISBN 9-0247-3380-4
  • Scheler, Max. 1992. Translated and edited by Harold J. Bershady. On Feeling, Knowing, and Valuing. Selected Writings. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-2267-3671-7

Secondary sources

  • Deeken, Alfons. 1974. Process and Permanence in Ethics: Max Scheler's Moral Philosophy. Paulist Press. ISBN 978-0809118007
  • Frings, Manfred S. 1995. Max Scheler: A Concise Introduction to the World of a Great Thinker. Marquette University Press. ISBN 978-0874626056
  • Frings, Manfred S. 1974. Max Scheler (1874-1928): Centennial Essays. Springer. ISBN 978-9024716081
  • Frings, Manfred S. 1997. The Mind of Max Scheler: The First Comprehensive Guide Based on the Complete Works. Marquette University Press. ISBN 978-0874626131
  • Kelly, Eugene. 1977. Max Scheler. Twaynes Pub. ISBN 978-0805777079
  • Nota, John H. 1984. Max Scheler: The Man and His Work. Franciscan Press. ISBN 978-0819908520
  • Staude, John Raphael. 1967. Max Scheler 1874-1928: An Intellectual Portrait. Free Pr. ISBN 978-0029307700

External links

All links retrieved November 8, 2022.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.