Difference between revisions of "Panpsychism" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
(import from wiki)
 
 
(17 intermediate revisions by 6 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
 +
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{copyedited}}
 +
'''Panpsychism''' is the view that all of the fundamental entities in the universe possess some degree of mentality or consciousness, where this mentality or consciousness is not exhaustively explicable in terms of their physical properties.  The opposing position is often referred to as "[[emergentism]]," which asserts that mentality or consciousness is not a feature of everything, but rather only emerges (perhaps inexplicably) when certain non-mental entities are arranged in certain ways.  The chief motivation behind panpsychism is that it allows one to avoid the threat of just such an inexplicable emergence of mentality from the non-mental.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
The view has appeared numerous times in the history of philosophical thought, though often in radically differing forms.  Thinkers who have been counted as panpsychists (though almost never without controversy) include [[Thales]], [[Anaxagoras]], [[Girolamo Cardano]], [[Giordano Bruno]], [[Spinoza]], [[Leibniz]], [[Gustav Fechner]], and [[Josiah Royce]].  This article will focus on the core of the panpsychist position, by considering the line of thought that best supports it, and then by briefly considering what may be the clearest and most influential example of panpsychism as presented in the philosophy of Leibniz.
  
'''Panpsychism''', in [[philosophy]], is either the view that all parts of matter involve mind, or the more [[holism|holistic]] view that the whole universe is an organism that possesses a mind. It is thus a stronger and more ambitious view than [[hylozoism]], which holds only that all things are alive. This is not to say that panpsychism believes that all matter is alive or even conscious but rather that the constituent parts of matter are composed of some form of mind and are [[sentient]].
+
== Emergence and panpsychism ==
 +
Panpsychism, at least in its stronger forms, is not an intuitive position. People naturally think of much of the universe (rocks, light-waves, etc.) as different from themselves in a very fundamental way—namely, that living creatures have a [[mind]] and are conscious, and those other, inanimate things aren't. Such a division is at the root of many ethical views, as well. People tend to think that there is something much worse about stabbing an animal with a hot poker than there is about stabbing a rock or a machine (even a complex machine). The reason for that simply seems to be that animals, by virtue of having minds, have a ''capacity for pain'' that rocks and circuit boards simply lack.
  
Panpsychism claims that everything is sentient and that there are either many separate minds, or one single mind that unites everything that is. The concept of the [[Unconscious mind|unconscious]], made popular by the [[psychoanalysis|psychoanalysts]], made possible a variant of panpsychism that denies [[consciousness]] from some entities while still asserting the ubiquity of mind.  
+
Given this, it is natural to wonder what motivation panpsychism could possibly have that could weigh against such a well-entrenched intuitive position. The chief motivation becomes more clear when one reflects on the question of how it is that consciousness, or minds, could appear in the world.
  
== Relation to metaphysical positions ==
+
Consider the growth and development of an animal like a cow.  Typically, one believes that a full-grown cow is a conscious being, but that the individual reproductive cells of its parent-cows and the food they ingest are not conscious. Yet, sometime after the time when the reproductive cells establish physical contact, a conscious being seems to appear where none had been there before (note that this issue is distinct from the issue of ''life,'' since, intuitively, there are plenty of non-conscious living beings). In this way of describing things, an observer can say that consciousness emerges, where this means that a certain property comes into being where it had not existed before.
  
Panpsychism can be understood as a form of [[idealism]] - the [[metaphysics|metaphysical]] view that says the fundamental constituents of reality are mental (a view that holds that [[matter]] is dependent on [[minds]], or that only mental qualities exist- a type of substance [[monism]]).  
+
The emergence of some properties in the world is not so mysterious.  For instance, as a result of a certain political process, some entity might suddenly acquire the property of being Prime Minister, where it had not been Prime Minister before. The reason this does not seem mysterious is that anyone who understands what the property of being Prime Minister is will be able to see how it could have arisen from some combination of other properties (that is, the property of being a candidate, plus the property of being voted for by A, plus the property of being voted for by B, etc.). Such an understanding will allow someone to predict, with a great deal of precision and confidence, when (and where) the property of being Prime Minister will emerge.
  
[[Eliminative Materialism]], the view that there is no such thing as mind, but only matter- is incompatible with panpsychism. [[Materialism]] generally, the view that ultimately there is only matter, is compatible with panpsychism just in case the property of mindedness is attributed to matter.
+
But the same can't be said for the property of being conscious. Each human being seems to have some sort of grasp on what it is to be conscious, yet has no idea how such a property could emerge out of some combination of non-conscious [[cell]]s and [[molecule]]s. This lack of understanding is manifested in a complete inability to say, with any confidence, when it is in the development of an animal that consciousness emerges. The central point is that the property of consciousness just seems to be radically ''different'' from any physical property that, there's no way one can imagine how some combination of physical properties could produce it.
  
[[Hylopathism]] argues for just this attribution. Few writers would advocate a hylopathic materialism, although the idea is not new; it has been formulated as "whatever underlies consciousness in a material sense, i.e., whatever it is about the brain that gives rise to consciousness, must necessarily be present to some degree in any other material thing". This idea relies upon a [[noumenon|"thing in itself"]] in order to explain all phenomena (see [[hyle]]). Similar ideas have been formulated by philosopher [[David Chalmers]], in the form of the [[philosophical zombie]] thought experiment, of which a major criticism is that it can be demonstrated that the only properties shared by all [[qualia]] are that they are not precisely descriptible and thus are of [[indeterminate]] meaning within any philosophy which relies upon precise definition. This has been somewhat of a blow to panpsychism in general, since some of the same problems seem to be present in panpsychism in that it tends to presuppose a definition for mentality without describing it in any real detail. (What separates mental and non-mental phenomena?)
+
One response to this line of thought is to claim that an important part of the growth of an animal has been left out—namely, that at some point, its body comes to be inhabited by a special sort of entity, a [[soul]], and that this entity is what explains why the body comes to have consciousness.  On this view, consciousness never emerges at all, for, souls are always conscious.
  
However, there are also varieties of [[monism]] that don't presuppose (like materialism and idealism do) that mind and matter are fundamentally separable. An example is [[neutral monism]] first introduced by [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]] and later propounded by [[William James]]. Panpsychism can be combined with this view.
+
Of course, such a response requires the existence of souls, as entities distinct from matter and with patterns of motion (e.g. entering into bodies) that appear to resist scientific explanation. That makes the response unacceptable to those who either deny that any such non-physical things can exist (for example, [[Hobbes]]) or those who believe that, regardless of whether souls exist, they shouldn't be appealed to outside of religious contexts. Yet, even philosophers who were completely convinced of the existence of souls, and who appealed to their existence in scientific contexts (a good example being [[Leibniz]], discussed below) have found such a response unsatisfying in its mysterious appeal to floating souls.
  
== In the history of philosophy ==
+
The key thought behind panpsychism appears at this point. It is very hard to understand how consciousness could emerge out of non-conscious properties. But it's less hard to understand how more complex consciousnesses (e.g. a mind that's contemplating physics) could emerge out of less complex consciousnesses (e.g. individual thoughts about particular shapes and numbers). If that's right, then one way to avoid the problem of emergence without appeal to souls would be to claim that some degree of mentality is present in all matter in the universe.
  
The view of the world as a [[macrocosm]] in relation to man (which is a [[microcosm]], respectively) was a staple theme in Greek philosophy. In that view it was natural to think about the world in [[anthropomorphism|anthropomorphic]] terms. The view passed into the medieval period via [[Neoplatonism]], and became shared by [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]], [[Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph von Schelling|Schelling]], [[Arthur Schopenhauer|Schopenhauer]] and many others.  
+
== Leibniz ==
 +
The great German philosopher, mathematician, and scientist, Gottfriend Wilhelm [[Leibniz]] (1646-1716) was at the center of some of the brightest moments of the European [[Enlightenment]]. Of particular importance was his discovery of microorganisms, following the sixteenth century invention of the [[microscope]]. Many apparently lifeless substances, it turned out on closer reflection, turned out to be swarming with living entities.  Impressed by this and the line of thought described above, over the course of his career, Leibniz developed a systematic metaphysics centered on the idea of "[[monad]]s."  Monads were to be the building-blocks of reality. They were infinitely small (unextended, in fact) and yet all had conscious, perceptual states. Those conscious states were, in fact, confused representations of other monads. As monads entered into certain combinations (as ordained by God), their representations became less and less confused. On Leibniz's view, each human had a dominant monad, but that monad's conscious thoughts were perfectly correlated with the happenings in the other monads that composed its body (one of the more mature expositions of these thoughts is Leibniz's 1714 ''Monadology'').
  
Idea of "animated atom" in [[Russian cosmism]] in the early 20th century.
+
To put matters somewhat metaphorically, Leibniz understood mentality to be more fundamental to reality than physicality.  Part of his motivations for this came from his concerns about what sort of entity even could be basic (in short: Only a simple one, and the only simple thing is a mind).  To Leibniz's mind, the suggestion that mentality could emerge from something non-mental was incoherent because it was the exact opposite of the truth.  
  
[[Josiah Royce]] (1855-1916), the leading American absolute idealist, held to the panpsychist view, though he didn't necessarily attribute mental properties to the smallest constituents of mentalistic "systems".  
+
Though sympathetic with much of Leibniz's system, in his ''Critique of Pure Reason,'' [[Kant]] charged that Leibniz had posited mentality as the inner nature of substances because of his inability to conceive of any alternative for inner natures (see the ''Amphiboly of Reflection''). Kant thought that it was possible that Leibniz was right, but that if so, it would have merely been a lucky guess, for Kant held that people are unable, in principle, to know anything about the inner natures of [[substance]]s.
  
The panpsychist doctrine has recently been making some kind of a comeback in the American [[philosophy of mind]] — for example, [[David Chalmers]], [[Christian de Quincey]] and [[Leo Stubenberg]] have each recently defended it. In the philosophy of mind, panpsychism is one possible solution to the so-called [[hard problem of consciousness]]. The doctrine has also been applied in the field of environmental philosophy through the work of Australian philosopher, [[Freya Mathews]].
+
== References ==
 
+
* Clark, D. 2004. ''Panpsychism: Past and Recent (Selected Readings).'' Albany: SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0791461310
== In the psychoanalytic tradition ==
+
* Fechner, D. 1946. ''The Religion of a Scientist'' (selections of Fechner's writing in English translation), W. Lowrie, ed., trans. New York: Pantheon.
 
+
* Kant, I.  (1781) 1999.  ''Critique of Pure Reason.'' P. Guyer and A. Wood, eds. and trans.  Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.  ISBN 0521657296 
[[Carl Jung]], who is maybe best known for his idea of [[collective unconscious]], wrote that "psyche and matter are contained in one and the same world, and moreover are in continuous contact with one another", and that it was probable that "psyche and matter are two different aspects of one and the same thing". (orig. source unknown, cited in [[Danah Zohar]] & Ian Marshall, SQ: Connecting with our Spiritual Intelligence, Bloomsbury, 2000, p. 81). This could be interpreted as panpsychism, apparently of the [[neutral monism]] variety.
+
* Leibniz, G. (1714) 1989. ''Monadology,'' in ''G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Essays,'' R. Ariew and D. Garber, eds. and trans. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
 
+
* Royce, J. 1901. ''The World and the Individual.'' New York: Macmillan. ISBN 978-0766102248 
== Other manifestations ==
+
* Skrbina, D. 2005. ''Panpsychism in the West.'' Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2007.  ISBN 0262693518
 
+
* Spinoza, B. (1677) 1985. ''Ethics,'' in ''The Collected Works of Spinoza (Volume I),'' E. Curley, ed. and trans. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691072221   
Panpsychism and [[emergentism]] can be seen as alternative ways to bridge the more extreme positions of crude [[reductionism]] and crude [[holism]]. Panpsychism differs from emergentism in that according to panpsychism, even the smallest physical particles have mental characteristics. Emergentism claims that though the particles be mindless, some [[systems]] formed by them, and by nothing but them, ''do'' possess mental attributes. The human brain is a case in point.  
+
* Sprigge, T.L.S. 1998. "Panpsychism," in E. Craig (Ed.), ''Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.'' London: Routledge.
 
 
[[Gaia theory]], which views the [[biosphere]] as a [[self-regulation|self-regulating]] [[system]], that maintains [[homeostasis]] in relation to many vital chemical and physical variables, is sometimes interpreted as panpsychism, because some think that any goal-directed behavior qualifies as mental. However, the goal-directed behavior of the biosphere, as explained by the [[Gaia theory]], is an emergent function of ''organised, living'' matter, not a quality of ''any'' matter. Thus [[Gaia theory]] is more properly associated with [[emergentism]] than panpsychism.
 
 
 
The label "naive" (vs. "philosophical") panpsychism is sometimes used to mean, not a doctrine defended by any philosopher, but the attitude of primal people and children to think of even inanimate objects as sentient and/or [[intention|intentional]]. This is the same as [[animism]].
 
 
 
Panpsychism, as a view that the universe has "universal consciousness", is shared by some forms of religious thought: [[theosophy]], [[pantheism]], [[panentheism]], and [[cosmotheism]].
 
 
 
'''Panexperientialism''' or '''panprotopsychism''' are related concepts.
 
[[Alfred North Whitehead]] incorporated a scientific worldview into the development of his philosophical system similar to [[Albert Einstein|Einstein]]’s [[Theory of Relativity]]. His ideas were a significant development of the idea of panpsychism, also known as panexperientialism, due to Whitehead’s emphasis on experience. [[Process philosophy]] suggests that fundamental elements of the universe are occasions of experience, which can be collected into groups creating something as complex as a human being. This experience is not consciousness; there is no mind-body duality under this system as mind is seen as a very developed kind of experience. Whitehead was not a subjective idealist and, while his philosophy resembles the concept of [[monad]]s first proposed by Leibniz, Whitehead’s occasions of experience are interrelated with every other occasion of experience that has ever occurred. He embraced panentheism with God encompassing all occasions of experience, transcending them. Whitehead believed that the occasions of experience are the smallest element in the universe—even smaller than subatomic particles.
 
 
 
== See also ==
 
*[[Animism]]
 
*[[Hylozoism]]
 
*[[Pantheism]]
 
*[[Solipsism]]
 
*[[Philosophy of Mind]]
 
  
 
== External links ==
 
== External links ==
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Panpsychism]
+
All links retrieved November 18, 2022.
*[http://ucadia.org/uca/u04/040000.htm The concept of existence and awareness]: Ucadia.Org
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/panpsychism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Panpsychism].
*[http://newadvent.org/cathen/11446a.htm The Catholic Encyclopedia - Panpsychism]
+
===General philosophy sources===
*[http://www.consciousentities.com/deadends.htm#panpsychism consciousentities.com - Philosophical Deadends - Panpsychism]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].  
*[http://jamaica.u.arizona.edu/~chalmers/biblio/1.html#1.4g Bibliography on Panpsychism] compiled by [[David Chalmers]]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
*[http://www.panpsychism.net panpsychism.net]
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].  
 
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].  
[[Category:Philosophy of mind]]
 
 
 
[[ja:汎心論]]
 
[[ru:Панпсихизм]]
 
[[fi:Panpsykismi]]
 
[[de:Panpsychismus]]
 
 
 
  
 +
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 +
[[Category:philosophy]]
  
 
{{Credit|101252256}}
 
{{Credit|101252256}}

Latest revision as of 06:37, 18 November 2022

Panpsychism is the view that all of the fundamental entities in the universe possess some degree of mentality or consciousness, where this mentality or consciousness is not exhaustively explicable in terms of their physical properties. The opposing position is often referred to as "emergentism," which asserts that mentality or consciousness is not a feature of everything, but rather only emerges (perhaps inexplicably) when certain non-mental entities are arranged in certain ways. The chief motivation behind panpsychism is that it allows one to avoid the threat of just such an inexplicable emergence of mentality from the non-mental.

The view has appeared numerous times in the history of philosophical thought, though often in radically differing forms. Thinkers who have been counted as panpsychists (though almost never without controversy) include Thales, Anaxagoras, Girolamo Cardano, Giordano Bruno, Spinoza, Leibniz, Gustav Fechner, and Josiah Royce. This article will focus on the core of the panpsychist position, by considering the line of thought that best supports it, and then by briefly considering what may be the clearest and most influential example of panpsychism as presented in the philosophy of Leibniz.

Emergence and panpsychism

Panpsychism, at least in its stronger forms, is not an intuitive position. People naturally think of much of the universe (rocks, light-waves, etc.) as different from themselves in a very fundamental way—namely, that living creatures have a mind and are conscious, and those other, inanimate things aren't. Such a division is at the root of many ethical views, as well. People tend to think that there is something much worse about stabbing an animal with a hot poker than there is about stabbing a rock or a machine (even a complex machine). The reason for that simply seems to be that animals, by virtue of having minds, have a capacity for pain that rocks and circuit boards simply lack.

Given this, it is natural to wonder what motivation panpsychism could possibly have that could weigh against such a well-entrenched intuitive position. The chief motivation becomes more clear when one reflects on the question of how it is that consciousness, or minds, could appear in the world.

Consider the growth and development of an animal like a cow. Typically, one believes that a full-grown cow is a conscious being, but that the individual reproductive cells of its parent-cows and the food they ingest are not conscious. Yet, sometime after the time when the reproductive cells establish physical contact, a conscious being seems to appear where none had been there before (note that this issue is distinct from the issue of life, since, intuitively, there are plenty of non-conscious living beings). In this way of describing things, an observer can say that consciousness emerges, where this means that a certain property comes into being where it had not existed before.

The emergence of some properties in the world is not so mysterious. For instance, as a result of a certain political process, some entity might suddenly acquire the property of being Prime Minister, where it had not been Prime Minister before. The reason this does not seem mysterious is that anyone who understands what the property of being Prime Minister is will be able to see how it could have arisen from some combination of other properties (that is, the property of being a candidate, plus the property of being voted for by A, plus the property of being voted for by B, etc.). Such an understanding will allow someone to predict, with a great deal of precision and confidence, when (and where) the property of being Prime Minister will emerge.

But the same can't be said for the property of being conscious. Each human being seems to have some sort of grasp on what it is to be conscious, yet has no idea how such a property could emerge out of some combination of non-conscious cells and molecules. This lack of understanding is manifested in a complete inability to say, with any confidence, when it is in the development of an animal that consciousness emerges. The central point is that the property of consciousness just seems to be radically different from any physical property that, there's no way one can imagine how some combination of physical properties could produce it.

One response to this line of thought is to claim that an important part of the growth of an animal has been left out—namely, that at some point, its body comes to be inhabited by a special sort of entity, a soul, and that this entity is what explains why the body comes to have consciousness. On this view, consciousness never emerges at all, for, souls are always conscious.

Of course, such a response requires the existence of souls, as entities distinct from matter and with patterns of motion (e.g. entering into bodies) that appear to resist scientific explanation. That makes the response unacceptable to those who either deny that any such non-physical things can exist (for example, Hobbes) or those who believe that, regardless of whether souls exist, they shouldn't be appealed to outside of religious contexts. Yet, even philosophers who were completely convinced of the existence of souls, and who appealed to their existence in scientific contexts (a good example being Leibniz, discussed below) have found such a response unsatisfying in its mysterious appeal to floating souls.

The key thought behind panpsychism appears at this point. It is very hard to understand how consciousness could emerge out of non-conscious properties. But it's less hard to understand how more complex consciousnesses (e.g. a mind that's contemplating physics) could emerge out of less complex consciousnesses (e.g. individual thoughts about particular shapes and numbers). If that's right, then one way to avoid the problem of emergence without appeal to souls would be to claim that some degree of mentality is present in all matter in the universe.

Leibniz

The great German philosopher, mathematician, and scientist, Gottfriend Wilhelm Leibniz (1646-1716) was at the center of some of the brightest moments of the European Enlightenment. Of particular importance was his discovery of microorganisms, following the sixteenth century invention of the microscope. Many apparently lifeless substances, it turned out on closer reflection, turned out to be swarming with living entities. Impressed by this and the line of thought described above, over the course of his career, Leibniz developed a systematic metaphysics centered on the idea of "monads." Monads were to be the building-blocks of reality. They were infinitely small (unextended, in fact) and yet all had conscious, perceptual states. Those conscious states were, in fact, confused representations of other monads. As monads entered into certain combinations (as ordained by God), their representations became less and less confused. On Leibniz's view, each human had a dominant monad, but that monad's conscious thoughts were perfectly correlated with the happenings in the other monads that composed its body (one of the more mature expositions of these thoughts is Leibniz's 1714 Monadology).

To put matters somewhat metaphorically, Leibniz understood mentality to be more fundamental to reality than physicality. Part of his motivations for this came from his concerns about what sort of entity even could be basic (in short: Only a simple one, and the only simple thing is a mind). To Leibniz's mind, the suggestion that mentality could emerge from something non-mental was incoherent because it was the exact opposite of the truth.

Though sympathetic with much of Leibniz's system, in his Critique of Pure Reason, Kant charged that Leibniz had posited mentality as the inner nature of substances because of his inability to conceive of any alternative for inner natures (see the Amphiboly of Reflection). Kant thought that it was possible that Leibniz was right, but that if so, it would have merely been a lucky guess, for Kant held that people are unable, in principle, to know anything about the inner natures of substances.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Clark, D. 2004. Panpsychism: Past and Recent (Selected Readings). Albany: SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0791461310
  • Fechner, D. 1946. The Religion of a Scientist (selections of Fechner's writing in English translation), W. Lowrie, ed., trans. New York: Pantheon.
  • Kant, I. (1781) 1999. Critique of Pure Reason. P. Guyer and A. Wood, eds. and trans. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521657296
  • Leibniz, G. (1714) 1989. Monadology, in G. W. Leibniz: Philosophical Essays, R. Ariew and D. Garber, eds. and trans. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.
  • Royce, J. 1901. The World and the Individual. New York: Macmillan. ISBN 978-0766102248
  • Skrbina, D. 2005. Panpsychism in the West. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2007. ISBN 0262693518
  • Spinoza, B. (1677) 1985. Ethics, in The Collected Works of Spinoza (Volume I), E. Curley, ed. and trans. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0691072221
  • Sprigge, T.L.S. 1998. "Panpsychism," in E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London: Routledge.

External links

All links retrieved November 18, 2022.

General philosophy sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.