Difference between revisions of "John Stuart Mill" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m
(re-importing the lastest version from wiki)
Line 14: Line 14:
 
   birth            = [[May 20]], [[1806]] ([[Pentonville]], [[London]], [[England]]) |
 
   birth            = [[May 20]], [[1806]] ([[Pentonville]], [[London]], [[England]]) |
 
   death            = [[May 8]], [[1873]] ([[Avignon]], [[France]]) |
 
   death            = [[May 8]], [[1873]] ([[Avignon]], [[France]]) |
   school_tradition = [[Utilitarianism]] |
+
   school_tradition = [[Empiricism]], [[Utilitarianism]] |
 
   main_interests  = [[Political philosophy]], [[Ethics]], [[Economics]], [[Inductive reasoning|Inductive Logic]] |
 
   main_interests  = [[Political philosophy]], [[Ethics]], [[Economics]], [[Inductive reasoning|Inductive Logic]] |
   influences      = [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas]], [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]], [[Adam Smith|Smith]], [[David Ricardo|Ricardo]], [[Alexis de Tocqueville|Tocqueville]], [[James Mill]], [[Claude Henri de Rouvroy, comte de Saint-Simon|Saint-Simon]] |
+
   influences      = [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], [[Thomas Aquinas|Aquinas]], [[Thomas Hobbes|Hobbes]], [[John Locke|Locke]], [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]], [[Adam Smith|Smith]], [[David Ricardo|Ricardo]], [[Alexis de Tocqueville|Tocqueville]], [[James Mill]], [[Claude Henri de Rouvroy, comte de Saint-Simon|Saint-Simon]] ([[Utopian socialism|Utopian Socialists)]]<ref>{{cite journal|author=[[Friedrich Hayek]]|title=The Counter-Revolution of Science|year=1941|journal=Economica|volume=8|issue=31|pages=281-320|doi=10.2307/2549335}}</ref> |
   influenced      = Many political philosophers after him, including [[John Rawls]], [[Robert Nozick]], [[Bertrand Russell]] , [[Karl Popper]], [[Ronald Dworkin]], [[H.L.A. Hart]], [[Peter Singer]] |
+
   influenced      = Many philosophers after him, including [[John Rawls]], [[Robert Nozick]], [[Bertrand Russell]], [[Karl Popper]], [[Ronald Dworkin]], [[H.L.A. Hart]], [[Peter Singer]] |
 
   notable_ideas    = public/private sphere, hierarchy of pleasures in Utilitarianism, liberalism, early liberal feminism, first system of inductive logic |
 
   notable_ideas    = public/private sphere, hierarchy of pleasures in Utilitarianism, liberalism, early liberal feminism, first system of inductive logic |
 
}}
 
}}
  
'''John Stuart Mill''' ([[May 20]], [[1806]] &ndash; [[May 8]], [[1873]]), an [[England|English]] [[philosopher]] and [[political economy|political economist]], was an influential [[liberalism|liberal]] thinker of the [[19th century]]. He was an advocate of [[utilitarianism]], the ethical theory that was systemized by his godfather [[Jeremy Bentham]].  
+
'''John Stuart Mill''' ([[May 20]], [[1806]] &ndash; [[May 8]], [[1873]]), an [[England|English]] [[philosopher]] and [[political economy|political economist]], was an influential [[liberalism|liberal]] thinker of the [[19th century]]. He was an advocate of [[utilitarianism]], the ethical theory that was systemised by his godfather, [[Jeremy Bentham]], but adapted to [[German romanticism]]. It is usually suggested that Mill is an advocate of [[Negative liberty]]. However, this has been contested by many academics, notably Dr. David Walker of [[Newcastle University]] in England.
  
 
== Biography ==
 
== Biography ==
John Stuart Mill was born in [[Pentonville]], [[London]], the oldest son of the [[Scotland|Scottish]] philosopher and historian [[James Mill]]. John Stuart was educated by his father, with the advice and assistance of [[Jeremy Bentham]] and [[Francis Place]]. He was given an extremely rigorous upbringing, and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings. His father, a follower of [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]] and an adherent of [[associationism]], had as his explicit aim to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of [[utilitarianism]] and its implementation after he and Bentham were dead.
+
John Stuart Mill was born in [[Pentonville]], [[London]], the oldest son of the [[Scotland|Scottish]] philosopher and historian [[James Mill]]. John Stuart was educated by his father, with the advice and assistance of [[Jeremy Bentham]] and [[Francis Place]]. He was given an extremely rigorous, some would say harsh, upbringing, and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings. His father, a follower of [[Jeremy Bentham|Bentham]] and an adherent of [[associationism]], had as his explicit aim to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of [[utilitarianism]] and its implementation after he and Bentham were dead.
  
His feats as a child were exceptional; at the age of three he was taught the [[Greek alphabet]] and long lists of Greek words with their English equivalents. By the age of eight he had read [[Aesop|Aesop's]] ''[[Aesop's Fables|Fables]]'', [[Xenophon]]'s ''[[Anabasis (Xenophon)|Anabasis]],'' and the whole of [[Herodotus]], and was acquainted with [[Lucian]], [[Diogenes Laërtius]], [[Isocrates]] and six dialogues of [[Plato]] (see his Autobiography). He had also read a great deal of history in English and had been taught [[arithmetic]].
+
John Stuart's feats as a child were exceptional; at the age of three he was taught the [[Greek alphabet]] and long lists of Greek words with their English equivalents. By the age of eight he had read [[Aesop|Aesop's]] ''[[Aesop's Fables|Fables]]'', [[Xenophon]]'s ''[[Anabasis (Xenophon)|Anabasis]],'' and the whole of [[Herodotus]], and was acquainted with [[Lucian]], [[Diogenes Laërtius]], [[Isocrates]] and six dialogues of [[Plato]] (see his Autobiography). He had also read a great deal of history in English and had been taught [[arithmetic]].
  
 
A contemporary record of Mill's studies from eight to thirteen is published in [[Alexander Bain|Bain]]'s sketch of his life. It suggests that his autobiography rather understates the amount of work done. At the age of eight he began learning [[Latin]], [[Euclid]], and [[algebra]], and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family. His main reading was still history, but he went through all the Latin and [[Greek language|Greek]] authors commonly read in the schools and universities at the time. He was not taught to compose either in Latin or in Greek, and he was never an exact scholar; it was for the subject matter that he was required to read, and by the age of ten he could read [[Plato]] and [[Demosthenes]] with ease. His father's ''History of India'' was published in 1818; immediately thereafter, about the age of twelve, John began a thorough study of the [[scholastic]] [[logic]], at the same time reading [[Aristotle]]'s logical treatises in the original language. In the following year he was introduced to [[political economy]] and studied [[Adam Smith]] and [[David Ricardo]] with his father—ultimately completing their [[Classical economics|classical economic view]] of [[factors of production]].
 
A contemporary record of Mill's studies from eight to thirteen is published in [[Alexander Bain|Bain]]'s sketch of his life. It suggests that his autobiography rather understates the amount of work done. At the age of eight he began learning [[Latin]], [[Euclid]], and [[algebra]], and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family. His main reading was still history, but he went through all the Latin and [[Greek language|Greek]] authors commonly read in the schools and universities at the time. He was not taught to compose either in Latin or in Greek, and he was never an exact scholar; it was for the subject matter that he was required to read, and by the age of ten he could read [[Plato]] and [[Demosthenes]] with ease. His father's ''History of India'' was published in 1818; immediately thereafter, about the age of twelve, John began a thorough study of the [[scholastic]] [[logic]], at the same time reading [[Aristotle]]'s logical treatises in the original language. In the following year he was introduced to [[political economy]] and studied [[Adam Smith]] and [[David Ricardo]] with his father—ultimately completing their [[Classical economics|classical economic view]] of [[factors of production]].
  
In 1823, he co-founded the ''[[Westminster Review]]'' with [[Jeremy Bentham]] as a journal for philosophical radicals.
+
This intensive study however had injurious effects on Mill's mental health, and state of mind.  At the age of 21 he suffered a [[nervous breakdown]]; as explained in chapter V of his ''Autobiography'', this was caused by the great physical and mental arduousness of his studies which had suppressed any [[feeling]]s he might have developed normally in childhood.  Nevertheless, this depression eventually began to dissipate, as he began to find solace in the poetry of [[William Wordsworth]].  His capacity for emotion resurfaced, Mill remarking that the "cloud gradually drew off".
  
This intensive study however had injurious effects on Mill's mental health, and state of mind.  At the age of 21 he suffered a [[nervous breakdown]]; as explained in chapter V of his ''Autobiography'', this was caused by the great physical and mental arduousness of his studies which had suppressed any [[feeling]]s he might have developed normally in childhoodNevertheless, this depression eventually began to dissipate, as he began to find solace in the poetry of [[William Wordsworth]].  His capacity for emotion resurfaced, Mill remarking that the "cloud gradually drew off".
+
Mill refused to study at [[Oxford University]] or [[University of Cambridge|Cambridge University]], because he refused to take [[Anglican]] orders.<ref name="bio">Capaldi, Nicholas. ''John Stuart Mill: A Biography.'' p.33, Cambridge, 2004, ISBN 0-521-62024-4.</ref> Instead he followed his father to work for the [[British East India Company]] until 1858Between the years 1865-1868 he served as Lord Rector of the [[University of St. Andrews]], where he gave an inaugural speech on the value of Culture.
  
Mill was offered a place to study at [[University of Cambridge|Cambridge University]], but instead followed his father to work for the [[British East India Company]], and after the company was dissolved he was elected for a brief period as an independent [[Member of Parliament]], representing the City and Westminster constituency from 1865 to 1868.  During his time as an MP, Mill advocated easing the burdens on [[Ireland]], and became the first person in parliament to call for women to be given the right to vote. In ''Considerations on Representative Government'', Mill called for various reforms of Parliament and voting, especially [[proportional representation]], the [[Single Transferable Vote]], and the extension of [[suffrage]].  He was godfather to [[Bertrand Russell]].
+
During the same period, 1865-8, he was an independent [[Member of Parliament]], representing the City and Westminster constituency from 1865 to 1868. <ref name="bi2o">Ibid. p.321-322</ref> During his time as an MP, Mill advocated easing the burdens on [[Ireland]], and became the first person in parliament to call for women to be given the right to vote. In ''Considerations on Representative Government'', Mill called for various reforms of Parliament and voting, especially [[proportional representation]], the [[Single Transferable Vote]], and the extension of [[suffrage]].  He was godfather to [[Bertrand Russell]].
  
 
[[Image:Taylor-harriet.jpg|left|frame|Harriet Taylor]]
 
[[Image:Taylor-harriet.jpg|left|frame|Harriet Taylor]]
  
In 1851, Mill married [[Harriet Taylor Mill|Harriet Taylor]] after 21 years of an at times intense friendship and love affair. Taylor was a significant influence on Mill's work and ideas during both friendship and marriage. His relationship with Harriet Taylor reinforced Mill's advocacy of [[Womens' rights|women's rights]].  He cites her influence in his final revision of ''On Liberty'', which was published shortly after her death, and appears to be obliquely cited in the text of ''[[The Subjection of Women]]''.
+
In 1851, Mill married [[Harriet Taylor Mill|Harriet Taylor]] after 21 years of an intimate friendship.  Taylor was married when they met, and their relationship was close but chaste during the years before her first husband died. Brilliant in her own right, Taylor was a significant influence on Mill's work and ideas during both friendship and marriage. His relationship with Harriet Taylor reinforced Mill's advocacy of [[Womens' rights|women's rights]].  He cites her influence in his final revision of ''On Liberty'', which was published shortly after her death, and she appears to be obliquely referenced in ''[[The Subjection of Women]]''.  Taylor died in 1858 after developing severe [[lung]] congestion, only seven years into her marriage to Mill.
  
 
He died in [[Avignon]], [[France]] in [[1873]], and is buried alongside his wife.
 
He died in [[Avignon]], [[France]] in [[1873]], and is buried alongside his wife.
  
==Work==
+
==Works==
One foundational book on the concept of liberty was ''[[On Liberty]]'', about the nature and limits of the power which can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual. One argument that Mill developed further than any previous philosopher was the [[harm principle]], that is, people should be free to engage in whatever behavior they wish as long as it does not harm others, acting in order to prevent the individual from harming himself is not legitimate, however from this Mill excludes those "incapable of self-government" such as young children or 'barbarians'.  
+
===Theory of liberty===
 +
 
 +
Mill's ''[[On Liberty]]'' is one of the founding texts of [[liberalism]] and one of the most important treatises ever written on the concept of liberty. The book explores the nature and limits of the power that can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual. One argument that Mill develops further than any previous philosopher is the [[harm principle]]. The harm principle holds that each individual has the right to act as he wants, so long as these actions do not harm others. If the action is self-regarding, that is, if it only directly affects the person undertaking the action, then society has no right to intervene, even if it feels the actor is harming himself. Mill excuses those who are "incapable of self-government" from this principle, such as young children or those living in “backward states of society". It is important to emphasise that Mill did not consider giving offence to constitute “harm”; an action could not be restricted because it violated the conventions or morals of a given society.
 +
 
 +
''On Liberty'' involves an impassioned defence of free speech. Mill argues that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress. We can never be sure, he contends, if a silenced opinion does not contain some element of the truth. He also argues that allowing people to air false opinions is productive for two reasons. First, individuals are more likely to abandon erroneous beliefs if they are engaged in an open exchange of ideas. Second, by forcing other individuals to re-examine and re-affirm their beliefs in the process of debate, these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma. It is not enough for Mill that one simply has an unexamined belief that happens to be true; one must understand why the belief in question is the true one.
 +
 
 +
Mill's statement of the harm principle in Chapter 1 of ''On Liberty'' — "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not sufficient warrant" — seems clear, but in fact entails a number of complications. For example, Mill explicitly states that “harms” may include acts of omission as well as acts of commission. Thus, failing to rescue a drowning child counts as a harmful act, as does failing to pay taxes, or failing to appear as a witness in court. All such harmful omissions may be regulated, according to Mill. By contrast, it does not count as harming someone if (without force or fraud) the affected individual consents to assume the risk: thus one may permissibly offer unsafe employment to others, provided there is no deception involved. (Mill does, however, recognise one limit to consent: society should not permit people to sell themselves into slavery). In these and other cases, it is important to keep in mind that the arguments in ''On Liberty'' are grounded on the principle of Utility, and not on appeals to [[natural rights]]. The question of what counts as a self-regarding action and what actions, whether of omission or commission, constitute harmful actions subject to regulation, continues to exercise interpreters of Mill. 
 +
 
 +
Mill is also famous for being one of the earliest and strongest supporters of women's liberation. His book ''[[The Subjection of Women]]'' is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author.  He felt that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times, a set of prejudices that severely impeded the progress of humanity.
 +
 
 +
===Utilitarianism===
  
The liberty John Stuart Mill speaks of in ''On Liberty'' is [[negative liberty]], defined by [[Isaiah Berlin]] as an absence or lack of impediments, obstacles or coercion. This is in contrast with his other idea of [[positive liberty]], a capacity for behavior, and the presence of conditions for freedom, be they material resources, a level of enlightenment, or the opportunity for political participation.
+
The canonical statement of Mill's Utilitarianism can be found in ''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]].'' This philosophy has a long tradition, arguably beginning, albeit in different forms, with [[Aristotle]], although Mill's account is primarily influenced by [[Jeremy Bentham]], and Mill's father [[James Mill]]. Mill’s famous formulation of Utilitarianism is known as the “greatest happiness principle.” It holds that one must always act so as to produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people. One of Mill's major contributions to Utilitarianism is his argument for the qualitative separation of pleasures.  Bentham treats all forms of happiness as equal, whereas Mill argues that intellectual and moral pleasures are superior to more physical forms of pleasure.  Mill distinguishes between "happiness" and "contentment," claiming that the former is of higher value than the latter, a belief wittily encapsulated in his statement that it is better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.
  
Thus Mill argued that it is Government's role only to remove the barriers, such as laws, to behaviors that do not harm others.  Crucially, he felt that offense did not constitute harm, and therefore supported almost total freedom of speech; only in cases where free speech would lead to direct harm did Mill wish to limit it. For example, whipping up an angry mob to go and attack people would '''not''' be defended in Mill's system.  Mill argued that free discourse was vital to ensure progress.  He argued that we could never be sure if a silenced opinion did not hold some portion of the truthIngeniously he also argued that even false opinions have worth, in that in refuting false opinions the holders of true opinions have their beliefs reaffirmed.  Without having to defend one's beliefs, Mill argued, the beliefs would become dead and we would forget why we held them at all. Mill argued that opposing arguments and opinions should be encouraged. The more a position is accepted the more it is important to have an advocate making the best contrary argument against it, and if one did not exist it should even be invented.
+
The qualitative account of happiness Mill advocates thus sheds light on his account presented in ''On Liberty''.  As Mill suggests in that text, utility is to be conceived in relation to mankind "as a progressive being," which includes the development and exercise of our rational capacities as we strive to achieve a “higher mode of existence"Thus the rejection of censorship and paternalism is intended to provide the necessary social conditions for the achievement of knowledge and the greatest ability for the greatest number to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities.  
  
Though Mill's statement of the harm principle in Chapter 1 of ''On Liberty,'' i.e., "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not sufficient warrant," might seem particularly determinate, Mill notes a number of exceptions that connect his work in ''On Liberty'' with his mature [[Utilitarianism|philosophy of Utilitarianism]].  Mill notes that the state can and ought to prevent people from selling themselves into slavery.  Furthermore, he insists that it would be acceptable to require people to pay taxes for the maintenance of public goods.  He also seems to explicitly support "Good Samaritain" laws, which insist that important benefits to others are legally required.  Though these exceptions appear to be patently incompatible with his harm principle, Mill notes that the principles of ''On Liberty'' are explicitly defended by the principle of Utility.  Thus, when the principle of Utility is applied to the categorical statement of the harm principle, yield certain important exceptions.
+
===Economic philosophy===
  
The canonical statement of Mill's Utilitarianism is to be found in ''[[Utilitarianism (book)|Utilitarianism]]''This philosophy had a long tradition, arguably stretching (in some form or other) back to Aristotle, although Mill's account was primarily influenced by [[Jeremy Bentham]], and Mill's father [[James Mill]]. Utilitarianism holds that actions are good in proportion to the amount of happiness produced and number of people happiness is produced in. Mill's main contribution to Utilitarianism is the argument for a qualitative separation of pleasures. Bentham had treated all forms of happiness as equal, whereas Mill argued that intellectual and moral pleasures and developments were superior to more physical forms of pleasure.  Mill separated "happiness" and "contentment", and claimed that the former was more clearly constituted by the higher modes of existence, as illustrated by his claim that it is better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.
+
Mill's early economic philosophy was one of [[free market]]sHowever, he accepted interventions in the economy, such as a tax on alcohol, if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds. He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare. [http://www.ifaw.org/ifaw/dfiles/file_285.pdf] Mill believed that "equality of taxation" meant "equality of sacrifice" and that [[progressive tax]]ation penalised those who worked harder and saved more and was therefore "a mild form of robbery".[http://www.irefeurope.org/col_docs/doc_51_fr.pdf]
  
The qualitative account of happiness Mill advocates thus sheds light on his account presented in ''On Liberty''.  As Mill suggests in that text, utility is to be conceived in relation to mankind "as a progressive being," which include the development and exercise of our rational capacities in the living of a higher "mode of existence". Thus the rejection of censorship and paternalist, offense, and moralist legislation is intended to provide the necessary social conditions of the achievement of knowledge and the greatest ability for the greatest number to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities - most clearly stated in Chapter Three of ''On Liberty''. The exceptions, however, also follow from his Utilitarianism, including most notably the rejection of selling one's self into slavery - for this is a clear case in which the state can successfully intervene in requiring particular citizens to live according to their higher capacities.
+
Mill's ''Principles of Political Economy'', first published in 1848, was one of the most widely read of all books on economics in the period.<ref>{{cite book
 +
  | author=Ekelund, Robert B., Jr. and Hébert, Robert F.
 +
  | title=A history of economic theory and method
 +
  | edition=4th
 +
  | Publisher=Waveland Press [Long Grove, Illinois]
 +
  | year=1997
 +
  | id=ISBN 1-57766-381-0
 +
  | page=172}}</ref>  As Adam Smith's ''Wealth of Nations'' had during an earlier period, Mill's ''Principles'' dominated economics teaching. (In the case of Oxford University it was the standard text until 1919, probably because the text that replaced it was written by Cambridge's Alfred Marshall). Mill was the last great ''political economist'' who championed the market system.{{fact}} After him the great economic thinkers eschewed value judgements and stuck to developing theory while allowing others to decide on policy choices.{{fact}}
  
Mill's main economic philosophy was one of [[laissez faire]], but he accepted interventions in the economy, such as a tax on alcohol, if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds. He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare. [http://www.ifaw.org/ifaw/dfiles/file_285.pdf]
+
Later in life, Mill moved to favor more socialist-oriented politics.[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/#PolEco]
  
Mill's [[magnum opus]] was his ''[[A System of Logic]], Ratiocinative and Inductive'', which went through several revisions and editions. [[William Whewell]]'s ''History of the Inductive Sciences'' ([[1837]]) was a chief influence. The reputation of this work is largely due to his analysis of inductive proof, in contrast to Aristotle's syllogisms, which are deductive. Mill describes the five basic principles of induction which have come to be known as [[Mill's Methods]] - the method of agreement, the method of difference, the joint or double method of agreement and difference, the method of residues, and that of concomitant variations. The common feature of these methods, the one real method of scientific inquiry, is that of elimination. All the other methods are thus subordinate to the method of difference.  It was  also Mill's attempt to postulate a [[epistemology|theory of knowledge]], in the same vein as [[John Locke]].
+
===Logic===
  
Mill is also famous for being one of the earliest and strongest male supporters of women's liberation.  His book ''[[The Subjection of Women]]'' is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author. He felt that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times, one which impeded the progress of humanity. This was an issue he actively supported throughout his life, writing many newspaper articles and delivering many speeches on it.
+
Mill's ''[[magnum opus]]'' was his ''[[A System of Logic]], Ratiocinative and Inductive'', which went through several revisions and editions. [[William Whewell]]'s ''History of the Inductive Sciences'' ([[1837]]) was a chief influence. The reputation of this work is largely due to his analysis of inductive proof, in contrast to Aristotle's syllogisms, which are deductive. Mill describes the five basic principles of induction which have come to be known as [[Mill's Methods]] - the method of agreement, the method of difference, the joint or double method of agreement and difference, the method of residues, and that of concomitant variations. The common feature of these methods, the one real method of scientific inquiry, is that of elimination. All the other methods are thus subordinate to the method of difference. It was also Mill's attempt to postulate a [[epistemology|theory of knowledge]], in the same vein as [[John Locke]].
  
 
He was also the first to use the term [[dystopia]].<ref name="Mill">John Stuart Mill uses the term dystopia in a parliamentary speech, possibly the first recorded use of the term. [http://hem.passagen.se/replikant/dystopia_timeline.htm Exploring Dystopia], last accessed on 19th March 2006, see also [http://books.google.com/books?ie=UTF-8&vid=ISBN157181440X&id=3ye0vWc85eYC&pg=PA230&lpg=PA230&dq=John+Stuart+Mill+dystopia+1868&sig=YesYZ8kSJZhhi2NdHdOQdZ0nDTk]</ref>
 
He was also the first to use the term [[dystopia]].<ref name="Mill">John Stuart Mill uses the term dystopia in a parliamentary speech, possibly the first recorded use of the term. [http://hem.passagen.se/replikant/dystopia_timeline.htm Exploring Dystopia], last accessed on 19th March 2006, see also [http://books.google.com/books?ie=UTF-8&vid=ISBN157181440X&id=3ye0vWc85eYC&pg=PA230&lpg=PA230&dq=John+Stuart+Mill+dystopia+1868&sig=YesYZ8kSJZhhi2NdHdOQdZ0nDTk]</ref>
 
==Books written by John Stuart Mill==
 
*''[[On Liberty]]'' (ISBN 159986973X)
 
  
 
==Writings==
 
==Writings==
Line 77: Line 91:
 
*([[1865]]) ''[[Examinations of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy]]''
 
*([[1865]]) ''[[Examinations of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy]]''
 
*([[1865]]) ''[[Auguste Comte and Positivism]]''
 
*([[1865]]) ''[[Auguste Comte and Positivism]]''
 +
*([[1867]]) ''Inaugural Address at St. Andrews'' - Rectorial Inaugural Address at the [[University of St. Andrews]], concerning the value of culture.
 
*([[1869]]) ''[[The Subjection of Women]]''
 
*([[1869]]) ''[[The Subjection of Women]]''
 
*([[1873]]) ''[[Autobiography (John Stuart Mill)|Autobiography]]''
 
*([[1873]]) ''[[Autobiography (John Stuart Mill)|Autobiography]]''
 
*([[1874]]) ''[[Three Essays on Religion]]''
 
*([[1874]]) ''[[Three Essays on Religion]]''
 
==Other==
 
*([[1867]]) ''Inaugural Address at St. Andrews'' - Rectorial Inaugural Address at the [[University of St. Andrews]], concerning the value of culture.
 
  
 
==See also==
 
==See also==
Line 90: Line 102:
  
 
==References==
 
==References==
:Inline:
+
;Inline:
 
<references/>
 
<references/>
:General:
+
;General:
 
*David O. Brink, "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," in ''Philosophy and Public Affairs'' 21 (1992), 67-103.
 
*David O. Brink, "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," in ''Philosophy and Public Affairs'' 21 (1992), 67-103.
 
*Sterling Harwood, "Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism," in Louis P. Pojman, ed., Moral Philosophy: A Reader (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1998), and in Sterling Harwood, ed., Business as Ethical and Business as Usual (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1996), Chapter 7, and in [http://www.sterlingharwood.com]www.sterlingharwood.com.
 
*Sterling Harwood, "Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism," in Louis P. Pojman, ed., Moral Philosophy: A Reader (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1998), and in Sterling Harwood, ed., Business as Ethical and Business as Usual (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1996), Chapter 7, and in [http://www.sterlingharwood.com]www.sterlingharwood.com.
Line 102: Line 114:
 
{{Wikisource author}}
 
{{Wikisource author}}
 
{{Wikiquote}}
 
{{Wikiquote}}
 +
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/bios/Mill.html John Stuart Mill] in the ''Concise Encyclopedia of Economics'' on [[Econlib]]
 
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/ John Stuart Mill] in the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
 
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill/ John Stuart Mill] in the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
 
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/m/milljs.htm John Stuart Mill] in the [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
 
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/m/milljs.htm John Stuart Mill] in the [[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
* [http://metalibri.incubadora.fapesp.br/portal/authors/m/mill-john-stuart MetaLibri Digital Library]: John Stuart Mill's folder.
 
 
* {{gutenberg author|id=John_Stuart_Mill|name=John Stuart Mill}}
 
* {{gutenberg author|id=John_Stuart_Mill|name=John Stuart Mill}}
 +
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlLbty.html ''On Liberty''], by John Stuart Mill. Definitive edition, free on [[Econlib]]
 +
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlP.html ''Principles of Political Economy''], by John Stuart Mill. Definitive edition, free on [[Econlib]]
 +
* [http://www.econlib.org/library/Mill/mlUQP.html ''Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy''], by John Stuart Mill. Definitive edition, free on [[Econlib]]
 +
* [http://oll.libertyfund.org/Intros/MillJS.php Works of John Stuart Mill] in The Online Library of Liberty
 
* [http://utilitarian.net/jsmill John Stuart Mill]. Extensive collection of links to writings by and about J.S. Mill.
 
* [http://utilitarian.net/jsmill John Stuart Mill]. Extensive collection of links to writings by and about J.S. Mill.
 
* [http://atheisme.free.fr/Biographies/Mill_e.htm Biography, works and quotes of John Stuart Mill]
 
* [http://atheisme.free.fr/Biographies/Mill_e.htm Biography, works and quotes of John Stuart Mill]
* [http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/ More easily readable versions of On Liberty and Utilitarianism]
+
* [http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/ More easily readable versions of On Liberty, Utilitarianism, and Three Essays on Religion]
 
*[http://www.utilitarianism.com/millauto/ Autobiography of John Stuart Mill]
 
*[http://www.utilitarianism.com/millauto/ Autobiography of John Stuart Mill]
 +
* MetaLibri Digital Library:
 +
**'''[http://metalibri.incubadora.fapesp.br/portal/authors/m/john-stuart-mill/utilitarianism/ Utilitarianism]'''
 
*[http://www.la-articles.org.uk/Did%20Mill%20ever%20prefer%20socialism%20to%20liberalism.doc ''How far did JS Mill let liberalism down? Did he prefer Socialism to Liberalism?''] by David McDonagh
 
*[http://www.la-articles.org.uk/Did%20Mill%20ever%20prefer%20socialism%20to%20liberalism.doc ''How far did JS Mill let liberalism down? Did he prefer Socialism to Liberalism?''] by David McDonagh
 
*[http://catallarchy.net/blog/archives/2006/05/19/welcome-to-catallarchys-mill-fest-the-bicentennial-edition/ Mill-fest: The Bicentennial Edition''] by the blog Catallarchy
 
*[http://catallarchy.net/blog/archives/2006/05/19/welcome-to-catallarchys-mill-fest-the-bicentennial-edition/ Mill-fest: The Bicentennial Edition''] by the blog Catallarchy
 
  
 
[[Category:19th century philosophers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:19th century philosophers|Mill, John Stuart]]
Line 121: Line 138:
 
[[Category:Classical economists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Classical economists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English philosophers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English philosophers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
[[Category:Philosophers of language|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English political writers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:English political writers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Political theorists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Political theorists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Feminist writers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 
[[Category:Feminist writers|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
[[Category:Voting theorists|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
[[Category:People from London|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
[[Category:People commemorated by blue plaques|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
[[Category:Anglo-Scots|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
[[Category:1806 births|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
[[Category:1873 deaths|Mill, John Stuart]]
 +
 +
[[bs:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[bg:Джон Стюарт Мил]]
 +
[[ca:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[cs:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[da:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[de:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[et:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[el:Τζον Στιούαρτ Μιλλ]]
 +
[[es:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[eo:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[fa:استوارت میل]]
 +
[[fr:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[gl:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[ko:존 스튜어트 밀]]
 +
[[io:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[is:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[it:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[he:ג'ון סטיוארט מיל]]
 +
[[hu:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[nl:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[ja:ジョン・スチュアート・ミル]]
 +
[[no:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[oc:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[pl:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[pt:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[ro:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[ru:Милль, Джон Стюарт]]
 +
[[simple:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[sk:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[fi:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[sv:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[vi:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[tr:John Stuart Mill]]
 +
[[zh:约翰·斯图尔特·密尔]]
 +
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
  
{{Credit|66256488}}
+
{{Credit|94402732}}

Revision as of 18:59, 22 December 2006

Western Philosophy
19th-century philosophy
JohnStuartMill.JPG
Name: John Stuart Mill
Birth: May 20, 1806 (Pentonville, London, England)
Death: May 8, 1873 (Avignon, France)
School/tradition: Empiricism, Utilitarianism
Main interests
Political philosophy, Ethics, Economics, Inductive Logic
Notable ideas
public/private sphere, hierarchy of pleasures in Utilitarianism, liberalism, early liberal feminism, first system of inductive logic
Influences Influenced
Plato, Aristotle, Aquinas, Hobbes, Locke, Bentham, Smith, Ricardo, Tocqueville, James Mill, Saint-Simon (Utopian Socialists)[1] Many philosophers after him, including John Rawls, Robert Nozick, Bertrand Russell, Karl Popper, Ronald Dworkin, H.L.A. Hart, Peter Singer

John Stuart Mill (May 20, 1806 – May 8, 1873), an English philosopher and political economist, was an influential liberal thinker of the 19th century. He was an advocate of utilitarianism, the ethical theory that was systemised by his godfather, Jeremy Bentham, but adapted to German romanticism. It is usually suggested that Mill is an advocate of Negative liberty. However, this has been contested by many academics, notably Dr. David Walker of Newcastle University in England.

Biography

John Stuart Mill was born in Pentonville, London, the oldest son of the Scottish philosopher and historian James Mill. John Stuart was educated by his father, with the advice and assistance of Jeremy Bentham and Francis Place. He was given an extremely rigorous, some would say harsh, upbringing, and was deliberately shielded from association with children his own age other than his siblings. His father, a follower of Bentham and an adherent of associationism, had as his explicit aim to create a genius intellect that would carry on the cause of utilitarianism and its implementation after he and Bentham were dead.

John Stuart's feats as a child were exceptional; at the age of three he was taught the Greek alphabet and long lists of Greek words with their English equivalents. By the age of eight he had read Aesop's Fables, Xenophon's Anabasis, and the whole of Herodotus, and was acquainted with Lucian, Diogenes Laërtius, Isocrates and six dialogues of Plato (see his Autobiography). He had also read a great deal of history in English and had been taught arithmetic.

A contemporary record of Mill's studies from eight to thirteen is published in Bain's sketch of his life. It suggests that his autobiography rather understates the amount of work done. At the age of eight he began learning Latin, Euclid, and algebra, and was appointed schoolmaster to the younger children of the family. His main reading was still history, but he went through all the Latin and Greek authors commonly read in the schools and universities at the time. He was not taught to compose either in Latin or in Greek, and he was never an exact scholar; it was for the subject matter that he was required to read, and by the age of ten he could read Plato and Demosthenes with ease. His father's History of India was published in 1818; immediately thereafter, about the age of twelve, John began a thorough study of the scholastic logic, at the same time reading Aristotle's logical treatises in the original language. In the following year he was introduced to political economy and studied Adam Smith and David Ricardo with his father—ultimately completing their classical economic view of factors of production.

This intensive study however had injurious effects on Mill's mental health, and state of mind. At the age of 21 he suffered a nervous breakdown; as explained in chapter V of his Autobiography, this was caused by the great physical and mental arduousness of his studies which had suppressed any feelings he might have developed normally in childhood. Nevertheless, this depression eventually began to dissipate, as he began to find solace in the poetry of William Wordsworth. His capacity for emotion resurfaced, Mill remarking that the "cloud gradually drew off".

Mill refused to study at Oxford University or Cambridge University, because he refused to take Anglican orders.[2] Instead he followed his father to work for the British East India Company until 1858. Between the years 1865-1868 he served as Lord Rector of the University of St. Andrews, where he gave an inaugural speech on the value of Culture.

During the same period, 1865-8, he was an independent Member of Parliament, representing the City and Westminster constituency from 1865 to 1868. [3] During his time as an MP, Mill advocated easing the burdens on Ireland, and became the first person in parliament to call for women to be given the right to vote. In Considerations on Representative Government, Mill called for various reforms of Parliament and voting, especially proportional representation, the Single Transferable Vote, and the extension of suffrage. He was godfather to Bertrand Russell.

Harriet Taylor

In 1851, Mill married Harriet Taylor after 21 years of an intimate friendship. Taylor was married when they met, and their relationship was close but chaste during the years before her first husband died. Brilliant in her own right, Taylor was a significant influence on Mill's work and ideas during both friendship and marriage. His relationship with Harriet Taylor reinforced Mill's advocacy of women's rights. He cites her influence in his final revision of On Liberty, which was published shortly after her death, and she appears to be obliquely referenced in The Subjection of Women. Taylor died in 1858 after developing severe lung congestion, only seven years into her marriage to Mill.

He died in Avignon, France in 1873, and is buried alongside his wife.

Works

Theory of liberty

Mill's On Liberty is one of the founding texts of liberalism and one of the most important treatises ever written on the concept of liberty. The book explores the nature and limits of the power that can be legitimately exercised by society over the individual. One argument that Mill develops further than any previous philosopher is the harm principle. The harm principle holds that each individual has the right to act as he wants, so long as these actions do not harm others. If the action is self-regarding, that is, if it only directly affects the person undertaking the action, then society has no right to intervene, even if it feels the actor is harming himself. Mill excuses those who are "incapable of self-government" from this principle, such as young children or those living in “backward states of society". It is important to emphasise that Mill did not consider giving offence to constitute “harm”; an action could not be restricted because it violated the conventions or morals of a given society.

On Liberty involves an impassioned defence of free speech. Mill argues that free discourse is a necessary condition for intellectual and social progress. We can never be sure, he contends, if a silenced opinion does not contain some element of the truth. He also argues that allowing people to air false opinions is productive for two reasons. First, individuals are more likely to abandon erroneous beliefs if they are engaged in an open exchange of ideas. Second, by forcing other individuals to re-examine and re-affirm their beliefs in the process of debate, these beliefs are kept from declining into mere dogma. It is not enough for Mill that one simply has an unexamined belief that happens to be true; one must understand why the belief in question is the true one.

Mill's statement of the harm principle in Chapter 1 of On Liberty — "The only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilised community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others. His own good, either physical or moral, is not sufficient warrant" — seems clear, but in fact entails a number of complications. For example, Mill explicitly states that “harms” may include acts of omission as well as acts of commission. Thus, failing to rescue a drowning child counts as a harmful act, as does failing to pay taxes, or failing to appear as a witness in court. All such harmful omissions may be regulated, according to Mill. By contrast, it does not count as harming someone if (without force or fraud) the affected individual consents to assume the risk: thus one may permissibly offer unsafe employment to others, provided there is no deception involved. (Mill does, however, recognise one limit to consent: society should not permit people to sell themselves into slavery). In these and other cases, it is important to keep in mind that the arguments in On Liberty are grounded on the principle of Utility, and not on appeals to natural rights. The question of what counts as a self-regarding action and what actions, whether of omission or commission, constitute harmful actions subject to regulation, continues to exercise interpreters of Mill.

Mill is also famous for being one of the earliest and strongest supporters of women's liberation. His book The Subjection of Women is one of the earliest written on this subject by a male author. He felt that the oppression of women was one of the few remaining relics from ancient times, a set of prejudices that severely impeded the progress of humanity.

Utilitarianism

The canonical statement of Mill's Utilitarianism can be found in Utilitarianism. This philosophy has a long tradition, arguably beginning, albeit in different forms, with Aristotle, although Mill's account is primarily influenced by Jeremy Bentham, and Mill's father James Mill. Mill’s famous formulation of Utilitarianism is known as the “greatest happiness principle.” It holds that one must always act so as to produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people. One of Mill's major contributions to Utilitarianism is his argument for the qualitative separation of pleasures. Bentham treats all forms of happiness as equal, whereas Mill argues that intellectual and moral pleasures are superior to more physical forms of pleasure. Mill distinguishes between "happiness" and "contentment," claiming that the former is of higher value than the latter, a belief wittily encapsulated in his statement that it is better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisfied.

The qualitative account of happiness Mill advocates thus sheds light on his account presented in On Liberty. As Mill suggests in that text, utility is to be conceived in relation to mankind "as a progressive being," which includes the development and exercise of our rational capacities as we strive to achieve a “higher mode of existence". Thus the rejection of censorship and paternalism is intended to provide the necessary social conditions for the achievement of knowledge and the greatest ability for the greatest number to develop and exercise their deliberative and rational capacities.

Economic philosophy

Mill's early economic philosophy was one of free markets. However, he accepted interventions in the economy, such as a tax on alcohol, if there were sufficient utilitarian grounds. He also accepted the principle of legislative intervention for the purpose of animal welfare. [2] Mill believed that "equality of taxation" meant "equality of sacrifice" and that progressive taxation penalised those who worked harder and saved more and was therefore "a mild form of robbery".[3]

Mill's Principles of Political Economy, first published in 1848, was one of the most widely read of all books on economics in the period.[4] As Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations had during an earlier period, Mill's Principles dominated economics teaching. (In the case of Oxford University it was the standard text until 1919, probably because the text that replaced it was written by Cambridge's Alfred Marshall). Mill was the last great political economist who championed the market system.[citation needed] After him the great economic thinkers eschewed value judgements and stuck to developing theory while allowing others to decide on policy choices.[citation needed]

Later in life, Mill moved to favor more socialist-oriented politics.[4]

Logic

Mill's magnum opus was his A System of Logic, Ratiocinative and Inductive, which went through several revisions and editions. William Whewell's History of the Inductive Sciences (1837) was a chief influence. The reputation of this work is largely due to his analysis of inductive proof, in contrast to Aristotle's syllogisms, which are deductive. Mill describes the five basic principles of induction which have come to be known as Mill's Methods - the method of agreement, the method of difference, the joint or double method of agreement and difference, the method of residues, and that of concomitant variations. The common feature of these methods, the one real method of scientific inquiry, is that of elimination. All the other methods are thus subordinate to the method of difference. It was also Mill's attempt to postulate a theory of knowledge, in the same vein as John Locke.

He was also the first to use the term dystopia.[5]

Writings

Major works are in bold type.

  • (1843) A System of Logic
  • (1844) Essays on Some Unsettled Questions of Political Economy
  • (1848) Principles of Political Economy
  • (1859) On Liberty
  • (1861) Considerations on Representative Government
  • (1863) Utilitarianism
  • (1865) Examinations of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy
  • (1865) Auguste Comte and Positivism
  • (1867) Inaugural Address at St. Andrews - Rectorial Inaugural Address at the University of St. Andrews, concerning the value of culture.
  • (1869) The Subjection of Women
  • (1873) Autobiography
  • (1874) Three Essays on Religion

See also

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

Inline
  1. Friedrich Hayek (1941). The Counter-Revolution of Science. Economica 8 (31): 281-320.
  2. Capaldi, Nicholas. John Stuart Mill: A Biography. p.33, Cambridge, 2004, ISBN 0-521-62024-4.
  3. Ibid. p.321-322
  4. Ekelund, Robert B., Jr. and Hébert, Robert F. (1997). A history of economic theory and method, 4th. ISBN 1-57766-381-0. 
  5. John Stuart Mill uses the term dystopia in a parliamentary speech, possibly the first recorded use of the term. Exploring Dystopia, last accessed on 19th March 2006, see also [1]
General
  • David O. Brink, "Mill's Deliberative Utilitarianism," in Philosophy and Public Affairs 21 (1992), 67-103.
  • Sterling Harwood, "Eleven Objections to Utilitarianism," in Louis P. Pojman, ed., Moral Philosophy: A Reader (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Co., 1998), and in Sterling Harwood, ed., Business as Ethical and Business as Usual (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1996), Chapter 7, and in [5]www.sterlingharwood.com.
  • Robinson, Dave & Groves, Judy (2003). Introducing Political Philosophy. Icon Books. ISBN 1-84046-450-X.
  • Samuel Hollander - The Economics of John Stuart Mill (University of Toronto Press, 1985)
  • Mill, John Stuart, A System of Logic, University Press of the Pacific, Honolulu, 2002, ISBN 1-4102-0252-6

External links

Wikisource
Wikisource has original works written by or about:
Wikiquote-logo-en.png
Wikiquote has a collection of quotations related to:

bs:John Stuart Mill bg:Джон Стюарт Мил ca:John Stuart Mill cs:John Stuart Mill da:John Stuart Mill de:John Stuart Mill et:John Stuart Mill el:Τζον Στιούαρτ Μιλλ es:John Stuart Mill eo:John Stuart Mill fa:استوارت میل fr:John Stuart Mill gl:John Stuart Mill ko:존 스튜어트 밀 io:John Stuart Mill is:John Stuart Mill it:John Stuart Mill he:ג'ון סטיוארט מיל hu:John Stuart Mill nl:John Stuart Mill ja:ジョン・スチュアート・ミル no:John Stuart Mill oc:John Stuart Mill pl:John Stuart Mill pt:John Stuart Mill ro:John Stuart Mill ru:Милль, Джон Стюарт simple:John Stuart Mill sk:John Stuart Mill fi:John Stuart Mill sv:John Stuart Mill vi:John Stuart Mill tr:John Stuart Mill zh:约翰·斯图尔特·密尔

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.