Difference between revisions of "Altruism" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 1: Line 1:
{{verify}}{{claimed}}
+
“Psychological altruism” refers to behavior that both benefits others and is undertaken for their benefit. In this sense, altruism is opposed to [[egoism]]. Philosophical concerns relating to altruism include whether altruism is in fact possible, that is, whether we ever in fact do act for reasons other than our own best interests.  
{{original research}}
 
{{for|the ethical doctrine|Altruism (ethics)}}
 
'''Altruism''' is the willful sacrifice of one's own interests or well-being for the sake of something that is non-self. It is also often defined as being the selfless concern for the [[Quality of life|welfare]] of others. It is a traditional [[virtue]] in many cultures, and central to many religious traditions. In English, this idea was often described as the [[Ethic of reciprocity|Golden rule of ethics]]. In [[Buddhism]] it is considered a fundamental property of [[human nature]]. However, altruism also includes those who force others to sacrifice for some higher cause, even if it is a nonhuman or nonexistent one. Communism, [[Nazism]], Fascism, and [[Conservatism]] are altruistic philosophies, as are most of the world's [[religions]]. Many think that [[socialism]], welfare statism, and [[liberalism]] are also altruistic, but they might in fact deliver a net gain to all members of a society which does not limit freedom or [[capitalism]] too severely. At any rate, they are far less altruistic than most other options, and many conservative altruists criticize them for promoting too much [[selfishness]] and [[hedonism]].
 
  
Altruism can be distinguished from a feeling of [[loyalty]] and [[duty]], although both of these are in fact altruistic. Sheer altruism focuses on a motivation to help others without reward, while duty focuses on a moral obligation towards a specific 'higher' individual (for example, [[God]], a [[monarch|king]]), a specific organization (for example, a [[government]]), or an abstract concept (for example, [[patriotism]] etc). Some individuals may feel altruism without duty, while others may not.  Pure altruism is giving without regard to reward or the benefits of recognition.
+
“Biological altruism” refers to the tendency of some organisms to behave in ways that benefit other creatures at a cost to themselves. Biological altruism is widespread in the natural world. Examples include sterile worker bees devoting their whole lives to caring for their queen, and the “helpers” of certain bird species, who guard the nest and care for the young of other breeding pairs. Altruism is of significance for socio-biology, because its existence is apparently in conflict with basic principles of [[Darwin]]’s theory of [[evolution]], which seem to suggest that organisms would not behave in ways that decreased their own reproductive fitness.
  
The concept has a long history in [[philosophical]] and [[ethical]] thought, and has more recently become a topic for [[psychologists]], [[sociologists]], [[evolutionary biologists]], and [[ethology|ethologists]]. While ideas about altruism from one field can have an impact on the other fields, the different methods and focuses of these fields lead to different perspectives on altruism.
+
==Psychological Altruism==
  
Subsequent thinkers, including Dr. [[Martin Luther King]] have added to Comte's early reflections in the following way:
+
Psychological altruism (sometimes called ‘real’ altruism) refers to behavior that benefits others, often at a cost to the agent, which is undertaken for the motive of benefiting others. Behavior benefiting other people is not necessarily altruistic. For example, if one helped out another person with the motive of enhancing one’s own reputation, this behavior would not count as altruistic, but as self-interested.
  
The ethical doctrine of altruism has also been called ''the ethic of altruism'', ''moralistic altruism'', and ''ethical altruism''.
+
Psychological altruism is opposed to psychological [[egoism]]. Psychological egoism is an empirical hypothesis about human behaviour: it holds that every human has only one ultimate goal: his or her own good (where this good can variously be defined as welfare, happiness or pleasure). Thus, while it allows for action that does not accomplish its goal of maximising self-interest, as well as action that is at odds with one’s intentions (a weak will), most forms of psychological egoism rule out both altruistic behaviour and acting solely out of respect for duty.  
  
==Altruism in ethics==
+
One basic philosophical concern relating to altruism is whether it is in fact possible, that is, whether we ever in fact do act for reasons other than our own best interests. Since egoism is opposed to altruism, arguments for psychological egoism are arguments against the possibility of altruism. Psychological egoism is motivated in various ways: Firstly, it is sometimes thought to follow from widespread and frequent observations of self-interested behaviour. Secondly, we often motivate people to act in certain ways by appealing to their self-interest in the form of rewards and punishments, and thirdly, acts appearing altruistic can often be shown to be motivated by self-interest.
{{main|Altruism (ethics)}}
 
The word "altruism" (derived from [[French language|French]] ''autre'' "other", in its turn derived from [[Latin]] ''alter'' "other") was coined by [[Auguste Comte]], the French founder of [[positivism]], in order to describe the ethical doctrine he supported. He believed that individuals had a moral obligation to serve the interest of others or the "greater good" of humanity. Comte says, in his Catechisme Positiviste, that ''"[the] social point of view cannot tolerate the notion of rights, for such notion rests on individualism. We are born under a load of obligations of every kind, to our predecessors, to our successors, to our contemporaries. After our birth these obligations increase or accumulate, for it is some time before we can return any service.... This ["to live for others"], the definitive formula of human morality, gives a direct sanction exclusively to our instincts of benevolence, the common source of happiness and duty. [Man must serve] Humanity, whose we are entirely."'' As the name of the ethical doctrine is "altruism," doing what the ethical doctrine prescribes has also come to be referred to by the term "altruism" — serving others through placing their interests above one's own.
 
  
Philosophers who support [[ethical egoism|egoism]] have argued that altruism is demeaning to the individual and that no moral obligation to help others actually exists. [[Nietzsche]] asserts that altruism is predicated on the assumption that others are more important than one's self and that such a position is degrading and demeaning. He also claims that it was very uncommon for people in Europe to consider the sacrifice of one's own interests for others as virtuous until after the advent of Christianity.
+
In contrast with egoism, psychological altruism says that human beings do sometimes act for the interests of others out of a genuine concern for their well being. Consider an example in which a soldier throws himself on a grenade in order to prevent other people from being killed. His motivation for this act of self-sacrifice might be plausibly a desire to save the other peoples’ lives. This seems to qualify his act as altruistic because he has benefited other people, at great cost to himself, from the motivation of saving their lives.  
  
Advocates of altruism as an ethical doctrine maintain that one ought to act, or refrain from acting, so that benefit or [[good (economics)|good]] is bestowed on other people, if necessary to the exclusion of one's own interests (Note that refraining from murdering someone, for example, is not altruism since he is not receiving a benefit or being helped, as he already has his life; this would amount to the same thing as ignoring someone).
+
When faced with examples of altruistic behaviour such as these, egoists may try to defend their position by arguing that the soldier’s action, although it appears to be altruistic, ought to be explained by some more fundamental self-interested motive. Perhaps the soldier believes in an afterlife in which he will be rewarded ten-fold for his apparently selfless act on earth, or perhaps, if he had not hurled himself on the grenade, he would be overcome by guilt and a concomitant sense of self-loathing. In both cases then, he is, at least from his perspective, acting in his self-interest by acting in this apparently selfless manner.  
  
==Altruism in ethology and evolutionary biology==
+
There are two problems with this response. The first is that, while it might explain many instances of apparent self-sacrifice as motivated by egoistic concerns, it does not necessarily cover all cases. The psychological egoist must argue that all instances of ostensible altruistic behaviour are in fact motivated by self-interested desires. If, for instance, our soldier disagrees with this, and claims that his action was truly altruistic in motivation, the egoist must respond that he is lying or is deceiving himself. At this point, however, egoism turns out to be trivially true, which means that it is un-falsifiable, since there is no empirical instance that could in principle disprove the hypothesis; it provides no useful information and therefore fails as an empirical theory.  
In the science of [[ethology]] (the study of behavior), and more generally in the study of [[social evolution]], altruism refers to behavior by an individual that increases the [[fitness (biology)|fitness]] of another individual while decreasing the fitness of the actor. Recent developments in [[game theory]] (look into [[ultimatum game]]) have provided some explanations for apparent altruism, as have traditional evolutionary analyses. Among the proposed mechanisms are:
 
  
* [[Behavioural manipulation]] (for example, by certain [[parasites]] that can alter the behavior of the host)
+
==Psychological altruism in its historical context==
* [[Bounded rationality]] (for example, [[Herbert Simon]])
 
* [[Conscience]]
 
* [[Kin selection]] including [[eusociality]] (see also "[[selfish gene]]")
 
* [[Meme]]s (by influencing behavior to favour their own spread, for example,  [[religion]])
 
* [[Reciprocal altruism]], mutual aid
 
* [[Sexual selection]]
 
* [[Reciprocity (social psychology)]]
 
** [[Indirect reciprocity]] (for example, [[reputation]])
 
** [[Strong reciprocity]]
 
* [[Pseudo-reciprocity]]
 
  
The study of altruism was the initial impetus behind [[George R. Price]]'s development of the [[Price equation]] which is a mathematical equation used to study genetic evolution. An interesting example of altruism is found in the cellular [[slime mould]]s, such as ''[[Dictyostelid|Dictyostelium]] mucoroides''. These protists live as individual [[amoebae]] until starved, at which point they aggregate and form a multicellular fruiting body in which some cells sacrifice themselves to promote the survival of other cells in the fruiting body. Social behavior and altruism share many similarities to the interactions between the many parts (cells, genes) of an organism, but are distinguished by the ability of each individual to reproduce indefinitely without an absolute requirement for its neighbors.
+
All ancient ethical theories are forms of [[eudaimonism]], conceiving of human persons as fundamentally directed towards their individual eudaimonia, or (in its common English translation) happiness. It might seem to follow from this that ancient ethics cannot accommodate altruism, because it conceives of each person as ultimately focused on his or her individual well being.  
  
Jorge Moll and Jordan Grafman, neuroscientists at the National Institutes of Health have some results showing, that when test were carried out on volunteers placing the interests of others before their own, the generosity activated a primitive part of the brain that usually lights up in response to food or sex. Altruism, the experiment suggested, was not a superior moral faculty that suppresses basic selfish urges but rather was basic to the brain, hard-wired and pleasurable.<ref name="brain">[http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-dyn/content/article/2007/05/27/AR2007052701056.html If It Feels Good to Be Good, It Might Be Only Natural on Washingtonpost.com]</ref>
+
This appearance may be deceiving, however, because all the main writers—such as [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], and the [[Stoics]]—emphasize the importance of civic virtues, such as justice, as essential components of individual eudaimonia. If one conceives of the virtue of justice as involving a disposition to respect the interests of one’s fellow citizens because of one’s regard for the importance of these interests, it is easy to see that someone with the virtue of justice will behave altruistically. Given that the main ancient writers conceive of justice as an indispensable component of the good life, it follows that they also regard altruism as a component in the happy life. On Plato’s version of this idea, the altruistic person, in the sense of the just person, is someone who acquires and preserves a state of psychological harmony, which is necessary (and perhaps sufficient) for the attainment of happiness (Republic).  
  
==Altruism in politics==
+
Although [[Epicurus]] is a hedonist and conceives as the good life as the life of maximal pleasure, this is not, necessarily, incompatible with altruism. It is open for Epicurus to argue that practicing justice, and other forms of altruism, are ultimately productive of pleasure. This would be to invoke the commonplace that altruism is often advantageous, when it motivates others to respond in kind. However, it is difficult to see how this could amount to a justification of ‘real altruism’, that is, altruistic behavior undertaken from altruistic motives. Rather, it seems at most to justify acting in ways that appear to be altruistic. Indeed, Epicurus admits that one should abstain from actions that harm others, only in return for a similar undertaking from them. The motivation for adhering to the social contract is thoroughly egoistic.
With regard to their political convictions, altruists may be divided in two broad groups: Those who believe altruism is a matter of personal choice (and therefore selfishness can and should be tolerated), and those who believe that altruism is a moral ideal which should be embraced, if possible, by all human beings.
 
  
A prominent example of the former branch of altruist political thought is [[Lysander Spooner]], who, in ''Natural Law'', writes: "''Man, no doubt, owes many other moral duties to his fellow men; such as to feed the hungry, clothe the naked, shelter the homeless, care for the sick, protect the defenceless, assist the weak, and enlighten the ignorant. But these are simply moral duties, of which each man must be his own judge, in each particular case, as to whether, and how, and how far, he can, or will, perform them.''" Things such as a law that motorists pull over to let emergency vehicles pass may also be justified by appealing to the altruism ethic. Finally, radical altruists of this branch may take things further and advocate some form of [[collectivism]] or [[communalism]].
+
In the modern period, [[Thomas Hobbes]] is generally agreed to have endorsed psychological egoism, and therefore, to have denied the reality of altruism. The strategy of reinterpreting apparently altruistic motives so that they reappear as egoistic (e.g. understanding the soldier’s act of self sacrifice as motivated by a desire for reward in the after life), discussed in the last section, derives from Hobbes. Hobbes’s psychological egoism came under heavy attack by the [[Earl of Shaftsbury]], [[Francis Hutcheson]], and [[David Hume]]. They argue that human beings are capable of altruism, since they naturally have desires for their own good and for that of others (“private good” and “public good”). In the vocabulary of the day, there are principles of benevolence and self-love, where, roughly speaking, benevolence is a desire for the happiness of others, whereas self-love is a desire for one’s own happiness. In this way, Hobbes’ critics tried to show that benevolence, pity and sympathy are as natural as self-love
  
On a somewhat related note, altruism is often held &mdash; even by non-altruists &mdash; to be the kind of ethic that should guide the actions of politicians and other people in positions of power. Such people are usually expected to set their own interests aside and serve the populace. When they do not, they may be criticized as defaulting on what is believed to be an ethical obligation to place the interests of others above their own.
+
One of the most sophisticated modern defences of altruism is found in the writings of [[Joseph Butler]]. Butler analyses man’s nature into a hierarchy of motivations, and tries to show that self-love cannot be the only element in our motivational system. He argues, against Hobbes, that even though the satisfaction of desires produces pleasure, this does not entail that pleasure is the object of those desires. Taking pleasure in one’s actions is compatible with altruistic motives. That someone experiences pleasure upon helping another person in need does not show that he or she acted in order to attain this pleasure.
  
==Altruism in psychology and sociology==
+
==Biological altruism==
If one performs an act beneficial to others with a view to gaining some personal benefit, then it is not an altruistically motivated act. There are several different perspectives on how "benefit" (or "interest") should be defined. A material gain (for example, money, a physical reward, etc.) is clearly a form of benefit, while others identify and include both material and immaterial gains (affection, respect, happiness, satisfaction etc.) as being philosophically identical benefits.
 
  
According to ''[[psychological egoism]]'', while people can exhibit altruistic ''behavior'', they cannot have altruistic ''motivations''. Psychological egoists would say that while they might very well spend their lives benefitting others with no material benefit (or a material net loss) to themselves, their most basic motive for doing so is always to further their own interests. For example, it would be alleged that the foundational motive behind a person acting this way is to advance their own psychological well-being ("good feelings"). Critics of this theory often reject it on the grounds that it is [[falsifiability|non-falsifiable]]; in other words, it is impossible to prove or disprove because immaterial gains such as a "good feelings" cannot be measured or proven to exist in all people performing altruistic acts. Psychological egoism has also been accused of using [[circular logic]]: "If a person willingly performs an act, that means he derives personal enjoyment from it; therefore, people only perform acts that give them personal enjoyment". This particular statement is circular because its conclusion is identical to its hypothesis (it assumes that people only perform acts that give them personal enjoyment, and concludes that people only perform acts that give them personal enjoyment).
+
“Biological altruism” refers to the tendency of some organisms to behave in ways that benefit other creatures at a cost to themselves. Biological altruism is widespread in the natural world. Examples include sterile worker bees devoting their whole lives to caring for their queen, and the “helpers” of certain bird species, who guard the nest and care for the young of other breeding pairs. Altruism is of significance for [[socio-biology]], because its existence is apparently in conflict with basic Darwinian principles, which seem to suggest that organisms would not behave in ways that decreased their own reproductive fitness.  
  
In common parlance, altruism usually means helping another person without expecting material reward from that or other persons, although it may well entail the "internal" benefit of a "good feeling," sense of satisfaction, self-esteem, fulfillment of duty (whether imposed by a religion or ideology or simply one's conscience), or the like. In this way one need not speculate on the motives of the altruist in question.
+
Evolutionary biologists are interested in altruism because it seems to contradict certain basic tenets of Darwin’s theory of [[evolution]], or more particularly, his theory of the mechanism of evolution, viz. [[natural selection]]. The operation of natural selection may be explained as follows. Imagine that in a population, say a population of horses, an individual is born who possesses a new gene, via mutation or recombination, which results in a new characteristic.  Assume too that this characteristic serves to enhance its fitness; i.e., with the characteristic the individual is more likely to survive and reproduce. For example, we might imagine that this gene enables the horse to run faster than its peers so it can better outrun predators; it is therefore more likely to survive longer and to reproduce more. The next generation inheriting the gene will have a competitive advantage, and hence will also be more likely to survive and reproduce. In this way, the “slower” gene will be eliminated from the population of horses, and replaced by the “speedier” gene.
  
Humans are not exclusively altruistic towards family members, previous co-operators or potential future allies, but can be altruistic towards people they do not know and will never meet. For example, some humans donate to international [[Charitable organization|charities]] and volunteer their time to help [[society]]'s less fortunate. It can however be argued that an individual would contribute to a charity to gain respect or stature within his/her own community.
+
It now is possible to explain how why biological altruism seems in tension with the operations of natural selection. In evolutionary biology, benefit is measured in terms of reproductive fitness, units of heredity, or expected number of offspring. When an organism behaves altruistically, it reduces its own reproductive fitness, and increases the reproductive fitness of other organisms. For example, when the ‘helper birds’ guard the nest of another breeding pair, they make it more likely that they will be killed by predators, and more likely that the offspring of other breeding pairs will survive. Consequently, they make it less likely that they will pass on their own altruistic genes in comparison with other birds that do not display similar altruism. So it seems that natural selection ought to favour selfish birds, and to eliminate altruists from the genetic pool. Given the mechanism of natural selection, we should not expect altruism to occur in nature.
  
It strains plausibility to claim that these altruistic deeds are done in the hope of a return favor. The game theory analysis of this 'just in case' strategy, where the principle would be 'always help everyone in case you need to pull in a favor in return', is a decidedly ''non-optimal'' strategy, where the net expenditure of effort (tit) is far greater than the net profit when it occasionally pays off (tat).  
+
There are various attempts to reconcile the existence of biological altruism with the mechanics of natural selection. Firstly, as [[Darwin]] himself pointed out, if natural selection operates not only at the individual level but also at the level of groups, then altruistic behaviour may be expected. Altruistic behaviour could make a group more likely to survive even if the individual’s reproductive fitness is diminished. However, one notable difficulty with Darwin’s group selection explanation of altruism is the problem of  ‘subversion from within’. Imagine that in a group of birds with altruistic genes, one mutant bird with selfish genes is born. This selfish bird will be a ‘free rider’ because it will have an advantage in reproductive fitness in virtue of the altruism of the other birds. Consequently, its selfish gene is more likely to be reproduced, and, over time, we should expect selfish mutant genes to dominate over the altruistic gene.  
  
According to some, it is difficult to believe that these behaviors are solely explained as indirect selfish [[rationality]], be it conscious or sub-conscious. Mathematical formulations of [[kin selection]], along the lines of the [[prisoner's dilemma]], are helpful as far as they go; but what a [[game theory|game-theoretic]] explanation glosses over is the fact that altruistic behavior can be attributed to that apparently mysterious phenomenon, the [[conscience]]. One recent suggestion, proposed by the philosopher [[Daniel Dennett]], was initially developed when considering the problem of so-called 'free riders' in the [[tragedy of the commons]], a larger-scale version of the [[prisoner's dilemma]].
+
Two other attempts to reconcile the existence of altruism with natural selection are [[kin selection]]” theories, and theories of [[reciprocal altruism]]”. According to the “kin selection” theory, altruists will not necessarily be at a reproductive disadvantage if they are careful about how they direct their altruism. If they behave altruistically only toward their relatives (kin), they will enhance the likelihood that their genes continue, because their relatives have the same genes as they do. This explains how the altruistic gene can perpetuate itself. Altruistic genes reduce the reproductive fitness of individuals, but increase the fitness of their kin, who carry the same (altruistic) genes as they do.
  
In [[game theory]] terms, a free rider is an [[agent (grammar)|agent]] who draws benefits from a co-operative society without contributing. In a one-to-one situation, free riding can easily be discouraged by a tit-for-tat strategy. But in a larger-scale society, where contributions and benefits are pooled and shared, they can be incredibly difficult to shake off.  
+
“Kin selection” theories do not explain all instances of altruistic behaviour found in nature because some creatures behave altruistically toward non-relatives. It is here that the theory of “reciprocal altruism” provides a more general explanation for biological altruism. The basic idea underlying “reciprocal altruism” is a simple one: “if you scratch my back, I'll scratch yours”. Altruistic genes may not be eliminated by natural selection if altruistic behaviour makes it more likely that other creatures will respond in kind. The loss in reproductive fitness due to altruistic behaviour is compensated by the increase in reciprocal behaviour of those creatures that are inclined to ‘return the favour’.
  
Imagine an elementary society of co-operative organisms. Co-operative agents interact with each other, each contributing resources and each drawing on the common good. Now imagine a [[rogue]] [[free rider]], an agent who draws a favor ("you scratch my back") and later refuses to return it. The problem is that free riding is always going to be beneficial to individuals at cost to society. How can well-behaved co-operative agents avoid being cheated? Over many generations, one obvious solution is for co-operators to evolve the ability to spot potential free riders in advance and refuse to enter into [[Reciprocity (social psychology)|reciprocal]] arrangements with them. Then, the canonical free rider response is to evolve a more convincing [[disguise]], fooling co-operators into co-operating after all. This can lead to an evolutionary [[arms race]]s, with ever-more-sophisticated disguises and ever-more-sophisticated detectors.
+
What is the relation between psychological and biological altruism? Biological altruism emphasizes actual benefit, and not the conscious motives for which altruistic behavior is undertaken. This distinguishes it from psychological altruism, since benefit-bringing behavior performed for non-altruistic motives does not entail for psychological altruism. Conversely, an action done with a conscious altruistic motive may not actually enhance or diminish reproductive potential at all. Therefore, psychological altruism does not entail biological altruism. Psychological and biological altruism are logically independent concepts.
  
In this evolutionary arms race, how best might one convince comrades that one ''really is'' a genuine co-operator, not a free rider in disguise?  One answer is by ''actually making oneself'' a  genuine co-operator, by erecting [[psychological barriers]] to breaking promises, and by advertising this fact to everyone else. In other words, a good solution is for organisms to evolve things that everyone knows will force them to be co-operators - and to make it obvious that they've evolved these things. So evolution will produce organisms who are sincerely moral and who wear their hearts on their sleeves; in short, evolution will give rise to the phenomenon of conscience.
+
==References and further reading==
  
This theory, combined with ideas of [[kin selection]] and the one-to-one sharing of benefits, may explain how a blind and fundamentally selfish process can produce a genuinely non-cynical form of altruism that gives rise to the human conscience.
+
===Psychological altruism===
  
Critics of such technical game theory analysis point out that it appears to forget that human beings are rational and emotional. To presume an analysis of human behaviour without including human rationale or emotion is necessarily unrealistically narrow, and treats human beings as if they are mere machines, sometimes called [[Homo economics]]. Another objection is that often people donate anonymously, so that it is impossible to determine if they really did the altruistic act.
+
*Butler, Jospeh. (1900). ''Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel. In The Works of Bishop Butler''. J. H. Bernard (ed.). London: Macmillan. Available online at: http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/3150 [See Sermons I and XI for responses to Hobbes’ version of exclusive egoism]
 +
*Hobbes, Thomas. (1651). ''Leviathan''. Michael Oakeshott (ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. Available online at: http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/3207 [A classical account of psychological egoism and ethical egoism]
 +
*Hume, David. (1975). ''An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals''. In Enquiries.  L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See Appendix II for an elegant criticism of psychological egoism]
 +
*Kavka, Gregory. (1986). ''Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory''. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [A partial defense of Hobbesian ethical and political theory. See pp. 64-80 for an explication of predominant egoism]  
 +
*Long, A.A., and D.N. Sedley, ‘’The Hellenistic Philosophers’’, vol 1 and 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987)
 +
*Nagel, Thomas. (1970). ''The Possibility of Altruism''. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
 +
*Plato, ‘’Plato's Complete Works’’, John M. Cooper, ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1997).  
 +
*Slote, Michael Anthony. (1964). “An Empirical Basis for Psychological Egoism”. In ''Journal of Philosophy'' 61: 530-537.
  
Beginning with an understanding that rational human beings benefit from living in a benign universe, logically it follows that particular human beings may gain substantial emotional satisfaction from acts which they perceive to make the world a better place.
+
===Biological altruism===
 +
*Darwin, C., 1859, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, London: John Murray.
 +
*Darwin, C., 1871, The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex, New York: Appleton
 +
*Dawkins, R., 1976, The Selfish Gene, Oxford: Oxford University Press
 +
*Dawkins, R., 1979, ‘Twelve Misunderstandings of Kin Selection’, Zeitschrift fur Tierpsychologie, 51: 184-200
 +
*Hamilton, W. D., 1970, ‘Selfish and Spiteful Behaviour in an Evolutionary Model’, Nature, 228: 1218-1220
 +
*Hamilton, W. D., 1972, ‘Altruism and Related Phenomena, mainly in the Social Insects’, Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 3: 193-232.
 +
*Maynard Smith, J., 1964, ‘Group Selection and Kin Selection’, Nature, 201: 1145-1147
 +
*Maynard Smith, J., 1998, ‘The Origin of Altruism’, Nature, 393: 639-640
 +
*Singer, Peter. (1982). ''The Expanding Circle''. New York: New American Library. [A discussion of the relevance of  sociobiology to egoism]
 +
*Sober, E. and Wilson D.S., 1998, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press
 +
*Sober, E., 1988, ‘What is Evolutionary Altruism?’, in New Essays on Philosophy and Biology (Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supp. Vol. 14), B. Linsky and M. Mathen (eds.), Calgary: University of Calgary Press
 +
===Fiction and Popular Literature===
  
==Altruism and religion==
+
A selection of literature in popular culture dealing with egoism and altruism:
{{sect-stub}}
 
Most, if not all, of the world's [[religion]]s promote altruism as a very important moral value. [[Christianity]] and [[Buddhism]] place particular emphasis on altruistic morality, as noted above, but [[Judaism]], [[Islam]], [[Hinduism]] and many other religions also promote altruistic behavior.
 
Altruism was central to the teachings of [[Jesus]] found in the [[Gospel]]. From biblical to medieval [[Christian traditions]], tensions between self-affirmation and other-regard were sometimes discussed under the heading of "disinterested love," as in the Pauline phrase "love seeks not its own interests." In his book on Indoctrination and Self-deception... Roderick Hindery tries to shed light on these tensions by contrasting them with impostors of authentic self-affirmation and altruism, by analysis of other-regard within creative  individuation of the self, and by contrasting love for the few with love for the many. If love, which confirms others in their freedom, shuns propagandas and masks, assurance of its presence is ultimately confirmed not by mere declarations from others, but by each person's experience and practice from within. As in practical arts, the presence and meaning of love become validated and grasped not by words and reflections alone, but in the doing.
 
  
Though it might seem obvious that altruism is central to the teachings of Jesus, one important and influential strand of Christianity would qualify this. St Thomas Aquinas in the Summa Theologia, I:II Quaestion 26, Article 4 states that we should love ourselves more than our neighbour. His interpretation of the Pauline phrase is that we should seek the common good more than the private good but this is because the common good is a more desirable good for the individual. 'You should love your neighbour as yourself' from Leviticus 19 and Matthew 22 is interpreted by St Thomas as meaning that love for ourself is the exemplar of love for others. He does think though, that we should love God more than ourselves and our neighbour, taken as an entirety, more than our bodily life, since the ultimate purpose of love of our neighbour is to share in eternal beatitude, a more desirable thing than bodily well being. Comte was probably opposing this Thomistic doctrine, now part of mainstream Catholicism, in coining the word Altruism, as stated above.
+
*Clavell, James. (1962). ''King Rat''. London: Martin Joseph; Delta, 1999. ISBN 0385333765
<!-- This section should continue by quoting altruism-related verses from the holy books of the aforementioned religions —>
+
*Lavey, Anton Szandor, Gilmore, Peter H. (1969). ''The Satanic Bible''. Avon; Reissue edition, 1969. ISBN 0380015390 
 
+
*Rand, Ayn. (1957). ''Atlas Shrugged''. New York: Signet; 35th Anniv edition, 1996. ISBN 0451191145  
==Altruism and love (the problem of love)==
+
*Rand, Ayn. (1964). ''The Virtue of Selfishness''. New York: Signet; Reissue edition, 1964. ISBN 0451163931
In philosophy, the '''problem of love''' questions whether the desire to do good for another is based solely on the outward ability to [[love]] another person because the lover sees something (or someone) worth loving, or if a little [[self-interest]] is always present in the desire to do good for another.
 
 
 
The problem arises from an analysis of the [[free will|human will]] and is often debated among [[Thomistic philosophy|Thomistic philosophers]].  The "problem" centers on [[Thomas Aquinas]]'s understanding that human expressions of love are always based partly on love of self and similitude of being: “Even when a man loves in another what he loves not in himself, there is a certain likeness of proportion: because as the latter is to that which is loved in him, so is the former to that which he loves in himself.” See Thomas Aquinas, [[Summa Theologica]] (New York: Benziger Bros., 1948), I-II, Q. 27, Art. 3, rep. obj. 2.)
 
 
 
The French philosopher Pierre Rousselot (1878-1915) locates the philosophical problem in terms of a pure "ecstatic" or totally selfless love versus an egoistic, more self-interested love, beginning his examination from Aristotle's text ([[Nicomachean Ethics]], Book 9): Amicabilia quae sunt ad alterum vererunt amicabilibus quae sunt ad se ipsum [The friendly feelings that we bear for another have arisen from the friendly feelings that we bear for ourselves]. See Pierre Rousselot, The Problem of Love in the Middle Ages: A Historical Contribution. Trans. Alan Vincelette (Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press, 2001).
 
 
 
==Notes==
 
<references/>
 
 
 
==References==
 
<div class="references-small" style="-moz-column-count: 2; column-count: 2;">
 
*Batson, C.D. (1991).  ''The altruism question''. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.  
 
*Fehr, E. & Fischbacher, U. ([[23 October]] [[2003]]). The nature of human altruism. In ''Nature, 425'', 785 &ndash; 791.
 
*[[August Comte]], ''Catechisme positiviste'' (1852) or ''Catechism of Positivism'', tr. R. Congreve, (London: Kegan Paul, 1891)
 
* [[Thomas Jay Oord]], Science of Love (Philadelphia: Templeton Foundation Press, 2004).
 
*[[Nietzsche, Friedrich]], ''[[Beyond Good and Evil]]''
 
*[[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]], ''The Philosophy of Poverty'' (1847)
 
*[[Lysander Spooner]], ''Natural Law''
 
*[[Matt Ridley]], ''[[The Origins of Virtue]]''
 
*Oliner, Samuel P. and Pearl M.  Towards a Caring Society: Ideas into Action.  West Port, CT: Praeger, 1995.
 
* ''[[The Evolution of Cooperation]]'', [[Robert Axelrod]], Basic Books,  ISBN 0-465-02121-2
 
*''[[The Selfish Gene]]'', [[Richard Dawkins]] (1990), second edition — includes two chapters about the evolution of cooperation, ISBN 0-19-286092-5
 
*[[Robert Wright (journalist)|Robert Wright]], ''The moral animal'', Vintage, 1995, ISBN 0-679-76399-6.
 
*Madsen, E.A., Tunney, R., Fieldman, G., [[Henry Plotkin|Plotkin, H.C.]], [[Robin Dunbar|Dunbar, R.I.M.]], Richardson, J.M., & McFarland, D. (2006) Kinship and altruism: A cross-cultural experimental study. ''British Journal of Psychology'' [http://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/bpsoc/bjp/pre-prints/218320]
 
*Wedekind, C. and Milinski, M. Human Cooperation in the simultaneous and the alternating Prisoner's Dilemma: Pavlov versus Generous Tit-for-tat. ''Evolution'', Vol. 93, pp. 2686-2689, April 1996.
 
</div>
 
 
 
==See also==
 
{|
 
|
 
* [[Altruism (ethics)]]
 
* [[Altruism in animals]]
 
* [[Altruria]]
 
* [[Charity (practice)]]
 
* [[Charitable organization]]
 
* [[Egoism]]
 
* [[Empathy]]
 
* [[Gene-centered view of evolution]]
 
|
 
* [[Justice (economics)]]
 
* [[Misanthropy]]
 
* [[mutual aid]]
 
* [[Philanthropy]]
 
* [[Psychology]]
 
* [[Random acts of kindness]]
 
* [[Reciprocal altruism]]
 
* [[Selfishness]]
 
* [[Solidarity (sociology)]]
 
* [[Tit for tat]]
 
|}
 
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
*Philosophy and Religion
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/egoism// Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on Egoism]
**[http://yaleeconomicreview.com/issues/spring2006/altruism.php "Altruism and Utility"] in ''[[Yale Economic Review]]''
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/e/egoism.htm The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on Egoism]
**[http://them.polylog.org/3/fcs-en.htm Selflessness: Toward a Buddhist Vision of Social Justice] by [[Sungtaek Cho]]
 
**[http://www.empathy.se/Empathyeng/index.htm Organizes knowledge about empathy/altruism across disciplines]
 
 
 
*The Sciences
 
**[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/altruism-biological/ Biological Altruism] at the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]
 
**[http://www.humboldt.edu/~altruism/home.html The Altruistic Personality and Prosocial Behavior Institute] at [[Humboldt State University]]
 
**[http://www.nature.com/neuro/journal/vaop/ncurrent/abs/nn1833.html "Altruism is associated with an increased neural response to agency"] in ''[[Nature]]''
 
** [http://peacecenter.berkeley.edu/greatergood/ Greater Good magazine examines the roots of Altruism] at the [[University of California, Berkeley]]
 
 
 
*In Society 
 
**[http://www.altruists.org Altruists International] A group to re-establish altruism as a social norm.
 
 
 
{{Philosophy navigation}}
 
{{Charity}}
 
[[Category:Evolutionary biology]]
 
[[Category:philanthropy]]
 
[[Category:Social philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Social psychology]]
 
[[Category:Sociology]]
 
[[Category:Virtues]]
 
[[Category:Motivation]]
 
  
{{Credit|136317588}}
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.epistemelinks.com/  Philosophy Sources on Internet EpistemeLinks]
 +
*[http://www.earlham.edu/~peters/gpi/index.htm Guide to Philosophy on the Internet]
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]

Revision as of 09:50, 20 August 2007

“Psychological altruism” refers to behavior that both benefits others and is undertaken for their benefit. In this sense, altruism is opposed to egoism. Philosophical concerns relating to altruism include whether altruism is in fact possible, that is, whether we ever in fact do act for reasons other than our own best interests.

“Biological altruism” refers to the tendency of some organisms to behave in ways that benefit other creatures at a cost to themselves. Biological altruism is widespread in the natural world. Examples include sterile worker bees devoting their whole lives to caring for their queen, and the “helpers” of certain bird species, who guard the nest and care for the young of other breeding pairs. Altruism is of significance for socio-biology, because its existence is apparently in conflict with basic principles of Darwin’s theory of evolution, which seem to suggest that organisms would not behave in ways that decreased their own reproductive fitness.

Psychological Altruism

Psychological altruism (sometimes called ‘real’ altruism) refers to behavior that benefits others, often at a cost to the agent, which is undertaken for the motive of benefiting others. Behavior benefiting other people is not necessarily altruistic. For example, if one helped out another person with the motive of enhancing one’s own reputation, this behavior would not count as altruistic, but as self-interested.

Psychological altruism is opposed to psychological egoism. Psychological egoism is an empirical hypothesis about human behaviour: it holds that every human has only one ultimate goal: his or her own good (where this good can variously be defined as welfare, happiness or pleasure). Thus, while it allows for action that does not accomplish its goal of maximising self-interest, as well as action that is at odds with one’s intentions (a weak will), most forms of psychological egoism rule out both altruistic behaviour and acting solely out of respect for duty.

One basic philosophical concern relating to altruism is whether it is in fact possible, that is, whether we ever in fact do act for reasons other than our own best interests. Since egoism is opposed to altruism, arguments for psychological egoism are arguments against the possibility of altruism. Psychological egoism is motivated in various ways: Firstly, it is sometimes thought to follow from widespread and frequent observations of self-interested behaviour. Secondly, we often motivate people to act in certain ways by appealing to their self-interest in the form of rewards and punishments, and thirdly, acts appearing altruistic can often be shown to be motivated by self-interest.

In contrast with egoism, psychological altruism says that human beings do sometimes act for the interests of others out of a genuine concern for their well being. Consider an example in which a soldier throws himself on a grenade in order to prevent other people from being killed. His motivation for this act of self-sacrifice might be plausibly a desire to save the other peoples’ lives. This seems to qualify his act as altruistic because he has benefited other people, at great cost to himself, from the motivation of saving their lives.

When faced with examples of altruistic behaviour such as these, egoists may try to defend their position by arguing that the soldier’s action, although it appears to be altruistic, ought to be explained by some more fundamental self-interested motive. Perhaps the soldier believes in an afterlife in which he will be rewarded ten-fold for his apparently selfless act on earth, or perhaps, if he had not hurled himself on the grenade, he would be overcome by guilt and a concomitant sense of self-loathing. In both cases then, he is, at least from his perspective, acting in his self-interest by acting in this apparently selfless manner.

There are two problems with this response. The first is that, while it might explain many instances of apparent self-sacrifice as motivated by egoistic concerns, it does not necessarily cover all cases. The psychological egoist must argue that all instances of ostensible altruistic behaviour are in fact motivated by self-interested desires. If, for instance, our soldier disagrees with this, and claims that his action was truly altruistic in motivation, the egoist must respond that he is lying or is deceiving himself. At this point, however, egoism turns out to be trivially true, which means that it is un-falsifiable, since there is no empirical instance that could in principle disprove the hypothesis; it provides no useful information and therefore fails as an empirical theory.

Psychological altruism in its historical context

All ancient ethical theories are forms of eudaimonism, conceiving of human persons as fundamentally directed towards their individual eudaimonia, or (in its common English translation) happiness. It might seem to follow from this that ancient ethics cannot accommodate altruism, because it conceives of each person as ultimately focused on his or her individual well being.

This appearance may be deceiving, however, because all the main writers—such as Plato, Aristotle, and the Stoics—emphasize the importance of civic virtues, such as justice, as essential components of individual eudaimonia. If one conceives of the virtue of justice as involving a disposition to respect the interests of one’s fellow citizens because of one’s regard for the importance of these interests, it is easy to see that someone with the virtue of justice will behave altruistically. Given that the main ancient writers conceive of justice as an indispensable component of the good life, it follows that they also regard altruism as a component in the happy life. On Plato’s version of this idea, the altruistic person, in the sense of the just person, is someone who acquires and preserves a state of psychological harmony, which is necessary (and perhaps sufficient) for the attainment of happiness (Republic).

Although Epicurus is a hedonist and conceives as the good life as the life of maximal pleasure, this is not, necessarily, incompatible with altruism. It is open for Epicurus to argue that practicing justice, and other forms of altruism, are ultimately productive of pleasure. This would be to invoke the commonplace that altruism is often advantageous, when it motivates others to respond in kind. However, it is difficult to see how this could amount to a justification of ‘real altruism’, that is, altruistic behavior undertaken from altruistic motives. Rather, it seems at most to justify acting in ways that appear to be altruistic. Indeed, Epicurus admits that one should abstain from actions that harm others, only in return for a similar undertaking from them. The motivation for adhering to the social contract is thoroughly egoistic.

In the modern period, Thomas Hobbes is generally agreed to have endorsed psychological egoism, and therefore, to have denied the reality of altruism. The strategy of reinterpreting apparently altruistic motives so that they reappear as egoistic (e.g. understanding the soldier’s act of self sacrifice as motivated by a desire for reward in the after life), discussed in the last section, derives from Hobbes. Hobbes’s psychological egoism came under heavy attack by the Earl of Shaftsbury, Francis Hutcheson, and David Hume. They argue that human beings are capable of altruism, since they naturally have desires for their own good and for that of others (“private good” and “public good”). In the vocabulary of the day, there are principles of benevolence and self-love, where, roughly speaking, benevolence is a desire for the happiness of others, whereas self-love is a desire for one’s own happiness. In this way, Hobbes’ critics tried to show that benevolence, pity and sympathy are as natural as self-love

One of the most sophisticated modern defences of altruism is found in the writings of Joseph Butler. Butler analyses man’s nature into a hierarchy of motivations, and tries to show that self-love cannot be the only element in our motivational system. He argues, against Hobbes, that even though the satisfaction of desires produces pleasure, this does not entail that pleasure is the object of those desires. Taking pleasure in one’s actions is compatible with altruistic motives. That someone experiences pleasure upon helping another person in need does not show that he or she acted in order to attain this pleasure.

Biological altruism

“Biological altruism” refers to the tendency of some organisms to behave in ways that benefit other creatures at a cost to themselves. Biological altruism is widespread in the natural world. Examples include sterile worker bees devoting their whole lives to caring for their queen, and the “helpers” of certain bird species, who guard the nest and care for the young of other breeding pairs. Altruism is of significance for socio-biology, because its existence is apparently in conflict with basic Darwinian principles, which seem to suggest that organisms would not behave in ways that decreased their own reproductive fitness.

Evolutionary biologists are interested in altruism because it seems to contradict certain basic tenets of Darwin’s theory of evolution, or more particularly, his theory of the mechanism of evolution, viz. natural selection. The operation of natural selection may be explained as follows. Imagine that in a population, say a population of horses, an individual is born who possesses a new gene, via mutation or recombination, which results in a new characteristic. Assume too that this characteristic serves to enhance its fitness; i.e., with the characteristic the individual is more likely to survive and reproduce. For example, we might imagine that this gene enables the horse to run faster than its peers so it can better outrun predators; it is therefore more likely to survive longer and to reproduce more. The next generation inheriting the gene will have a competitive advantage, and hence will also be more likely to survive and reproduce. In this way, the “slower” gene will be eliminated from the population of horses, and replaced by the “speedier” gene.

It now is possible to explain how why biological altruism seems in tension with the operations of natural selection. In evolutionary biology, benefit is measured in terms of reproductive fitness, units of heredity, or expected number of offspring. When an organism behaves altruistically, it reduces its own reproductive fitness, and increases the reproductive fitness of other organisms. For example, when the ‘helper birds’ guard the nest of another breeding pair, they make it more likely that they will be killed by predators, and more likely that the offspring of other breeding pairs will survive. Consequently, they make it less likely that they will pass on their own altruistic genes in comparison with other birds that do not display similar altruism. So it seems that natural selection ought to favour selfish birds, and to eliminate altruists from the genetic pool. Given the mechanism of natural selection, we should not expect altruism to occur in nature.

There are various attempts to reconcile the existence of biological altruism with the mechanics of natural selection. Firstly, as Darwin himself pointed out, if natural selection operates not only at the individual level but also at the level of groups, then altruistic behaviour may be expected. Altruistic behaviour could make a group more likely to survive even if the individual’s reproductive fitness is diminished. However, one notable difficulty with Darwin’s group selection explanation of altruism is the problem of ‘subversion from within’. Imagine that in a group of birds with altruistic genes, one mutant bird with selfish genes is born. This selfish bird will be a ‘free rider’ because it will have an advantage in reproductive fitness in virtue of the altruism of the other birds. Consequently, its selfish gene is more likely to be reproduced, and, over time, we should expect selfish mutant genes to dominate over the altruistic gene.

Two other attempts to reconcile the existence of altruism with natural selection are “kin selection” theories, and theories of “reciprocal altruism”. According to the “kin selection” theory, altruists will not necessarily be at a reproductive disadvantage if they are careful about how they direct their altruism. If they behave altruistically only toward their relatives (kin), they will enhance the likelihood that their genes continue, because their relatives have the same genes as they do. This explains how the altruistic gene can perpetuate itself. Altruistic genes reduce the reproductive fitness of individuals, but increase the fitness of their kin, who carry the same (altruistic) genes as they do.

“Kin selection” theories do not explain all instances of altruistic behaviour found in nature because some creatures behave altruistically toward non-relatives. It is here that the theory of “reciprocal altruism” provides a more general explanation for biological altruism. The basic idea underlying “reciprocal altruism” is a simple one: “if you scratch my back, I'll scratch yours”. Altruistic genes may not be eliminated by natural selection if altruistic behaviour makes it more likely that other creatures will respond in kind. The loss in reproductive fitness due to altruistic behaviour is compensated by the increase in reciprocal behaviour of those creatures that are inclined to ‘return the favour’.

What is the relation between psychological and biological altruism? Biological altruism emphasizes actual benefit, and not the conscious motives for which altruistic behavior is undertaken. This distinguishes it from psychological altruism, since benefit-bringing behavior performed for non-altruistic motives does not entail for psychological altruism. Conversely, an action done with a conscious altruistic motive may not actually enhance or diminish reproductive potential at all. Therefore, psychological altruism does not entail biological altruism. Psychological and biological altruism are logically independent concepts.

References and further reading

Psychological altruism

  • Butler, Jospeh. (1900). Fifteen Sermons Preached at the Rolls Chapel. In The Works of Bishop Butler. J. H. Bernard (ed.). London: Macmillan. Available online at: http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/3150 [See Sermons I and XI for responses to Hobbes’ version of exclusive egoism]
  • Hobbes, Thomas. (1651). Leviathan. Michael Oakeshott (ed.). Oxford: Blackwell. Available online at: http://www.gutenberg.org/etext/3207 [A classical account of psychological egoism and ethical egoism]
  • Hume, David. (1975). An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. In Enquiries. L. A. Selby-Bigge and P. H. Nidditch (eds.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See Appendix II for an elegant criticism of psychological egoism]
  • Kavka, Gregory. (1986). Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press. [A partial defense of Hobbesian ethical and political theory. See pp. 64-80 for an explication of predominant egoism]
  • Long, A.A., and D.N. Sedley, ‘’The Hellenistic Philosophers’’, vol 1 and 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987)
  • Nagel, Thomas. (1970). The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
  • Plato, ‘’Plato's Complete Works’’, John M. Cooper, ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co., 1997).
  • Slote, Michael Anthony. (1964). “An Empirical Basis for Psychological Egoism”. In Journal of Philosophy 61: 530-537.

Biological altruism

  • Darwin, C., 1859, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection, London: John Murray.
  • Darwin, C., 1871, The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex, New York: Appleton
  • Dawkins, R., 1976, The Selfish Gene, Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • Dawkins, R., 1979, ‘Twelve Misunderstandings of Kin Selection’, Zeitschrift fur Tierpsychologie, 51: 184-200
  • Hamilton, W. D., 1970, ‘Selfish and Spiteful Behaviour in an Evolutionary Model’, Nature, 228: 1218-1220
  • Hamilton, W. D., 1972, ‘Altruism and Related Phenomena, mainly in the Social Insects’, Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 3: 193-232.
  • Maynard Smith, J., 1964, ‘Group Selection and Kin Selection’, Nature, 201: 1145-1147
  • Maynard Smith, J., 1998, ‘The Origin of Altruism’, Nature, 393: 639-640
  • Singer, Peter. (1982). The Expanding Circle. New York: New American Library. [A discussion of the relevance of sociobiology to egoism]
  • Sober, E. and Wilson D.S., 1998, Unto Others: The Evolution and Psychology of Unselfish Behavior, Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press
  • Sober, E., 1988, ‘What is Evolutionary Altruism?’, in New Essays on Philosophy and Biology (Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supp. Vol. 14), B. Linsky and M. Mathen (eds.), Calgary: University of Calgary Press

Fiction and Popular Literature

A selection of literature in popular culture dealing with egoism and altruism:

  • Clavell, James. (1962). King Rat. London: Martin Joseph; Delta, 1999. ISBN 0385333765
  • Lavey, Anton Szandor, Gilmore, Peter H. (1969). The Satanic Bible. Avon; Reissue edition, 1969. ISBN 0380015390
  • Rand, Ayn. (1957). Atlas Shrugged. New York: Signet; 35th Anniv edition, 1996. ISBN 0451191145
  • Rand, Ayn. (1964). The Virtue of Selfishness. New York: Signet; Reissue edition, 1964. ISBN 0451163931

External links

General Philosophy Sources