Difference between revisions of "Philo Judaeus" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m ({{Contracted}})
Line 2: Line 2:
 
{{wikify-date|April 2006}}  
 
{{wikify-date|April 2006}}  
 
{{otheruses}}
 
{{otheruses}}
'''Philo''' ([[20 BC|20 B.C.E.]] - [[40]] CE), known also as Philo of Alexandria and as Philo Judeaus, was a [[Hellenized]] [[Jewish]] [[philosopher]] born in [[Alexandria, Egypt]]. The few biographical details concerning him are found in his own works, especially in ''Legatio ad Caium,'' ("embassy to Caius") and in [[Josephus]] (''Antiquities" xviii. 8, § 1; comp. ib. xix. 5, § 1; xx. 5, § 2).
+
'''Philo''' (20 b.c.e. – 50 C.E.), known also as Philo of Alexandria and as Philo Judeus, was a [[Hellenized]] [[Jewish]] [[philosopher]] who synthesized Stoic, Platonic and Jewish ideas and laid a philosophical and theological foundation for the development of Christianity in the West and the East and, indirectly, for rational theologians in the Jewish and Islamic worlds. He developed concepts later used in the interpretations of Clement of Alexandria, Athenagoras, Theophilus, Justin Martyr, Tertullian and Origen. It is thought that he may have influenced Paul and the authors of the Gospel of John and the Epistle to the Hebrews.
 +
the highest perception of truth is possible only after a study of the encyclopedic sciences.
  
The only event that can be determined chronologically is his participation in the embassy which the Alexandrian Jews sent to the emperor [[Caligula]] at [[Rome]] for the purpose of asking protection against the attacks of the Alexandrian Greeks. This occurred in the year 40 C.E.
+
Philo was ignored by the Jewish tradition, which emphasized theology over philosophical speculations. His works were preserved by the Christian church, primarily because some early Christians perceived him as a Christian.   [[Eusebius]] speculated that the ''[[Therapeutae]]'', the Jewish group of ascetic hermits in the Egyptian desert that Philo describes in ''De vita contemplativa'' ("Contemplative Life") was in fact a Christian group.
 
 
Philo included in his philosophy both Greek wisdom and [[Judaism]], which he sought to fuse and harmonize by means of the art of allegory that he had learned as much from Jewish exegesis as from the Stoics. His work was not widely accepted. "The sophists of literalness," as he calls them (''De Somniis,'' i. 16-17), "opened their eyes superciliously" when he explained to them the marvels of his exegesis. Philo's works were enthusiastically received by the early [[Christianity|Christians]], some of whom saw in him a Christian. [[Eusebius]] speculated that the ''[[Therapeutae]]'', the Jewish group of ascetic hermits in the Egyptian desert that Philo describes in ''De vita contemplativa'' ("Contemplative Life") was in fact a Christian group.
 
 
[[Image:Philon.jpg|right|200px]]
 
[[Image:Philon.jpg|right|200px]]
  
==Biography==
+
== Life ==
We have a brief reference to Philo by the first century Jewish historian [[Josephus]].  In ''Antiquities of the Jews'', Josephus tells of Philo's selection by the Alexandrian Jewish community as their principal representative before the Roman emperor Gaius Caligula.  He says that Philo was sent to represent the Alexandrian Jews in regard to civil disorder that had arisen between the Jews and the Greeks in Alexandria (in Egypt).  Josephus tells us also that Philo was skilled in philosophy, and that he was brother to an official called Alexander the alabarch.  According to Josephus, Philo and the larger Jewish community refused to treat the emperor as a god, to erect statues in honor of the emperor, and to build altars and temples to the emperor.  Josephus says Philo believed that God actively supports this refusal.  This portrait of Philo matches the character of Philo that is expressed in his own writings, as discussed below.
+
Little information is available about the life of Philo, except for a few biographical details in his own works, especially in ''Legatio ad Caium,'' ("Embassy to Caius"), and a brief mention of him in the ''Antiquities" (xviii. 8, § 1; comp. ib. xix. 5, § 1; xx. 5, § 2) of Josephus.
 
 
Josephus' comments about Philo are so brief that we can quote them here in full:
 
:"There was now a tumult arisen at Alexandria, between the Jewish inhabitants and the Greeks; and three ambassadors were chosen out of each party that were at variance, who came to Gaius. Now one of these ambassadors from the people of Alexandria was Apion, (29) who uttered many blasphemies against the Jews; and, among other things that he said, he charged them with neglecting the honors that belonged to Caesar; for that while all who were subject to the Roman empire built altars and temples to Gaius, and in other regards universally received him as they received the gods, these Jews alone thought it a dishonorable thing for them to erect statues in honor of him, as well as to swear by his name. Many of these severe things were said by Apion, by which he hoped to provoke Gaius to anger at the Jews, as he was likely to be. But Philo, the principal of the Jewish embassage, a man eminent on all accounts, brother to Alexander the alabarch, (30) and one not unskillful in philosophy, was ready to betake himself to make his defense against those accusations; but Gaius prohibited him, and bid him begone; he was also in such a rage, that it openly appeared he was about to do them some very great mischief. So Philo being thus affronted, went out, and said to those Jews who were about him, that they should be of good courage, since Gaius's words indeed showed anger at them, but in reality had already set God against himself." [''Antiquities of the Jews'', xviii. 8, § 1, Whiston's translation (online)]
 
 
 
Our remaining information about Philo is based upon his own writings.  Philo himself claims in his ''Embassy to Gaius'' to have been part of an embassy sent by the Alexandrian Jews to the Roman Emperor Gaius.  Philo says he was carrying a petition which described the sufferings of the Alexandrian Jews, and which asked the emperor to secure their rights.  Philo gives a detailed description of their sufferings, in a way that Josephus overlooks, to show that the Alexandrian Jews were simply the victims of attacks by Alexandrian Greeks.  Philo says he was regarded by his people as having unusual prudence, due to his age, education, and knowledge.  This indicates that he was already an older man at this time (40 C.E.).  Philo considers Gaius' plan to erect a statue of himself in the temple of Jerusalem to be a provocation, saying, "Are you making war upon us, because you anticipate that we will not endure such indignity, but that we will fight on behalf of our laws, and die in defence of our national customs? For you cannot possibly have been ignorant of what was likely to result from your attempt to introduce these innovations respecting our temple." In this entire presentation he implicitly supports the Jewish commitment to rebel against the emperor rather than allow such sacrilege to take place.  This reveals Philo's identification with the Jewish community.  [''Embassy to Gaius'', Chapter 28-31, Yonge's translation (online)].
 
 
 
In "Flaccus", Philo tells indirectly of his own life in Alexandria by describing how the situation of Jews in Alexandria Egypt changed after Caius Caligula became the emperor of Rome.  Although we have no independent confirmation for most of his account, it is an account of mostly public events, so in its main points it would have been difficult for Philo to have misrepresented the situation.  Speaking of the large Jewish population in Egypt, Philo says that Alexandria "had two classes of inhabitants, our own nation and the people of the country, and that the whole of Egypt was inhabited in the same manner, and that Jews who inhabited Alexandria and the rest of the country from the Catabathmos on the side of Libya to the boundaries of Ethiopia were not less than a million of men."  Regarding the large proportion of Jews in Alexandria, he writes, "There are five districts in the city, named after the first five letters of the written alphabet, of these two are called the quarters of the Jews, because the chief portion of the Jews lives in them."  Other sources tell us that Caius had been asking to receive the honors due to a god.  Philo says Flaccus, the Roman governor over Alexandria, permitted a Greek mob to erect statues of the Emperor Caius in Jewish synagogues of Alexandria, an unprecendented provocation.  This invasion of the synagogues was perhaps resisted by force, since Philo then says that Flaccus "was destroying the synagogues, and not leaving even their name."  In response, Philo says that Flaccus then "issued a notice in which he called us all foreigners and aliens...  allowing any one who was inclined to proceed to exterminate the Jews as prisoners of war."  Philo says that in response, the mobs "drove the Jews entirely out of four quarters, and crammed them all into a very small portion of one ...  while the populace, overrunning their desolate houses, turned to plunder, and divided the booty among themselves as if they had obtained it in war."  In addition, Philo says their enemies, "slew them and thousands of others with all kinds of agony and tortures, and newly invented cruelties, for wherever they met with or caught sight of a Jew, they stoned him, or beat him with sticks".  Philo even says, "the most merciless of all their persecutors in some instances burnt whole families, husbands with their wives, and infant children with their parents, in the middle of the city, sparing neither age nor youth, nor the innocent helplessness of infants."  Some men, he says, were dragged to death, while "those who did these things, mimicked the sufferers, like people employed in the representation of theatrical farces".  Other Jews were crucified.  Flaccus was eventually removed from office and exiled, ultimately suffering the punishment of death.  [''Flaccus'', Chapters 6 - 9 (43, 53-56, 62, 66, 68, 71-72), Yonge's translation (online)].
 
 
 
==Influence of Hellenism==
 
 
 
Philo quotes the epic poets with frequency, or alludes to passages in their works. He has a wide acquaintance with the works of the Greek philosophers. He holds that the highest perception of truth is possible only after a study of the encyclopedic sciences. The dualistic contrast between God and the world, between the finite and the infinite, appears in both Platonism and in Neo-Pythagorism. The influence of [[Stoicism]] is unmistakable in the doctrine of God as the only efficient cause, in that of divine reason immanent in the world, in that of the powers emanating from God and suffusing the world. In the doctrine of the Logos various elements of Greek philosophy are united.
 
 
 
As Heinze shows ("Die Lehre vom Logos in der Griechischen Philosophie," 1872, pp. 204ff), this doctrine touches upon the Platonic doctrine of ideas as well as the Stoic doctrine of the γενικώτατόν τι and the Neo-Pythagorean doctrine of the type that served at the creation of the world; and in the shaping of the λόγος τομεύς it touches upon the [[Heraclitus|Heraclitean]] doctrine of strife as the moving principle. Philo's doctrine of dead, inert, non-existent matter harmonizes in its essentials with the [[Plato]]nic and Stoic doctrine.
 
 
 
His account of the Creation is almost identical with that of Plato; he follows the latter's "Timaeus" closely in his exposition of the world as having no beginning and no end. Like Plato, he places the creative activity as well as the act of creation outside of time, on the Platonic ground that time begins only with the world. The influence of [[Pythagoreans|Pythagorism]] appears in number-symbolism, to which Philo frequently refers.
 
 
 
The [[Aristotle|Aristotelian]] contrast between δύναμις and ἐντελέχεια ("Metaphysics," iii. 73) is found in Philo, "De Allegoriis Legum," i 64 (on Aristotle see Freudenthal in "Monatsschrift," 1875, p.233). In his psychology he adopts either the Stoic division of the soul into eight faculties, or the Platonic trichotomy of reason, courage, and desire, or the Aristotelian triad of the vegetative, emotive, and rational souls.
 
 
 
The doctrine of the body as the source of all evil corresponds entirely with the Neo-Pythagorean doctrine: the soul he conceives as a divine emanation, similar to Plato's νοῦς (see Siegfried, ''Philo,'' pp. 139ff). His ethics and allegories are based on Stoic ethics and allegories.  
 
  
Philo made his philosophy the means of defending and justifying Jewish religious truths. These truths he regarded as fixed and determinate; and philosophy was used as an aid to truth, and as a means of arriving at it. With this end in view Philo chose from the philosophical tenets of the Greeks, refusing those that did not harmonize with the Jewish religion, as, e.g., the Aristotelian doctrine of the eternity and indestructibility of the world.
+
He was born about 25 B.C.E. in Alexandria, which at that time was home to the largest Jewish community outside of Palestine. He was part of a prominent family; his brother Alexander Lysimachus was a wealthy official of the Roman government, who donated money to plate the gates of the temple in Jerusalem with gold and silver, and made a loan to Herod Agrippa I, grandson of Herod the Great.   One of Alexander’s sons married a daughter of Herod Agrippa I, and his other son abandoned the Jewish faith and became procurator of Judea and Prefect of Egypt.  Philo mentions that he once visited Jerusalem.
  
==Knowledge of Hebrew==
+
From Philo’s works it is clear that he had a thorough knowledge of Greek and of the theories of the Stoics, Plato’s dialogues, and neo-Pythagorean writings.  He said that a study of the sciences…  It is apparent that he used a Greek translation of the Jewish scriptures rather than Hebrew manuscripts.  His “Allegorical Commentary” indicates that he was deeply involved in the Jewish community. The most documented episode of his life is his participation in a Jewish delegation which traveled to Rome in 39 C.E. to complain to Emperor Gaius Caligula about the persecution of the Jews in Alexandria by the governor, Flaccus.
 +
 
 +
Josephus gives the following account of this mission in Antiquities: "There was now a tumult arisen at Alexandria, between the Jewish inhabitants and the Greeks; and three ambassadors were chosen out of each party that were at variance, who came to Gaius. Now one of these ambassadors from the people of Alexandria was Apion, (29) who uttered many blasphemies against the Jews; and, among other things that he said, he charged them with neglecting the honors that belonged to Caesar; for that while all who were subject to the Roman empire built altars and temples to Gaius, and in other regards universally received him as they received the gods, these Jews alone thought it a dishonorable thing for them to erect statues in honor of him, as well as to swear by his name. Many of these severe things were said by Apion, by which he hoped to provoke Gaius to anger at the Jews, as he was likely to be. But Philo, the principal of the Jewish embassage, a man eminent on all accounts, brother to Alexander the alabarch, (30) and one not unskillful in philosophy, was ready to betake himself to make his defense against those accusations; but Gaius prohibited him, and bid him begone; he was also in such a rage, that it openly appeared he was about to do them some very great mischief. So Philo being thus affronted, went out, and said to those Jews who were about him, that they should be of good courage, since Gaius's words indeed showed anger at them, but in reality had already set God against himself." [''Antiquities of the Jews'', xviii. 8, § 1, Whiston's translation (online)].
  
Philo read the [[Tanakh|Hebrew Bible]] chiefly in the Greek translation. His knowledge of Hebrew has been a matter of scholarly dispute, with most scholars arguing that he did not read that language. One piece of evidence that supports that hypothesis is Philo's creative (often fanciful) use of etymologies. His knowledge of [[Torah|Jewish law]], (Torah being the extent of canonized Jewish Law during Philo's life) however, was extensive and is at the heart of much of his work.
+
In his ''Embassy to Gaius,''  Philo says he was carrying a petition which described the sufferings of the Alexandrian Jews, and which asked the emperor to secure their rights. Philo says he was selected to represent his people because he had unusual prudence, due to his age, education, and knowledge.  Philo gives a detailed description of the sufferings of the Jews at the hands of Flaccus, and protests that Gaius' plan to erect a statue of himself in the temple of Jerusalem is be a provocation, saying, "Are you making war upon us, because you anticipate that we will not endure such indignity, but that we will fight on behalf of our laws, and die in defence of our national customs? For you cannot possibly have been ignorant of what was likely to result from your attempt to introduce these innovations respecting our temple.His presentation supports the Jewish commitment to rebel against the emperor rather than allow such sacrilege to take place.  [''Embassy to Gaius'', Chapter 28-31, Yonge's translation (online)].
  
== Exegesis ==
+
Philo’s work "Flaccus," gives a valuable account of the plight of the Jews in Alexandria under Emperor Caius Caligula  and Flaccus, the Roman governor of Alexandria.  Philo relates that Flaccus permitted a Greek mob to erect statues of the Emperor Caius in Jewish synagogues of Alexandria, an unprecendented provocation.  This invasion of the synagogues was perhaps resisted by force, since Philo then says that Flaccus "was destroying the synagogues, and not leaving even their name."  In response, Philo says that Flaccus "issued a notice in which he called us all foreigners and aliens...  allowing any one who was inclined to proceed to exterminate the Jews as prisoners of war."  The mobs "drove the Jews entirely out of four quarters, and crammed them all into a very small portion of one ...  while the populace, overrunning their desolate houses, turned to plunder, and divided the booty among themselves as if they had obtained it in war."  Philo says their enemies, "slew them and thousands of others with all kinds of agony and tortures, and newly invented cruelties, for wherever they met with or caught sight of a Jew, they stoned him, or beat him with sticks…the most merciless of all their persecutors in some instances burnt whole families, husbands with their wives, and infant children with their parents, in the middle of the city, sparing neither age nor youth, nor the innocent helplessness of infants."  Some men, he says, were dragged to death, while "those who did these things, mimicked the sufferers, like people employed in the representation of theatrical farces".  Other Jews were crucified.  Flaccus was eventually removed from office and exiled, ultimately suffering the punishment of death.  [''Flaccus'', Chapters 6 - 9 (43, 53-56, 62, 66, 68, 71-72), Yonge's  translation (online)].
  
The writings of Philo show resemblances to [[Plato]], [[Aristotle]], as well as from Attic orators and historians, and poetic phrases and allusions to the poets. Philo's works offer an anthology of Greek phraseology of the most different periods.
+
== Works ==
 +
Philo wrote mostly philosophical essays on the main themes of biblical thought.  He regarded Moses as a great philosopher, and attempted to show how Platonic or Stoic ideas resembled deductions made from the Biblical verses of Moses.  He was not the first to attempt to reconcile Greek thought with Hebrew tradition; philosophers such as Aristobulus and Pseudo-Aristeas had preceded him.  He was, however, the most successful and the most influential to do so.  His work was not widely accepted by his contemporaries. "The sophists of literalness," as he calls them (''De Somniis,'' i. 16-17), "opened their eyes superciliously" when he explained to them the marvels of his exegesis.  
 +
 +
Philo's works can be classified into three groups:
 +
1. Paraphrases of the Biblical texts of Moses: On Abraham, On the Decalogue, On Joseph, The Life of Moses, On the Creation of the World, On Rewards and Punishments, On the Special Laws, On the Virtues. A series of works include allegorical explanations of Genesis 2-41: On Husbandry, On the Cherubim, On the Confusion of Tongues, On the Preliminary Studies, The Worse Attacks the Better, On Drunkenness, On Flight and Finding, On the Giants, Allegorical Interpretation (Allegory of the Law), On the Migration of Abraham, On the Change of Names, On Noah's Work as a Planter, On the Posterity and Exile of Cain, Who is the Heir, On the Unchangeableness of God, On the Sacrifices of Abel and Cain, On Sobriety, On Dreams. Here belong also: Questions and Answers on Genesis and Questions and Answers on Exodus
  
Philo bases his doctrines on the Hebrew Bible, which he considers as the source and standard not only of religious truth but in general of all truth. Its pronouncements are for him divine pronouncements. They are the words of the ἱερὸς λόγος ϑειος ὀρϑὸς λόγος λόγος ("De Agricultura Noë," § 12 [i. 308]; "De Somniis," i. 681, ii. 25) uttered sometimes directly and sometimes through the mouth of a prophet, especially through Moses, whom Philo considers the real medium of revelation, while the other writers of the Old Testament appear as friends or pupils of Moses.
+
2. Philosophical treatises: Every Good Man is Free (a sequel of which had the theme that every bad man is a slave, which did not survive); On the Eternity of the World; On Providence : Alexander or On Whether Brute Animals Possess Reason (preserved only in Armenian) and called in Latin De Animalibus (On the Animals); a brief fragment De Deo (On God), preserved only in Armenian is an exegesis of Genesis 18, and belongs to the Allegory of the Law.
 +
3. Historical writings: Hypothetica or Apologia Pro Judaeos, which survives only in two Greek extracts quoted by Eusebius. Hypothetica is a rationalistic version of Exodus contrasting the severity of the Mosaic law with the laxity of the gentile laws.  Apologia Pro Judaeos describes the Essenes. The other apologetic essays include Against Flaccus, The Embassy to Gaius, and On the Contemplative Life, which describes the life of the monastic ascetic group of Therapeutae and Therapeutrides. All of these works relate to Philo's explanations of the texts of Moses.  
 +
Philo’s works are the most important surviving documents of Hellenistic Judaism.  In addition to being philosophical treatises, they furnish a great deal of historical information about the Alexandrian Jewish community and the interactions between the Jews and the Roman government.
 +
== Thought ==
 +
Philo used philosophy to defend and justify Jewish religious truths. He regarded these truths as fixed and determinate; philosophy was a means of arriving at truth and an aid to understanding it. Philo rejected certain philosophical tenets of the Greeks which did not harmonize with the Jewish religion, such as the Aristotelian doctrine of the eternity and indestructibility of the world.  Philo regarded the Bible as not only as a religious revelation, but as a source of philosophic truth; according to him, Greek philosophers such as Heraclitus (Rerum Divinarum Heres Sit," § 43 (i. 503) ), Zeno ("Quod Omnis Probus Liber," § 8 (ii. 454)), Lycurgus, and Hesiod had also borrowed from the Bible.  Greek philosophy seemed a natural development of the revelatory teachings of Moses.
  
Although he distinguishes between the words uttered by God, as the Decalogue, and the edicts of Moses, as the special laws ("De Specialibus Legibus," §§ 2 et seq. [ii. 300 et seq.]; "De Præmiis et Pœnis," § 1 [ii. 408]), he does not carry out this distinction, since he believes in general that everything in the Torah is of divine origin, even the letters and accents ("De Mutatione Nominum," § 8 [i. 587]).
+
Philo based his doctrines on the Hebrew Bible, which he considered the source and standard not only of religious, but of all truth. He considered its pronouncements to be divine pronouncements. They were the words of the ἱερὸς λόγος ϑειος ὀρϑὸς λόγος λόγος ("De Agricultura Noë," § 12 [i. 308]; "De Somniis," i. 681, ii. 25) uttered sometimes directly and sometimes through the mouth of a prophet, especially through Moses.  Philo viewed Moses the real medium of revelation, while the other writers of the Old Testament appeared as friends or pupils of Moses.  Although he distinguished between the words uttered by God, as the Decalogue, and the edicts of Moses, as the special laws ("De Specialibus Legibus," §§ 2 et seq. [ii. 300 et seq.]; "De Præmiis et Pœnis," § 1 [ii. 408]), he believed that everything in the Torah was of divine origin, even the letters and accents ("De Mutatione Nominum," § 8 [i. 587]).
  
The [[Hebrew Bible]] had not been [[Biblical canon|canonized]] at the time of Philo, and the extent of his knowledge of Biblical books cannot be exactly determined. Philo does not quote Ezekiel, Daniel, Canticles, Ruth, Lamentations, Ecclesiastes, or Esther. Philo regards the Bible as the source not only of religious revelation, but also of philosophic truth; for, according to him, the Greek philosophers also have borrowed from the Bible: Heraclitus, according to "[http://quisblog.250m.com Quis] Rerum Divinarum Heres Sit," § 43 [i. 503]; Zeno, according to "Quod Omnis Probus Liber," § 8 [ii. 454].
+
The [[Hebrew Bible]] had not been [[Biblical canon|canonized]] at the time of Philo, and the extent of his knowledge of Biblical books cannot be exactly determined. Philo does not quote Ezekiel, Daniel, Canticles, Ruth, Lamentations, Ecclesiastes, or Esther.  
 +
=== Truth and Allegory ===
 +
Philo, like other Jewish allegorists who preceded him, sought the hidden meaning of traditional texts in the Hebrew Bible and used symbolism to uncover truths which he related to later philosophical ideas.  He used philosophy to interpret the Jewish scriptures in the same way that Stoic allegorists found philosophical meaning in the works of Homer.  In some aspects of Jewish life, such as circumcision and observance of the Sabbath, Philo defended a literal interpretation of the scriptures, though he acknowledged the symbolic meaning of these rituals.
 +
Philo based his [[hermeneutics]] on the assumption of a twofold meaning in the Bible, the literal and the [[allegory|allegorical]]. He distinguishes the ῥητὴ καὶ φανερὰ ἀπόδοσις ("De Abrahamo," § 36 [ii. 29 et seq.]), "ad litteram" in contrast to "allegorice" ("Quæstiones in Genesin," ii. 21).  The two interpretations, however, were not of equal importance: the literal sense was adapted to human needs; but the allegorical sense was the real one, which only the initiated could comprehend. Philo addressed his discourses to the μύσται  ("initiated") among his audience, whom he expected to be able to comprehend his meaning. ("De Cherubim," § 14 [i. 47]; "De Somniis," i. 33 [i. 649]).
  
==Stoic influence==
+
A special method was requisite for determining the real meaning of the words of Scripture ("Canons of Allegory," "De Victimas Offerentibus," § 5 [ii. 255]); "Laws of Allegory," "De Abrahamo," § 15 [ii. 11]); the correct application of this method determined the correct allegory, and was therefore called "the wise architect" ("De Somniis," ii. 2 [i. 660]).  According to these rules of interpretation the literal sense of certain passages of the Bible had to be excluded altogether, such as the passages in which, according to a literal interpretation, something unworthy is said of God; or in which statements are made that are unworthy of the Bible, senseless, contradictory, or inadmissible; or in which allegorical expressions are used for the avowed purpose of drawing the reader's attention to the fact that the literal sense is to be disregarded.
  
Greek allegory had preceded Philo in this field. As the Stoic allegorists sought in Homer the basis for their philosophic teachings, so the Jewish allegorists, and especially Philo, went to the Old Testament. Following the methods of Stoic allegory, they interpreted the Bible philosophically (on Philo's Predecessors in the domain of the allegoristic Midrash among the Palestinian and Alexandrian Jews, see Siegfried, l.c. pp. 16-37).
+
Philo developed special guidelines to help the reader to recognize the passages which demanded an allegorical interpretation, and to help the initiated find the correct and intended meaning. Passages which contained the doubling of a phrase; an apparently superfluous expression in the text; the repetition of statements previously made; or a change of phraseology, indicated something special that the reader must consider. An entirely different meaning might also be found by disregarding the ordinarily accepted division of a sentence into phrases and clauses, and forming a different combination of the words. Synonyms required careful study; for example, why λαὸς was used in one passage and γένος in another. A play upon words might be utilized to uncover  a deeper meaning; e.g., sheep (πρόβατον) stand for progress in knowledge, since they derive their name from the fact of their progressing (προβαίνειν). A definite allegorical sense could be gathered from certain particles, adverbs, and prepositions; and in certain cases it could be gathered even from the parts of a word; such as from διά in διάλευκος. Every word must be explained in all its meanings, in order that different interpretations might be found. A skillful interpreter might make slight changes in a word, following the rabbinical rule, "Read not this way, but that way." Philo, therefore, changed accents, and breathings in Greek words. Any peculiarity in a phrase justified the assumption that some special meaning was intended: for example, where μία ("one") is used instead of πρώτη ("first"; Gen. i. 5). Details regarding the forms of words were very important: number and gender; whether the word showed any peculiarity in the singular or the plural: verb tense; or the presence or omission of an article.  Other clues to deeper meaning were the artificial interpretation of a single expression; the position of the verses of a passage; peculiar verse-combinations; noteworthy omissions; striking statements; and [[numerology|numeral symbolism]].  
 
 
==Attitude toward literal meaning==
 
 
 
Philo bases his [[hermeneutics]] on the assumption of a twofold meaning in the Bible, the literal and the [[allegory|allegorical]]. He distinguishes the ῥητὴ καὶ φανερὰ ἀπόδοσις ("De Abrahamo," § 36 [ii. 29 et seq.]), "ad litteram" in contrast to "allegorice" ("Quæstiones in Genesin," ii. 21).
 
 
 
The two interpretations, however, are not of equal importance: the literal sense is adapted to human needs; but the allegorical sense is the real one, which only the initiated comprehend. Hence Philo addresses himself to the μύσται  ("initiated") among his audience, by whom he expects to be really comprehended ("De Cherubim," § 14 [i. 47]; "De Somniis," i. 33 [i. 649]).
 
 
 
A special method is requisite for determining the real meaning of the words of Scripture ("Canons of Allegory," "De Victimas Offerentibus," § 5 [ii. 255]); "Laws of Allegory," "De Abrahamo," § 15 [ii. 11]); the correct application of this method determines the correct allegory, and is therefore called "the wise architect" ("De Somniis," ii. 2 [i. 660]).
 
 
 
As a result of some of these rules of interpretation the [[literal and figurative language|literal sense]] of certain passages of the Bible must be excluded altogether; e.g., passages in which according to a literal interpretation something unworthy is said of God; or in which statements are made that are unworthy of the Bible, senseless, contradictory, or inadmissible; or in which allegorical expressions are used for the avowed purpose of drawing the reader's attention to the fact that the literal sense is to be disregarded.
 
 
 
He has special rules that direct the reader to recognize the passages which demand an allegorical interpretation, and which help the initiated to find the correct and intended meaning. These passages are such as contain: (1) the doubling of a phrase; (2) an apparently superfluous expression in the text; (3) the repetition of statements previously made; (4) a change of phraseology—all these phenomena point to something special that the reader must consider. (5) An entirely different meaning may also be found by a different combination of the words, disregarding the ordinarily accepted division of the sentence in question into phrases and clauses. (6) The synonyms must be carefully studied; e.g., why λαὸς is used in one passage and γένος in another, etc. (7) A [[pun|play upon words]] must be utilized for finding a deeper meaning; e.g., sheep (πρόβατον) stand for progress in knowledge, since they derive their name from the fact of their progressing (προβαίνειν), etc. (8) A definite allegorical sense may be gathered from certain particles, adverbs, prepositions, etc.; and in certain cases it can be gathered even from (9) the parts of a word; e.g., from διά in διάλευκος. (10) Every word must be explained in all its meanings, in order that different interpretations may be found. (11) The skillful interpreter may make slight changes in a word, following the rabbinical rule, "Read not this way, but that way." Philo, therefore, changed accents, breathings, etc., in Greek words. (12) Any peculiarity in a phrase justifies the assumption that some special meaning is intended: e.g., where μία ("one") is used instead of πρώτη ("first"; Gen. i. 5), etc. Details regarding the form of words are very important: (13) the [[number]] of the word, if it shows any peculiarity in the singular or the plural: the tense of the verb, etc.; (14) the gender of the noun; (15) the presence or omission of the article; (16) the artificial interpretation of a single expression; (17) the position of the verses of a passage; (18) peculiar verse-combinations; (19) noteworthy omissions; (20) striking statements; (21) [[numerology|numeral symbolism]]. Philo found much material for this symbolism in the Hebrew Bible, and he developed it more thoroughly according to the methods of the Pythagoreans and Stoics. He could follow in many points the tradition handed down by his allegorizing predecessors ("De Vita Contemplativa," § 8 [ii. 481]).
 
 
 
== Numbers ==
 
  
 +
=== Numerology ===
 
Philo analyzed the usage of numbers of the Bible, and believed that certain numbers symbolized different ideas.
 
Philo analyzed the usage of numbers of the Bible, and believed that certain numbers symbolized different ideas.
 +
* Number one is God's number, and the basis for all numbers ("De Allegoriis Legum," ii. 12 [i. 66]).
 +
* Number two is the number of schism, of that which has been created, of death ("De Opificio Mundi, § 9 [i. 7]; "De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]; "De Somaniis," ii. 10 [i. 688]).
 +
* Three is the number of the body ("De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]) or of the Divine Being in connection with His fundamental powers ("De Sacrificiis Abelis et Caini," § 15 [i. 173]).
 +
* Four is potentially what the number ten actually is, the perfect number ("De Opificio Mundi," §§ 15, 16 [i. 10, 11], etc.); but in an evil sense four is the number of the passions, πάθη ("De Congressu Quærendæ Eruditionis Gratia." § 17 [i. 532]).
 +
* Five is the number of the senses and of sensibility ("De Opificio Mundi," § 20 [i. 14], etc.).
 +
* Six, the product of the masculine and feminine numbers 3 × 2 and in its parts equal to 3+3, is the symbol of the movement of organic beings ("De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]).
 +
* Seven has the most various and marvelous attributes ("De Opiticio Mundi," §§ 30-43 [i. 21 et seq.]).
 +
* Eight, the number of the cube, has many of the attributes determined by the Pythagoreans ("Quæstiones in Genesin," iii. 49 [i. 223, Aucher]).
 +
* Nine is the number of strife, according to Gen. xiv. ("De Congressu Qu. Eruditionis Gratia," § 17 [i. 532]).
 +
* Ten is the number of perfection ("De Plantatione Noë," § 29 [i. 347]).
  
* Philo regards number one as God's number, and the basis for all numbers ("De Allegoriis Legum," ii. 12 [i. 66]).
+
Philo also attributed special significance to the numbers 50, 70, and 100, 12, and 120.
  
* Philo regards number two as the number of schism, of that which has been created, of death ("De Opificio Mundi, § 9 [i. 7]; "De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]; "De Somaniis," ii. 10 [i. 688]).
+
===  Logos ===
 +
The term “logos” was widely used in the ancient Hellenistic world.  The Stoics conceived of Logos as the bond between different parts of the world, and the Heracliteans used Logos to refer to the source of the cosmic oppositions.  In Jewish literature “logos” referred to the words of the prophets, or the utterances of God as presented in the scriptures.  Philo synthesized these concepts and used the term Logos to mean the Divine Mind, the Platonic Form of Forms, the Idea of Ideas, or the sum total of Forms or Ideas. (Det. 75-76), the pattern according to which the corporeal universe was fashioned. By its inherent nature, preexistent, unformed matter could not come into direct contact with the Divine; Logos was in an intermediary position between the very essence of God and the substance of the corporeal world.
  
* Three is the number of the body ("De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]) or of the Divine Being in connection with His fundamental powers ("De Sacrificiis Abelis et Caini," § 15 [i. 173]).
+
“For it is out of that essence that God created everything, without indeed touching it himself, for it was not lawful for the all-wise and all-blessed God to touch materials which were all misshapen and confused, but he created them by the agency of his incorporeal powers, of which the proper name is Ideas, which he so exerted that every genus received its proper form.(LA 1.329).
  
* Four is potentially what the number ten actually is, the perfect number ("De Opificio Mundi," §§ 15, 16 [i. 10, 11], etc.); but in an evil sense four is the number of the passions, πάθη ("De Congressu Quærendæ Eruditionis Gratia." § 17 [i. 532]).
+
In an interpretation of the symbolism of the garment of the high priest in Exodus 28:34;36 Philo states: "But the seal is an Idea of Ideas, according to which God fashioned the world, being an incorporeal Idea, comprehensible only by the intellect" (Mig. 103).
  
* Five is the number of the senses and of sensibility ("De Opificio Mundi," § 20 [i. 14], etc.).
+
"The incorporeal world then was already completed, having its seat in the Divine Logos and the world, perceptible by the external senses, was made on the model of it" (Op. 36). Describing Moses' account of the creation of man, Philo claims also that Moses calls the invisible Divine Logos the Image of God (Op. 24; 31; LA 1.9).
  
* Six, the product of the masculine and feminine numbers 3 × 2 and in its parts equal to 3+3, is the symbol of the movement of organic beings ("De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]).
+
Philo also referred to Logos as the “first-born” of God, meaning that it was the first thought proceeding from the mind of God.
  
* Seven has the most various and marvelous attributes ("De Opiticio Mundi," §§ 30-43 [i. 21 et seq.]).
+
Some scholars believe that the concept of the Logos referred to in the prologue to the Gospel of John was influenced directly by Philonic teachings.  Others believe that early Christian writers confounded the Logos of John with the Logos of Philo, but that the two concepts differ and were simply drawn from a common Jewish background.
  
* Eight, the number of the cube, has many of the attributes determined by the Pythagoreans ("Quæstiones in Genesin," iii. 49 [i. 223, Aucher]).
+
== Eternal Creation ==
 +
Philo rejected the Aristotelian conclusion that the world existed from eternity, without any creative act.  "For some men, admiring the world itself rather than the Creator of the world, have represented it as existing without any maker, and eternal, and as impiously and falsely have represented God as existing in a state of complete inactivity" (Op. 7).
  
* Nine is the number of strife, according to Gen. xiv. ("De Congressu Qu. Eruditionis Gratia," § 17 [i. 532]).
+
Philo’s explanation of the Creation is based on the book of Genesis in the Bible.  On the grounds that no praise is given to matter in Genesis, Philo conceives of matter as evil and therefore incapable of direct contact with the divine. ("Quis Rerum Divinarum Heres Sit," § 32 [i. 495]).  As a result, he does not support Creation ex nihilo, but as a strict monist, he also could not accept God’s formation of the world from pre-existent matter, as Plato did.  The instrument of creation is Logos, which shapes formless matter into intelligible beings.  Philo compares God to an architect or gardener, who formed the present world (the κόσμος ἀισϑητός) according to a pattern, the ideal world (κόσμος νοητός).
  
* Ten is the number of perfection ("De Plantatione Noë," § 29 [i. 347]).
+
Philo made a modification to the Platonic doctrine of Forms and elaborated a theory of “eternal creation,” that God did not begin to create the world at a specific moment in time, but is "eternally applying Himself to its creation" (Prov. 1.7; Op. 7; Aet. 83-84).  "For God while he spake the word, did at the same moment create; nor did he allow anything to come between the Logos and the deed; and if one may advance a doctrine which is pretty nearly true, His Logos is his deed" (Sacr. 65; Mos.1.283).  Thus God is eternally and constantly creating the intelligible world of Ideas.  Time is a creation of God and exists only in the physical world (a Platonic concept).  The creative activity as well as the act of creation takes place outside of time.  In that context, formless, shapeless matter never exists because it is instantaneously modified by Logos into organized and intelligible being.
  
Philo determines also the values of the numbers 50, 70, and 100, 12, and 120.
 
  
==Cosmology==
 
  
Philo's conception of the matter out of which the world was created is similar to that of Plato and the Stoics. According to him, God does not create the world-stuff, but finds it ready at hand. God cannot create it, as in its nature it resists all contact with the divine. Sometimes, following the Stoics, he designates God as "the efficient cause,"and matter as "the affected cause." He seems to have found this conception in the Bible (Gen. i. 2) in the image of the spirit of God hovering over the waters ("De Opificio Mundi," § 2 [i. 12]).
 
  
Philo, again like Plato and the Stoics, conceives of matter as having no attributes or form; this, however, does not harmonize with the assumption of four elements. Philo conceives of matter as evil, on the ground that no praise is meted out to it in Genesis ("Quis Rerum Divinarum Heres Sit," § 32 [i. 495]). As a result, he cannot posit an actual Creation, but only a formation of the world, as Plato holds. God appears as demiurge and cosmoplast.
 
  
Philo frequently compares God to an architect or gardener, who formed the present world (the κόσμος ἀισϑητός) according to a pattern, the ideal world (κόσμος νοητός). Philo takes the details of his story of the Creation entirely from Gen. i. A specially important position is assigned here to the Logos, which executes the several acts of the Creation, as God cannot come into contact with matter, actually creating only the soul of the good.
+
___________________________________________________________________
  
== Anthropology ==
 
  
Philo regards the physical nature of man as something defective and as an obstacle to his development that can never be fully surmounted, but still as something indispensable in view of the nature of his being. With the body the necessity for food arises, as Philo explains in various allegories. The body, however, is also of advantage to the spirit, since the spirit arrives at its knowledge of the world by means of the five senses. But higher and more important is the spiritual nature of man. This nature has a twofold tendency: one toward the sensual and earthly, which Philo calls sensibility (αἴσϑησις), and one toward the spiritual, which he calls reason (νοῦς).
 
  
Sensibility has its seat in the body, and lives in the senses, as Philo elaborates in varying allegoric imagery. Connected with this corporeality of the sensibility are its limitations; but, like the body itself, it is a necessity of nature, the channel of all sense-perception. Sensibility, however, is still more in need of being guided by reason. Reason is that part of the spirit which looks toward heavenly things. It is the highest, the real divine gift that has been infused into man from without ("De Opiticio Mundi," i. 15; "De Eo Quod Deterius Potiori Insidiatur," i. 206); it is the masculine nature of the soul. The νοῦς is originally at rest; and when it begins to move it produces the several phenomena of mind (ἔνϑυμήματα). The principal powers of the νοῦς are judgment, memory, and language.
+
Thus Philo produced a synthesis of both traditions developing concepts for future Hellenistic interpretation of messianic Hebrew thought, especially by Clement of Alexandria, Christian Apologists like Athenagoras, Theophilus, Justin Martyr, Tertullian, and by Origen. He may have influenced Paul, his contemporary, and perhaps the authors of the Gospel of John (C. H. Dodd) and the Epistle to the Hebrews (R. Williamson and H. W. Attridge). In the process, he laid the foundations for the development of Christianity in the West and in the East, as we know it today. Philo's primary importance is in the development of the philosophical and theological foundations of Christianity. The church preserved the Philonic writings because Eusebius of Caesarea labeled the monastic ascetic group of Therapeutae and Therapeutrides, described in Philo's The Contemplative Life, as Christians, which is highly unlikely. Eusebius also promoted the legend that Philo met Peter in Rome. Jerome (345-420 C.E.) even lists him as a church Father. Jewish tradition was uninterested in philosophical speculation and did not preserve Philo's
  
More important in Philo's system is the doctrine of the moral development of man. Of this he distinguishes two conditions: (1) that before time was, and (2) that since the beginning of time. In the pretemporal condition the soul was without body, free from earthly matter. Without sex, in the condition of the generic (γενικός) man, morally perfect, i.e., without flaws, but still striving after a higher purity. On entering upon time the soul loses its purity and is confined in a body. The nous becomes earthly, but it retains a tendency toward something higher.
 
  
Philo is not entirely certain whether the body in itself or merely in its preponderance over the spirit is evil. But the body in any case is a source of danger, as it easily drags the spirit into the bonds of sensibility. Here, also, Philo is undecided whether sensibility is in itself evil, or whether it may merely lead into temptation, and must itself be regarded as a mean (μέσον). Sensibility in any case is the source of the passions and desires. The passions attack the sensibility in order to destroy the whole soul. On their number and their symbols in Scripture see Siegfried, l.c. pp. 245 et seq. The "desire" is either the lustful enjoyment of sensual things, dwelling as such in the abdominal cavity (κοιλία), or it is the craving for this enjoyment, dwelling in the breast. It connects the nous and the sensibility, this being a psychologic necessity, but an evil from an ethical point of view.
 
  
According to Philo, man passes through several steps in his ethical development. At first the several elements of the human being are in a state of latency, presenting a kind of moral neutrality which Philo designates by the terms "naked" or "medial." The nous is nude, or stands midway so long as it has not decided either for sin or for virtue. In this period of moral indecision God endeavors to prepare the earthly nous for virtue, presenting to him in the "earthly wisdom and virtue" an image of heavenly wisdom. But man (nous) quickly leaves this state of neutrality. As soon as he meets the woman (sensibility) he is filled with desire, and passion ensnares him in the bonds of sensibility. Here the moral duties of man arise; and according to his attitude there are two opposite tendencies in humanity.
 
  
== Ethics ==
+
The [[Aristotle|Aristotelian]] contrast between δύναμις and ἐντελέχεια ("Metaphysics," iii. 73) is found in Philo, "De Allegoriis Legum," i 64 (on Aristotle see Freudenthal in "Monatsschrift," 1875, p.233). In his psychology he adopts either the Stoic division of the soul into eight faculties, or the Platonic trichotomy of reason, courage, and desire, or the Aristotelian triad of the vegetative, emotive, and rational souls.
  
The soul is first aroused by the stimuli of sensual pleasures; it begins to turn toward them, and then becomes more and more involved. It becomes devoted to the body, and begins to lead an intolerable life (βίος ἄβίωτος). It is inflamed and excited by irrational impulses. Its condition is restless and painful. The sensibility endures, according to Gen. iii. 16, great pain. A continual inner void produces a lasting desire which is never satisfied. All the higher aspirations after God and virtue are stilled. The end is complete moral turpitude, the annihilation of all sense of duty, the corruption of the entire soul: not a particle of the soul that might heal the rest remains whole.
 
  
The worst consequence of this moral death is, according to Philo, absolute ignorance and the loss of the power of judgment. Sensual things are placed above spiritual; and wealth is regarded as the highest good. Too great a value especially is placed upon the human nous; and things are wrongly judged. Man in his folly even opposes God, and thinks to scale heaven and subjugate the entire earth. In the field of politics, for example, he attempts to rise from the position of leader of the people to that of ruler (Philo cites Joseph as a type of this kind). Sensual man generally employs his intellectual powers for sophistry, perverting words and destroying truth.
+
== Morality and Ethics ==
  
The biblical patriarch [[Abraham]] is seen by Philo as the symbol of man leaving sensuality to turn to reason ("De Migratione Abrahami." § 4 [i. 439]). Philo holds that there are three methods whereby one can rise toward the divine: through teaching, through practise(ἄσκησις), and through natural goodness (ὁσιότης).  
+
Philo regards the physical nature of man as being defective and an obstacle to his development, but as an indispensable aspect of the nature of his being.  The body has certain physical requirements which sometimes interfere with spiritual progress, yet it is of advantage to the spirit,  since the spirit arrives at its knowledge of the world by means of the five senses. The spiritual nature of man, which  has priority over the physical body. has a twofold tendency: one toward the sensual and earthly, which Philo calls sensibility (αἴσϑησις), and one toward the spiritual, which he calls reason (νοῦς).
  
== Views on virtue ==
+
Sensibility has its seat in the body, and lives in the senses. Sensibility, however, is in need of being guided by reason. Reason is that part of the spirit which looks toward heavenly things. It is the highest, the real divine gift that has been infused into man from without ("De Opiticio Mundi," i. 15; "De Eo Quod Deterius Potiori Insidiatur," i. 206). The νοῦς is originally at rest; when it begins to move it produces the several phenomena of mind (ἔνϑυμήματα). The principal powers of the νοῦς are judgment, memory, and language.
  
Philo holds that good moral endowment takes precedence of teaching and practise. Virtue here is not the result of hard labor, but is the excellent fruit maturing of itself. The biblical character [[Noah]] represents the preliminary stage. Noah is praised, while no really good deeds are reported of him, whence it may be concluded that the Bible refers to his good disposition. But as Noah is praised only in comparison with his contemporaries, it follows that he is not yet a perfect man.
+
The physical body is a source of danger, as it easily drags the spirit into the bonds of sensibility. Sensibility is the source of the passions and desires; passions attack the sensibility in order to destroy the whole soul. According to Philo, man passes through several steps in his ethical development. At first the several elements of the human being are in a state of latency, a kind of moral neutrality which Philo designates by the terms "naked" or "medial." The soul has not decided either for sin or for virtue. In this period of moral indecision God endeavors to present to it, in the "earthly wisdom and virtue," an image of heavenly wisdom. Man quickly leaves this state of neutrality as soon as he experiences desire, and passion ensnares him in the bonds of sensibility. Here the moral duties of man arise and he must navigate between two opposite tendencies.
  
Philo holds that there are several types in the Bible representing the perfect stage. It appears in its purest form in the biblical patriarch [[Isaac]]. Isaac is perfect from the beginning: perfection is a part of his nature (φύσις); and he can never lose it (αὑτήκοος καὶ αὑτομάϑης). With such persons, therefore, the soul is in a state of rest and joy.
+
Philo interpreted the Jewish scriptures as an allegorical account of the rise and fall of the human soul. The soul was first aroused by the stimuli of sensual pleasures, became devoted to the body, and began to lead an intolerable life (βίος ἄβίωτος), inflamed and excited by irrational impulses. Its condition was restless and painful; a continual inner void produced a lasting desire which was never satisfied. All the higher aspirations after God and virtue were stilled, the entire soul was corrupt and ignorant, and the power of judgement was lost.  Sensual things were valued above spiritual; and wealth was regarded as the highest good. Man in his folly even opposed God, and thought to scale heaven and subjugate the entire earth. The biblical patriarch [[Abraham]] was regarded by Philo as the symbol of man leaving sensuality to turn to reason ("De Migratione Abrahami." § 4 [i. 439]).  
  
Philo's doctrine of virtue is Stoic, although he is undecided whether complete dispassionateness (άπάϑεια; "De Allegoriis Legum." iii. 45 [i. 513]) or moderation (μετριοπαϑεῑν; "De Abrahamo," § 44 [ii. 137]) designates the really virtuous condition. Philo identifies virtue in itself and in general with divine wisdom. Hence he uses the symbols interchangeably for both; and as he also frequently identifies the Logos with divine wisdom, the allegoric designations here too are easily interchanged.
+
Philo elaborated three methods by which one can rise toward the divine: through education, through practice (ἄσκησις), and through natural goodness (ὁσιότης). 
 +
Good moral endowment takes precedence over education and practice. Virtue was not the result of hard labor, but was an excellent fruit maturing of itself. The biblical character [[Noah]] represented the preliminary stage. Noah was called by God, apparently because of his good disposition, since no particularly good deeds were reported of him. As Noah was praised only in comparison with his contemporaries, it followed that he was not yet a perfect man.
  
The Garden of Eden is "the wisdom of God" and also "the Logos of God" and "virtue." The fundamental virtue is goodness; and from it proceed four cardinal virtues—prudence, courage, self-control, and justice (φρόνησις, ἀνδρία, σωφροσύνη, δικαιοσύνη) — as the four rivers proceed from the river of [[Eden]].
+
Philo identified several characters in the Scriptures who represented the perfect man, such as the biblical patriarch [[Isaac]]. Perfection was a part of the nature (φύσις) of such persons; their souls were in a state of rest and joy. Philo’s concept of virtue resembled that of the Stoics, but he taught that man could not attain virtue through his own efforts, but only through religion, with the assistance of God.  
  
An essential difference between Philo and the Stoics is found in the fact that Philo seeks in religion the basis for all ethics. Religion helps man to attain to virtue, which he can not reach of himself, as the Stoics hold. God must implant virtue in man ("De Allegoriis Legum," i. 53 [i. 73]). Hence the goal of the ethical endeavor is a religious one: the ecstatic contemplation of God and the disembodiment of souls after death.
+
The Garden of Eden was a symbol for "the wisdom of God," the “Logos of God’” and “virtue.”  From it proceeded four rivers representing the cardinal virtues of prudence, courage, self-control, and justice (φρόνησις, ἀνδρία, σωφροσύνη, δικαιοσύνη).
  
 
==See also==
 
==See also==

Revision as of 01:49, 31 July 2006

Template:Wikify-date

For other uses, see Philo Judaeus (disambiguation).

Philo (20 B.C.E. – 50 C.E.), known also as Philo of Alexandria and as Philo Judeus, was a Hellenized Jewish philosopher who synthesized Stoic, Platonic and Jewish ideas and laid a philosophical and theological foundation for the development of Christianity in the West and the East and, indirectly, for rational theologians in the Jewish and Islamic worlds. He developed concepts later used in the interpretations of Clement of Alexandria, Athenagoras, Theophilus, Justin Martyr, Tertullian and Origen. It is thought that he may have influenced Paul and the authors of the Gospel of John and the Epistle to the Hebrews. the highest perception of truth is possible only after a study of the encyclopedic sciences.

Philo was ignored by the Jewish tradition, which emphasized theology over philosophical speculations. His works were preserved by the Christian church, primarily because some early Christians perceived him as a Christian. Eusebius speculated that the Therapeutae, the Jewish group of ascetic hermits in the Egyptian desert that Philo describes in De vita contemplativa ("Contemplative Life") was in fact a Christian group.

Life

Little information is available about the life of Philo, except for a few biographical details in his own works, especially in Legatio ad Caium, ("Embassy to Caius"), and a brief mention of him in the Antiquities" (xviii. 8, § 1; comp. ib. xix. 5, § 1; xx. 5, § 2) of Josephus.

He was born about 25 B.C.E. in Alexandria, which at that time was home to the largest Jewish community outside of Palestine. He was part of a prominent family; his brother Alexander Lysimachus was a wealthy official of the Roman government, who donated money to plate the gates of the temple in Jerusalem with gold and silver, and made a loan to Herod Agrippa I, grandson of Herod the Great. One of Alexander’s sons married a daughter of Herod Agrippa I, and his other son abandoned the Jewish faith and became procurator of Judea and Prefect of Egypt. Philo mentions that he once visited Jerusalem.

From Philo’s works it is clear that he had a thorough knowledge of Greek and of the theories of the Stoics, Plato’s dialogues, and neo-Pythagorean writings. He said that a study of the sciences… It is apparent that he used a Greek translation of the Jewish scriptures rather than Hebrew manuscripts. His “Allegorical Commentary” indicates that he was deeply involved in the Jewish community. The most documented episode of his life is his participation in a Jewish delegation which traveled to Rome in 39 C.E. to complain to Emperor Gaius Caligula about the persecution of the Jews in Alexandria by the governor, Flaccus.

Josephus gives the following account of this mission in Antiquities: "There was now a tumult arisen at Alexandria, between the Jewish inhabitants and the Greeks; and three ambassadors were chosen out of each party that were at variance, who came to Gaius. Now one of these ambassadors from the people of Alexandria was Apion, (29) who uttered many blasphemies against the Jews; and, among other things that he said, he charged them with neglecting the honors that belonged to Caesar; for that while all who were subject to the Roman empire built altars and temples to Gaius, and in other regards universally received him as they received the gods, these Jews alone thought it a dishonorable thing for them to erect statues in honor of him, as well as to swear by his name. Many of these severe things were said by Apion, by which he hoped to provoke Gaius to anger at the Jews, as he was likely to be. But Philo, the principal of the Jewish embassage, a man eminent on all accounts, brother to Alexander the alabarch, (30) and one not unskillful in philosophy, was ready to betake himself to make his defense against those accusations; but Gaius prohibited him, and bid him begone; he was also in such a rage, that it openly appeared he was about to do them some very great mischief. So Philo being thus affronted, went out, and said to those Jews who were about him, that they should be of good courage, since Gaius's words indeed showed anger at them, but in reality had already set God against himself." [Antiquities of the Jews, xviii. 8, § 1, Whiston's translation (online)].

In his Embassy to Gaius, Philo says he was carrying a petition which described the sufferings of the Alexandrian Jews, and which asked the emperor to secure their rights. Philo says he was selected to represent his people because he had unusual prudence, due to his age, education, and knowledge. Philo gives a detailed description of the sufferings of the Jews at the hands of Flaccus, and protests that Gaius' plan to erect a statue of himself in the temple of Jerusalem is be a provocation, saying, "Are you making war upon us, because you anticipate that we will not endure such indignity, but that we will fight on behalf of our laws, and die in defence of our national customs? For you cannot possibly have been ignorant of what was likely to result from your attempt to introduce these innovations respecting our temple." His presentation supports the Jewish commitment to rebel against the emperor rather than allow such sacrilege to take place. [Embassy to Gaius, Chapter 28-31, Yonge's translation (online)].

Philo’s work "Flaccus," gives a valuable account of the plight of the Jews in Alexandria under Emperor Caius Caligula and Flaccus, the Roman governor of Alexandria. Philo relates that Flaccus permitted a Greek mob to erect statues of the Emperor Caius in Jewish synagogues of Alexandria, an unprecendented provocation. This invasion of the synagogues was perhaps resisted by force, since Philo then says that Flaccus "was destroying the synagogues, and not leaving even their name." In response, Philo says that Flaccus "issued a notice in which he called us all foreigners and aliens... allowing any one who was inclined to proceed to exterminate the Jews as prisoners of war." The mobs "drove the Jews entirely out of four quarters, and crammed them all into a very small portion of one ... while the populace, overrunning their desolate houses, turned to plunder, and divided the booty among themselves as if they had obtained it in war." Philo says their enemies, "slew them and thousands of others with all kinds of agony and tortures, and newly invented cruelties, for wherever they met with or caught sight of a Jew, they stoned him, or beat him with sticks…the most merciless of all their persecutors in some instances burnt whole families, husbands with their wives, and infant children with their parents, in the middle of the city, sparing neither age nor youth, nor the innocent helplessness of infants." Some men, he says, were dragged to death, while "those who did these things, mimicked the sufferers, like people employed in the representation of theatrical farces". Other Jews were crucified. Flaccus was eventually removed from office and exiled, ultimately suffering the punishment of death. [Flaccus, Chapters 6 - 9 (43, 53-56, 62, 66, 68, 71-72), Yonge's translation (online)].

Works

Philo wrote mostly philosophical essays on the main themes of biblical thought. He regarded Moses as a great philosopher, and attempted to show how Platonic or Stoic ideas resembled deductions made from the Biblical verses of Moses. He was not the first to attempt to reconcile Greek thought with Hebrew tradition; philosophers such as Aristobulus and Pseudo-Aristeas had preceded him. He was, however, the most successful and the most influential to do so. His work was not widely accepted by his contemporaries. "The sophists of literalness," as he calls them (De Somniis, i. 16-17), "opened their eyes superciliously" when he explained to them the marvels of his exegesis.

Philo's works can be classified into three groups: 1. Paraphrases of the Biblical texts of Moses: On Abraham, On the Decalogue, On Joseph, The Life of Moses, On the Creation of the World, On Rewards and Punishments, On the Special Laws, On the Virtues. A series of works include allegorical explanations of Genesis 2-41: On Husbandry, On the Cherubim, On the Confusion of Tongues, On the Preliminary Studies, The Worse Attacks the Better, On Drunkenness, On Flight and Finding, On the Giants, Allegorical Interpretation (Allegory of the Law), On the Migration of Abraham, On the Change of Names, On Noah's Work as a Planter, On the Posterity and Exile of Cain, Who is the Heir, On the Unchangeableness of God, On the Sacrifices of Abel and Cain, On Sobriety, On Dreams. Here belong also: Questions and Answers on Genesis and Questions and Answers on Exodus

2. Philosophical treatises: Every Good Man is Free (a sequel of which had the theme that every bad man is a slave, which did not survive); On the Eternity of the World; On Providence : Alexander or On Whether Brute Animals Possess Reason (preserved only in Armenian) and called in Latin De Animalibus (On the Animals); a brief fragment De Deo (On God), preserved only in Armenian is an exegesis of Genesis 18, and belongs to the Allegory of the Law. 3. Historical writings: Hypothetica or Apologia Pro Judaeos, which survives only in two Greek extracts quoted by Eusebius. Hypothetica is a rationalistic version of Exodus contrasting the severity of the Mosaic law with the laxity of the gentile laws. Apologia Pro Judaeos describes the Essenes. The other apologetic essays include Against Flaccus, The Embassy to Gaius, and On the Contemplative Life, which describes the life of the monastic ascetic group of Therapeutae and Therapeutrides. All of these works relate to Philo's explanations of the texts of Moses. Philo’s works are the most important surviving documents of Hellenistic Judaism. In addition to being philosophical treatises, they furnish a great deal of historical information about the Alexandrian Jewish community and the interactions between the Jews and the Roman government.

Thought

Philo used philosophy to defend and justify Jewish religious truths. He regarded these truths as fixed and determinate; philosophy was a means of arriving at truth and an aid to understanding it. Philo rejected certain philosophical tenets of the Greeks which did not harmonize with the Jewish religion, such as the Aristotelian doctrine of the eternity and indestructibility of the world. Philo regarded the Bible as not only as a religious revelation, but as a source of philosophic truth; according to him, Greek philosophers such as Heraclitus (Rerum Divinarum Heres Sit," § 43 (i. 503) ), Zeno ("Quod Omnis Probus Liber," § 8 (ii. 454)), Lycurgus, and Hesiod had also borrowed from the Bible. Greek philosophy seemed a natural development of the revelatory teachings of Moses.

Philo based his doctrines on the Hebrew Bible, which he considered the source and standard not only of religious, but of all truth. He considered its pronouncements to be divine pronouncements. They were the words of the ἱερὸς λόγος ϑειος ὀρϑὸς λόγος λόγος ("De Agricultura Noë," § 12 [i. 308]; "De Somniis," i. 681, ii. 25) uttered sometimes directly and sometimes through the mouth of a prophet, especially through Moses. Philo viewed Moses the real medium of revelation, while the other writers of the Old Testament appeared as friends or pupils of Moses. Although he distinguished between the words uttered by God, as the Decalogue, and the edicts of Moses, as the special laws ("De Specialibus Legibus," §§ 2 et seq. [ii. 300 et seq.]; "De Præmiis et Pœnis," § 1 [ii. 408]), he believed that everything in the Torah was of divine origin, even the letters and accents ("De Mutatione Nominum," § 8 [i. 587]).

The Hebrew Bible had not been canonized at the time of Philo, and the extent of his knowledge of Biblical books cannot be exactly determined. Philo does not quote Ezekiel, Daniel, Canticles, Ruth, Lamentations, Ecclesiastes, or Esther.

Truth and Allegory

Philo, like other Jewish allegorists who preceded him, sought the hidden meaning of traditional texts in the Hebrew Bible and used symbolism to uncover truths which he related to later philosophical ideas. He used philosophy to interpret the Jewish scriptures in the same way that Stoic allegorists found philosophical meaning in the works of Homer. In some aspects of Jewish life, such as circumcision and observance of the Sabbath, Philo defended a literal interpretation of the scriptures, though he acknowledged the symbolic meaning of these rituals. Philo based his hermeneutics on the assumption of a twofold meaning in the Bible, the literal and the allegorical. He distinguishes the ῥητὴ καὶ φανερὰ ἀπόδοσις ("De Abrahamo," § 36 [ii. 29 et seq.]), "ad litteram" in contrast to "allegorice" ("Quæstiones in Genesin," ii. 21). The two interpretations, however, were not of equal importance: the literal sense was adapted to human needs; but the allegorical sense was the real one, which only the initiated could comprehend. Philo addressed his discourses to the μύσται ("initiated") among his audience, whom he expected to be able to comprehend his meaning. ("De Cherubim," § 14 [i. 47]; "De Somniis," i. 33 [i. 649]).

A special method was requisite for determining the real meaning of the words of Scripture ("Canons of Allegory," "De Victimas Offerentibus," § 5 [ii. 255]); "Laws of Allegory," "De Abrahamo," § 15 [ii. 11]); the correct application of this method determined the correct allegory, and was therefore called "the wise architect" ("De Somniis," ii. 2 [i. 660]). According to these rules of interpretation the literal sense of certain passages of the Bible had to be excluded altogether, such as the passages in which, according to a literal interpretation, something unworthy is said of God; or in which statements are made that are unworthy of the Bible, senseless, contradictory, or inadmissible; or in which allegorical expressions are used for the avowed purpose of drawing the reader's attention to the fact that the literal sense is to be disregarded.

Philo developed special guidelines to help the reader to recognize the passages which demanded an allegorical interpretation, and to help the initiated find the correct and intended meaning. Passages which contained the doubling of a phrase; an apparently superfluous expression in the text; the repetition of statements previously made; or a change of phraseology, indicated something special that the reader must consider. An entirely different meaning might also be found by disregarding the ordinarily accepted division of a sentence into phrases and clauses, and forming a different combination of the words. Synonyms required careful study; for example, why λαὸς was used in one passage and γένος in another. A play upon words might be utilized to uncover a deeper meaning; e.g., sheep (πρόβατον) stand for progress in knowledge, since they derive their name from the fact of their progressing (προβαίνειν). A definite allegorical sense could be gathered from certain particles, adverbs, and prepositions; and in certain cases it could be gathered even from the parts of a word; such as from διά in διάλευκος. Every word must be explained in all its meanings, in order that different interpretations might be found. A skillful interpreter might make slight changes in a word, following the rabbinical rule, "Read not this way, but that way." Philo, therefore, changed accents, and breathings in Greek words. Any peculiarity in a phrase justified the assumption that some special meaning was intended: for example, where μία ("one") is used instead of πρώτη ("first"; Gen. i. 5). Details regarding the forms of words were very important: number and gender; whether the word showed any peculiarity in the singular or the plural: verb tense; or the presence or omission of an article. Other clues to deeper meaning were the artificial interpretation of a single expression; the position of the verses of a passage; peculiar verse-combinations; noteworthy omissions; striking statements; and numeral symbolism.

Numerology

Philo analyzed the usage of numbers of the Bible, and believed that certain numbers symbolized different ideas.

  • Number one is God's number, and the basis for all numbers ("De Allegoriis Legum," ii. 12 [i. 66]).
  • Number two is the number of schism, of that which has been created, of death ("De Opificio Mundi, § 9 [i. 7]; "De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]; "De Somaniis," ii. 10 [i. 688]).
  • Three is the number of the body ("De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]) or of the Divine Being in connection with His fundamental powers ("De Sacrificiis Abelis et Caini," § 15 [i. 173]).
  • Four is potentially what the number ten actually is, the perfect number ("De Opificio Mundi," §§ 15, 16 [i. 10, 11], etc.); but in an evil sense four is the number of the passions, πάθη ("De Congressu Quærendæ Eruditionis Gratia." § 17 [i. 532]).
  • Five is the number of the senses and of sensibility ("De Opificio Mundi," § 20 [i. 14], etc.).
  • Six, the product of the masculine and feminine numbers 3 × 2 and in its parts equal to 3+3, is the symbol of the movement of organic beings ("De Allegoriis Legum," i. 2 [i. 44]).
  • Seven has the most various and marvelous attributes ("De Opiticio Mundi," §§ 30-43 [i. 21 et seq.]).
  • Eight, the number of the cube, has many of the attributes determined by the Pythagoreans ("Quæstiones in Genesin," iii. 49 [i. 223, Aucher]).
  • Nine is the number of strife, according to Gen. xiv. ("De Congressu Qu. Eruditionis Gratia," § 17 [i. 532]).
  • Ten is the number of perfection ("De Plantatione Noë," § 29 [i. 347]).

Philo also attributed special significance to the numbers 50, 70, and 100, 12, and 120.

Logos

The term “logos” was widely used in the ancient Hellenistic world. The Stoics conceived of Logos as the bond between different parts of the world, and the Heracliteans used Logos to refer to the source of the cosmic oppositions. In Jewish literature “logos” referred to the words of the prophets, or the utterances of God as presented in the scriptures. Philo synthesized these concepts and used the term Logos to mean the Divine Mind, the Platonic Form of Forms, the Idea of Ideas, or the sum total of Forms or Ideas. (Det. 75-76), the pattern according to which the corporeal universe was fashioned. By its inherent nature, preexistent, unformed matter could not come into direct contact with the Divine; Logos was in an intermediary position between the very essence of God and the substance of the corporeal world.

“For it is out of that essence that God created everything, without indeed touching it himself, for it was not lawful for the all-wise and all-blessed God to touch materials which were all misshapen and confused, but he created them by the agency of his incorporeal powers, of which the proper name is Ideas, which he so exerted that every genus received its proper form.” (LA 1.329).

In an interpretation of the symbolism of the garment of the high priest in Exodus 28:34;36 Philo states: "But the seal is an Idea of Ideas, according to which God fashioned the world, being an incorporeal Idea, comprehensible only by the intellect" (Mig. 103).

"The incorporeal world then was already completed, having its seat in the Divine Logos and the world, perceptible by the external senses, was made on the model of it" (Op. 36). Describing Moses' account of the creation of man, Philo claims also that Moses calls the invisible Divine Logos the Image of God (Op. 24; 31; LA 1.9).

Philo also referred to Logos as the “first-born” of God, meaning that it was the first thought proceeding from the mind of God.

Some scholars believe that the concept of the Logos referred to in the prologue to the Gospel of John was influenced directly by Philonic teachings. Others believe that early Christian writers confounded the Logos of John with the Logos of Philo, but that the two concepts differ and were simply drawn from a common Jewish background.

Eternal Creation

Philo rejected the Aristotelian conclusion that the world existed from eternity, without any creative act. "For some men, admiring the world itself rather than the Creator of the world, have represented it as existing without any maker, and eternal, and as impiously and falsely have represented God as existing in a state of complete inactivity" (Op. 7).

Philo’s explanation of the Creation is based on the book of Genesis in the Bible. On the grounds that no praise is given to matter in Genesis, Philo conceives of matter as evil and therefore incapable of direct contact with the divine. ("Quis Rerum Divinarum Heres Sit," § 32 [i. 495]). As a result, he does not support Creation ex nihilo, but as a strict monist, he also could not accept God’s formation of the world from pre-existent matter, as Plato did. The instrument of creation is Logos, which shapes formless matter into intelligible beings. Philo compares God to an architect or gardener, who formed the present world (the κόσμος ἀισϑητός) according to a pattern, the ideal world (κόσμος νοητός).

Philo made a modification to the Platonic doctrine of Forms and elaborated a theory of “eternal creation,” that God did not begin to create the world at a specific moment in time, but is "eternally applying Himself to its creation" (Prov. 1.7; Op. 7; Aet. 83-84). "For God while he spake the word, did at the same moment create; nor did he allow anything to come between the Logos and the deed; and if one may advance a doctrine which is pretty nearly true, His Logos is his deed" (Sacr. 65; Mos.1.283). Thus God is eternally and constantly creating the intelligible world of Ideas. Time is a creation of God and exists only in the physical world (a Platonic concept). The creative activity as well as the act of creation takes place outside of time. In that context, formless, shapeless matter never exists because it is instantaneously modified by Logos into organized and intelligible being.


___________________________________________________________________


Thus Philo produced a synthesis of both traditions developing concepts for future Hellenistic interpretation of messianic Hebrew thought, especially by Clement of Alexandria, Christian Apologists like Athenagoras, Theophilus, Justin Martyr, Tertullian, and by Origen. He may have influenced Paul, his contemporary, and perhaps the authors of the Gospel of John (C. H. Dodd) and the Epistle to the Hebrews (R. Williamson and H. W. Attridge). In the process, he laid the foundations for the development of Christianity in the West and in the East, as we know it today. Philo's primary importance is in the development of the philosophical and theological foundations of Christianity. The church preserved the Philonic writings because Eusebius of Caesarea labeled the monastic ascetic group of Therapeutae and Therapeutrides, described in Philo's The Contemplative Life, as Christians, which is highly unlikely. Eusebius also promoted the legend that Philo met Peter in Rome. Jerome (345-420 C.E.) even lists him as a church Father. Jewish tradition was uninterested in philosophical speculation and did not preserve Philo's



The Aristotelian contrast between δύναμις and ἐντελέχεια ("Metaphysics," iii. 73) is found in Philo, "De Allegoriis Legum," i 64 (on Aristotle see Freudenthal in "Monatsschrift," 1875, p.233). In his psychology he adopts either the Stoic division of the soul into eight faculties, or the Platonic trichotomy of reason, courage, and desire, or the Aristotelian triad of the vegetative, emotive, and rational souls.


Morality and Ethics

Philo regards the physical nature of man as being defective and an obstacle to his development, but as an indispensable aspect of the nature of his being. The body has certain physical requirements which sometimes interfere with spiritual progress, yet it is of advantage to the spirit, since the spirit arrives at its knowledge of the world by means of the five senses. The spiritual nature of man, which has priority over the physical body. has a twofold tendency: one toward the sensual and earthly, which Philo calls sensibility (αἴσϑησις), and one toward the spiritual, which he calls reason (νοῦς).

Sensibility has its seat in the body, and lives in the senses. Sensibility, however, is in need of being guided by reason. Reason is that part of the spirit which looks toward heavenly things. It is the highest, the real divine gift that has been infused into man from without ("De Opiticio Mundi," i. 15; "De Eo Quod Deterius Potiori Insidiatur," i. 206). The νοῦς is originally at rest; when it begins to move it produces the several phenomena of mind (ἔνϑυμήματα). The principal powers of the νοῦς are judgment, memory, and language.

The physical body is a source of danger, as it easily drags the spirit into the bonds of sensibility. Sensibility is the source of the passions and desires; passions attack the sensibility in order to destroy the whole soul. According to Philo, man passes through several steps in his ethical development. At first the several elements of the human being are in a state of latency, a kind of moral neutrality which Philo designates by the terms "naked" or "medial." The soul has not decided either for sin or for virtue. In this period of moral indecision God endeavors to present to it, in the "earthly wisdom and virtue," an image of heavenly wisdom. Man quickly leaves this state of neutrality as soon as he experiences desire, and passion ensnares him in the bonds of sensibility. Here the moral duties of man arise and he must navigate between two opposite tendencies.

Philo interpreted the Jewish scriptures as an allegorical account of the rise and fall of the human soul. The soul was first aroused by the stimuli of sensual pleasures, became devoted to the body, and began to lead an intolerable life (βίος ἄβίωτος), inflamed and excited by irrational impulses. Its condition was restless and painful; a continual inner void produced a lasting desire which was never satisfied. All the higher aspirations after God and virtue were stilled, the entire soul was corrupt and ignorant, and the power of judgement was lost. Sensual things were valued above spiritual; and wealth was regarded as the highest good. Man in his folly even opposed God, and thought to scale heaven and subjugate the entire earth. The biblical patriarch Abraham was regarded by Philo as the symbol of man leaving sensuality to turn to reason ("De Migratione Abrahami." § 4 [i. 439]).

Philo elaborated three methods by which one can rise toward the divine: through education, through practice (ἄσκησις), and through natural goodness (ὁσιότης). Good moral endowment takes precedence over education and practice. Virtue was not the result of hard labor, but was an excellent fruit maturing of itself. The biblical character Noah represented the preliminary stage. Noah was called by God, apparently because of his good disposition, since no particularly good deeds were reported of him. As Noah was praised only in comparison with his contemporaries, it followed that he was not yet a perfect man.

Philo identified several characters in the Scriptures who represented the perfect man, such as the biblical patriarch Isaac. Perfection was a part of the nature (φύσις) of such persons; their souls were in a state of rest and joy. Philo’s concept of virtue resembled that of the Stoics, but he taught that man could not attain virtue through his own efforts, but only through religion, with the assistance of God.

The Garden of Eden was a symbol for "the wisdom of God," the “Logos of God’” and “virtue.” From it proceeded four rivers representing the cardinal virtues of prudence, courage, self-control, and justice (φρόνησις, ἀνδρία, σωφροσύνη, δικαιοσύνη).

See also

  • Philosophy
  • Philo's view of God
  • Philo's Works
  • Pseudo-Philo

External links

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.