Difference between revisions of "Neoclassical economics" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
(updated)
Line 2: Line 2:
 
[[Category:Economics]]
 
[[Category:Economics]]
  
{{ History of economic thought}}
+
'''Neoclassical economics''' refers to a general approach in [[economics]] focusing on the determination of prices, outputs, and income [[distribution (economics)|distribution]]s in markets through [[supply and demand]]. These are mediated through a hypothesized maximization of income-constrained [[utility]] by individuals and of cost-constrained [[profits]] of firms employing available information and factors of production.  [[Mainstream economics|Mainstream]] economics is largely neoclassical in its assumptions, at least at the [[microeconomics|microeconomic]] level.
  
'''Neoclassical economics''' refers to a general approach in [[economics]] focusing on the determination of prices, outputs, and income [[distribution (economics)|distribution]]s in markets through [[supply and demand]]. These are mediated through a hypothesized maximization of income-constrained [[utility]] by individuals and of cost-constrained [[profits]] of firms employing available information and factors of production.<ref>Antonietta Campus (1987), "marginal economics,"  ''The [[New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics]]'', v. 3, p. 323.</ref>  [[Mainstream economics|Mainstream]] economics is largely neoclassical in its assumptions, at least at the [[microeconomics|microeconomic]] level.<ref name="TomGreen07">{{cite web |url=http://adbusters.org/the_magazine/69/The_Revolution_Will_Begin_with_a_Textbook_Part_Two.html |title=Adbusters : The Magazine - #69 The Big Ideas of 2007 / The Revolution Will Begin with a Textbook (Part Two) |accessdate=2007-06-29 |format= |work=}}</ref> There have been many critiques of neoclassical economics, often incorporated into newer versions of neoclassical theory as human awareness of economic criteria change. Neoclassical economics is often called the [[marginalism|marginalist]] school, although the [[Austrian School]] founded by [[Carl Menger]] is also sometimes called the marginalist school.<ref>Eds. Lysons JS, Cain LP, Williamson SH. (2008). ''Reflections on the Cliometrics Revolution''. Routledge. p 6, quote: "and the "Austrian" marginalist school of Carl Menger"</ref> 
 
  
The term was originally introduced by [[Thorstein Veblen]] in 1900, in his ''Preconceptions of Economic Science''.<ref name=Colander/> It was then used by [[George Stigler]] and [[John Hicks]] broadly to include the work of [[Carl Menger]], [[William Stanley Jevons]], and [[John Bates Clark]].<ref name=Colander>Colander, David. The Death of Neoclassical Economics.</ref> Today it is often used to refer to mainstream economics and the [[Chicago school of economists|Chicago school]], although it has been used as an [[umbrella term]] encompassing a number of mainly defunct [[school of thought|schools of thought]],<ref>Fonseca GL. [http://cepa.newschool.edu/~het/essays/margrev/ncintro.htm Introduction to the Neoclassicals] The New School.</ref>
+
President Richard Nixon, defending deficit spending against the conservative charge that it was "Keynesian," is reported to have replied, "…We're all Keynesians now…..." In fact, what he should have said is "….We're all neoclassicals now, even the Keynesians…..," because what is taught to students, what is mainstream economics today, is neoclassical economics ( E. R. Weintraub, 1985.)
notably excluding [[institutional economics]], various [[historical school of economics|historical schools of economics]], and [[Marxian economics]], in addition to various other [[heterodox economics]].
 
  
== Overview ==
 
Neoclassical economics is the singular element several schools of thought in [[economics]] address. There is not a complete agreement on what is meant by neoclassical economics, and the result is a wide range of neoclassical approaches to various problem areas and domains—ranging from neoclassical theories of labor to neoclassical theories of demographic changes.
 
As expressed by [[E. Roy Weintraub]], neoclassical economics rests on three assumptions, although certain branches of neoclassical theory may have different approaches:
 
#People have [[Rational choice theory|rational preferences]] among outcomes that can be identified and associated with a value.
 
#Individuals [[utility maximization|maximize utility]] and firms [[profit maximization|maximize profits]].
 
#People act independently on the basis of [[information asymmetry|full and relevant information]].
 
  
From these three assumptions, neoclassical economists have built a structure to understand the allocation of scarce resources among alternative ends—in fact understanding such allocation is often considered the definition of economics to neoclassical theorists. Here's how [[William Stanley Jevons]] presented "the problem of Economics."
+
==History of neoclassical economics==
  
<blockquote>"Given, a certain population, with various needs and powers of production, in possession of certain lands and other sources of material: required, the mode of employing their labour which will maximize the utility of their produce."<ref>[[William Stanley Jevons]] (1879, 2nd ed., p. 289), ''The Theory of Political Economy''. Italics in original.</ref></blockquote>
 
  
From the basic assumptions of neoclassical economics comes a wide range of theories about various areas of economic activity. For example, profit maximization lies behind the neoclassical [[theory of the firm]], while the derivation of [[demand]] curves leads to an understanding of [[consumer good]]s, and the [[supply]] curve allows an analysis of the [[factors of production]]. Utility maximization is the source for the neoclassical theory of consumption, the derivation of demand curves for consumer goods, and the derivation of labor supply curves and [[reservation price|reservation demand]]<ref>[[Philip H. Wicksteed]] ''The Common Sense of Political Economy''</ref>. Market [[supply and demand]] are aggregated across firms and individuals. Their interactions determine equilibrium output and price. The market supply and demand for each factor of production is derived analogously to those for market [http://bea.gov/bea/glossary/glossary.cfm?key_word=Final_use&letter=F#Final_use final output] to determine equilibrium income and the income distribution. Factor demand incorporates the [[Production, costs, and pricing|marginal-productivity]] relationship of that factor in the output market.
+
[[Classical economics]], developed in the 18th and 19th centuries, included a [[value theory]] and [[Distribution (economics)|distribution]] theory. The value of a product was thought to depend on the costs involved in producing that product. The explanation of costs in Classical economics was simultaneously an explanation of distribution. A landlord received rent, workers received wages, and a capitalist tenant farmer received profits on their investment. This classic approach included the work of [[Adam Smith]] and [[David Ricardo]].
<ref>Christopher Bliss (1987), "distribution theories, neoclassical," ''The New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics'',
+
 
v. 1, pp. 883-886.</ref>
+
 
<ref>Robert F. Dorfman (1987), "marginal productivity theory,"  ''The [[New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics]]'',
+
By the middle of the nineteenth century, English-speaking economists generally shared a perspective on value theory and distribution theory. The value of a bushel of corn, for example, was thought to depend on the costs involved in producing that bushel. The output or product of an economy was thought to be divided or distributed among the different social groups in accord with the costs borne by those groups in producing the output. This, roughly, was the "Classical Theory" developed by [[Adam Smith]], [[David Ricardo]], [[Thomas Robert Malthus]], [[John Stuart Mill]], and[[ Karl Marx]].
v. 3, pp. 323-25.</ref><ref>[[George J. Stigler]] (1941). ''Production and Distribution Theories''(1870-1895). New York: Macmillan.</ref> 
+
 
 +
 +
But there were difficulties in this approach. Chief among them was that prices in the market did not necessarily reflect the "value" so defined, for people were often willing to pay more than an object was "worth." The classical "substance" theories of value, which took value to be a property inherent in an object, gradually gave way to a perspective in which value was associated with the relationship between the object and the person obtaining the object.
 +
 +
Several economists in different places at about the same time (the 1870s and 1880s) began to base value on the relationship between costs of production and "subjective elements," later called "supply" and "demand." This came to be known as the Marginal Revolution in economics, and the overarching theory that developed from these ideas came to be called neoclassical economics. The first to use the term "neoclassical economics" seems to have been the American economist [[Thorstein Veblen]] ( see T. Veblen, 1900.)
 +
 +
It was then used by [[George Stigler]] and [[John Hicks]] broadly to include the work of [[Carl Menger]], [[William Stanley Jevons]], and [[John Bates Clark]].  Today it is often used to refer to mainstream economics and the [[Chicago school of economists|Chicago school]].
 +
Neoclassical economists usually assume, in other words, that human beings make the choices that give them the best possible advantage, given the circumstances they face. Circumstances include the prices of resources, goods and services, limited income, limited technology for transforming resources into goods and services, and taxes, regulations, and similar objective limitations on the choices they may make ( see E.R. Weintraub, 1985. )
 +
 
 +
 
 +
=== Overview and Assumptions===
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The framework of neoclassical economics is easily summarized. Buyers attempt to maximize their gains from getting goods, and they do this by increasing their purchases of a good until what they gain from an extra unit is just balanced by what they have to give up to obtain it. In this way they maximize "utility"—the satisfaction associated with the consumption of goods and services.  
 +
Likewise, individuals provide labor to firms that wish to employ them, by balancing the gains from offering the marginal unit of their services (the wage they would receive) with the disutility of labor itself—the loss of leisure. Individuals make choices at the margin. This results in a theory of demand for goods, and supply of productive factors.
 +
 
 +
Similarly, producers attempt to produce units of a good so that the cost of producing the incremental or marginal unit is just balanced by the revenue it generates. In this way they maximize profits. Firms also hire employees up to the point that the cost of the additional hire is just balanced by the value of output that the additional employee would produce.
 +
 
 +
 +
Neoclassical economics conceptualized the agents, households and firms, as rational actors. Agents were modeled as optimizers who were led to "better" outcomes. The resulting equilibrium was "best" in the sense that any other allocation of goods and services would leave someone worse off. Thus, the social system in the neoclassical vision was free of unresolvable conflict.  
  
Neoclassical economics emphasizes equilibria, where equilibria are the solutions of [[agent (economics)|agent]] maximization problems. Regularities in economies are explained by [[methodological individualism]], the position that economic phenomena can be explained by aggregating over the behavior of agents. The emphasis is on [[microeconomics]]. Institutions, which might be considered as prior to and conditioning individual behavior, are de-emphasized. [[Economic subjectivism]] accompanies these emphases. See also [[general equilibrium]].
+
The very term "social system" is a measure of the success of neoclassical economics, for the idea of a system, with its interacting components, its variables and parameters and constraints, is the language of mid-nineteenth-century physics. This field of rational mechanics was the model for the neoclassical framework. The following excerpt  clears many misunderstanding:
  
== Origins ==<!-- This section is linked from [[Labor theory of value]] —>
 
[[Classical economics]], developed in the 18th and 19th centuries, included a [[value theory]] and [[Distribution (economics)|distribution]] theory. The value of a product was thought to depend on the costs involved in producing that product. The explanation of costs in Classical economics was simultaneously an explanation of distribution. A landlord received rent, workers received wages, and a capitalist tenant farmer received profits on their investment. This classic approach included the work of [[Adam Smith]] and [[David Ricardo]].
 
  
However, some economists gradually began emphasizing the perceived value of a goods to the consumer. They proposed a theory that the value of a product was to be explained with differences in "utility." This is called [[Utilitarianism]] and is associated with philosopher and economic thinker [[John Stuart Mill]].
+
“…..''We understand that the allocation of resources is a social problem in any modern economy. Any modern economic system must somehow answer the questions posed by the allocation of resources. If we are further to understand the way in which people respond to this social problem, we have to make some assumptions about human behavior…….. The assumption at the basis of the neoclassical approach is that people are rational and (more of less) self-interested. This should be understood as an instance of positive economics (about what is) not normative economics (about what ought to be). This distinction, positive versus normative economics, is important in itself and is a key to understanding many aspects of economics''…..” ( B. Huberman and T. Hogg, 1995.)
 +
 
 +
 
 +
Agents, mentioned above, were like atoms; utility was like energy; utility maximization was like the minimization of potential energy, and so forth. In this way was the rhetoric of successful science linked to the neoclassical theory, and in this way economics became linked to science itself. Whether this linkage was planned by the early Marginalists, or rather was a feature of the public success of science itself, is less important than the implications of that linkage. For once neoclassical economics was associated with scientific economics, to challenge the neoclassical approach was to seem to challenge science and progress and modernity. These developments were accompanied by the introduction of new tools, such as [[indifference curve]]s and the theory of ordinal [[utility]]. The level of mathematical sophistication of neoclassical economics increased. [[Paul Samuelson]]'s ''[[Foundations of Economic Analysis]]'' (1947) contributed to this increase in [[formal rigor]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
Value is linked to unlimited desires and wants colliding with constraints, or scarcity. The tensions, the decision problems, are worked out in markets. Prices are the signals that tell households and firms whether their conflicting desires can be reconciled.
 +
 
 +
'''EXAMPLE''': At some price of cars, for example, I want to buy a new car. At that same price others may also want to buy cars. But manufacturers may not want to produce as many cars as we all want. Our frustration may lead us to "bid up" the price of cars, eliminating some potential buyers and encouraging some marginal producers. As the price changes, the imbalance between buy orders and sell orders is reduced. This is how optimization under constraint and market interdependence lead to an economic equilibrium. This is the neoclassical vision ( ibid.)
 +
 
 +
 
 +
To summarize: Neoclassical economics is what is called a metatheory. That is, it is a set of implicit rules or understandings for constructing satisfactory economic theories. It is a scientific research program that generates economic theories. Its fundamental assumptions are not open to discussion in that they define the shared understandings of those who call themselves neoclassical economists, or economists without any adjective. Those fundamental assumptions include the following:
 +
 
 +
 
 +
*People have [[Rational choice theory|rational preferences]] among outcomes that can be identified and associated with a value.
 +
 +
*Individuals [[utility maximization|maximize utility]] and firms [[profit maximization|maximize profits]].
 +
 +
*People act independently on the basis of [[information asymmetry|full and relevant information]].
 +
 
 +
 
 +
Theories based on, or guided by, these assumptions are neoclassical theories.
 +
Thus, we can speak of a neoclassical theory of profits, or employment, or growth, or money. We can create neoclassical production relationships between inputs and outputs, or neoclassical theories of marriage and divorce and the spacing of births. Consider layoffs, for example. A theory which assumes that a firm's layoff decisions are based on a balance between the benefits of laying off an additional worker and the costs associated with that action will be a neoclassical theory. A theory that explains the layoff decision by the changing tastes of managers for employees with particular characteristics will not be a neoclassical theory ( ibid.)
 +
 
 +
 +
The value of neoclassical economics can be assessed in the collection of truths to which we are led by its light. The kinds of truths about incentives—about prices and information, about the interrelatedness of decisions and the unintended consequences of choices—are all well developed in neoclassical theories, as is a self-consciousness about the use of evidence.
 +
 
 +
'''EXAMPLE''':  In planning for future electricity needs in my state, for example, the Public Utilities Commission develops a (neoclassical) demand forecast, joins it to a (neoclassical) cost analysis of generation facilities of various sizes and types (e.g., an 800-megawatt low-sulfur coal plant), and develops a least-cost system growth plan and a (neoclassical) pricing strategy for implementing that plan. Those on all sides of the issues, from industry to municipalities, from electric companies to environmental groups, all speak the same language of demand elasticities and cost minimization, of marginal costs and rates of return.
 +
The rules of theory development and assessment are clear in neoclassical economics, and that clarity is taken to be beneficial to the community of economists. The scientificness of neoclassical economics, on this view, is not its weakness but its strength ( ibid. )
 +
 
 +
 
 +
==Critique of  neoclassical economics==
 +
 
 +
 
 +
The ''rational'' consumer of the mainstream economist is a working assumption that was meant to free economists from dependence on psychology (e.g. Tversky and Kahneman 1986.)
 +
 +
The dilemma is that the assumption of rationality as intertemporally optimising is often confused with, and regularly presented as, real, purposive behaviour. In fact, the living consumer in historical time routinely makes decisions in undefined contexts. They muddle through, they adapt, they copy, they try what worked in the past, they gamble, they take uncalculated risks, they engage in costly altruistic activities, and regularly make unpredictable, even unexplainable, decisions (Sandven 1995).
 +
 
 +
 +
It mostly looks like that modern corporations are not even "acting as if" they equilibrate marginal cost-marginal revenue to maximise profits. Rather, they attempt to ''beat the average''. References to the "average" or "normal" pervade the business literature - from the analysis of stock performance, through the stacking of country growth rates and risk premia, to the ranking of corporate profitability.
 +
 
 +
In these terms, according to Nitzan and Bichler, the primary goal becomes "differential pecuniary accumulation", through which the corporation seeks to control a "larger share of the societal surplus". Consequently, success has less to do with the intuitively convincing textbook equality between marginal cost and marginal revenue, than with the capture of external contested income, thereby redistributing the available social surplus ( H. Thompson, 1997.)
 +
 
 +
 +
One neoclassical defence is to suggest that equilibrium is only a tendency towards which the system is moving. However, Weintraub (1991) reveals the manner whereby econometricians, such as Negishi, maintain that the equilibrium contained in a model is real and intuitively justified.
 +
 
 +
They do this by appealing to the "…..''reality out there…in which it is known that the economy is fairly shock-proof….We know from experience that prices usually do not explode to infinity or contract to zero''…" (Negishi, 1962.)
 +
 
 +
Neoclassical economics has represented, for two hundred years, the political self-representation of autonomous, self-subsistent, and self-interest-optimising individuals.
 +
 
 +
And no matter how hard neoclassical economists try to drive away the world of complexity, it too continues to confront them. Yet, to the frustration of "heterogeneous" antagonists the neoclassical paradigm remains dominant, blatantly promoting ignorance-squared. Elegance and technique have replaced relevance. What has been shown herein is that the production of that elegance has involved the opportunity cost of simultaneously producing ignorance. Ignorance-squared is replicated amongst students given the social interests of those dominant in the paradigm ( H. Thompson, 1997. )
 +
 
  
The third step from political economy to economics was the introduction of the "marginal theory of value" or [[marginalism]]. Marginal value means that economic actors make decisions based on the "margins." For example, a person decides to buy a second sandwich based on how full they are after the first one, a firm hires a new employee based on the expected increase in profits the employee will bring. This differs from the aggregate decision making of classical political economy in that it explains how vital goods such as water can be cheap, while luxuries can be expensive.
+
==Three axioms of the modern neoclassical economics: an answer to the critique==
  
Neoclassical economics is conventionally dated from [[William Stanley Jevons]]'s ''Theory of Political Economy'' (1871), [[Carl Menger]]'s ''Principles of Economics'' (1871), and [[Leon Walras]]'s ''Elements of Pure Economics'' (1874 &ndash; 1877). These three economists have been said to have promulgated the marginal utility revolution, or [[Neoclassical Revolution]]. Historians of economics and economists  have debated:
 
  
* Whether [[utility]] or marginalism was more essential to this revolution (whether the noun or the adjective in the phrase "marginal utility" is more important)
+
Neoclassical theory retains its roots firmly within liberal individualist social science. The method is still unbendingly of the analytic-synthetic type: the socio-economic phenomenon under scrutiny is to be analysed by focusing on the individuals whose actions brought it about; understanding fully their ‘workings’ at the individual level; and, finally, synthesising the knowledge derived at the individual level in order to understand the complex social phenomenon at hand. In short, neoclassical theory follows the watchmaker’s method who, faced with a strange watch, studies its function by focusing on understanding, initially, the function of each of its cogs and wheels. To the neoclassical economist, the latter are the individual agents who are to be studied, like the watchmaker’ cogs and  wheels, independently of the social whole their actions help bring about (Y. Varoufakis and Ch. Arnsperger, 2006.)
  
* Whether there was a revolutionary change of thought or merely a gradual development and change of emphasis from their predecessors
 
  
* Whether grouping these economists together disguises differences more important than their similarities<ref>William Jaff&eacute; (1976) "Menger, Jevons, and Walras De-Homogenized," ''Economic Inquiry'', V. 14 (December): 511-525</ref>.
+
===Methodological individualism===
  
In particular, Walras was more interested in the interaction of markets than in explaining the individual psyche through a hedonistic psychology. Jevons saw his economics as an application and development of [[Jeremy Bentham]]'s utilitarianism and never had a fully developed [[general equilibrium]] theory. Menger emphasized disequilibrium and the discrete. Menger had a philosophical objection to the use of mathematics in economics, while the other two modeled their theories after 19th century mechanics<ref>Philip Mirowski (1989) ''More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as Nature's Economics'', Cambridge University Press</ref>.
+
So, ''the first feature of the body of theory'' we think of as neoclassical is its methodological individualism: the idea that socio-economic explanation must be sought at the level of the individual agent. Note two things: First, this was not the method of classical economists like Adam Smith and David Ricardo. Or, indeed, of Keynes or Hayek.
  
[[Alfred Marshall]]'s textbook, ''Principles of Economics'' (1890), was the dominant textbook in England a generation later. Marshall's influence extended elsewhere; Italians would compliment [[Maffeo Pantaleoni]] by calling him the "Marshall of Italy." Marshall thought [[classical economics]] attempted to explain prices by the [[cost of production theory of value|cost of production]]. He asserted that the neoclassicals went too far in correcting this imbalance by overemphasizing utility and demand. Marshall thought the question of whether supply or demand was more important was analogous to the pointless question of which blade of a scissors did the cutting.
+
It is, we think, indisputable that all the new manifestations of what we term neoclassicism still subscribe to methodological individualism. While it is true that mainstream economists have, during the last few decades, acknowledged that the agent is a creature of his social context, and thus that social structure and individual agency are messily intertwined, their models retain the distinction and place the burden of explanation on the individual. Individual worker effort is nowadays often modelled as a function of sectoral unemployment (e.g. efficiency wage models), and the firms’ micro-strategies reflect the macroeconomic environment. Nevertheless, and despite these interesting linkages between the micro-agent and the macro-phenomenon, the explanatory trajectory remains one that begins from the agent and maps, unidirectionally, onto the social structure ( ibid. )
  
Marshall explained prices by the intersection of supply and demand curves. The introduction of different market "periods" was an important innovation of Marshall's:
 
*Market period. The goods produced for sale on the market are taken as given data, e.g. in a fish market. Prices quickly adjust to clear markets.
 
*Short period. Industrial capacity is taken as given. The level of output, the level of employment, the inputs of raw materials, and prices fluctuate to equate [[marginal cost]] and [[marginal revenue]], where profits are maximized. [[Economic rent]]s exist in short period equilibrium for fixed factors, and the rate of profit is not equated across sectors.
 
*Long period. The stock of [[capital (economics)|capital]] goods, such as factories and machines, is not taken as given. Profit-maximizing equilibria determine both industrial capacity and the level at which it is operated.
 
*Very long period. Technology, population trends, habits and customs are not taken as given, but allowed to vary in very long period models.
 
  
Marshall took supply and demand as stable functions and extended supply and demand explanations of prices to all runs. He argued supply was easier to vary in longer runs, and thus became a more important determinate of price in the very long run.
+
=== Methodological instrumentalism===
  
== Further developments ==
+
We label ''the second feature of neoclassical economics methodological instrumentalism'': all behaviour is preference-driven or, more precisely, it is to be understood as a means for maximising preference-satisfaction.
An important change in neoclassical economics occurred around 1933. [[Joan Robinson]] and [[Edward H. Chamberlin]], with the near simultaneous publication of their respective books, ''The Economics of Imperfect Competition'' (1933) and ''The Theory of Monopolistic Competition'' (1933), introduced models of [[imperfect competition]]. Theories of [[market form]]s and [[industrial organization]] grew out of this work. They also emphasized certain tools, such as the [[marginal revenue]] curve.
 
  
Joan Robinson's work on imperfect competition, at least, was a response to certain problems of Marshallian [[partial equilibrium]] theory highlighted by [[Piero Sraffa]]. Anglo-American economists also responded to these problems by turning towards [[general equilibrium]] theory, developed on the European continent by Walras and [[Vilfredo Pareto]]. [[J. R. Hicks]]'s ''[[Value and Capital]]'' (1939) was influential in introducing his English-speaking colleagues to these traditions. He, in turn, was influenced by the [[Austrian School]] economist [[Friedrich Hayek]]'s move to the [[London School of Economics]], where Hicks then studied.
+
Preference is given, current, fully determining, and strictly separate from both belief (which simply helps the agent predict uncertain future outcomes) and from the means employed. Everything we do and say is instrumental to preference-satisfaction so much so that there is no longer any philosophical room for questioning whether the agent will act on her preferences.
  
These developments were accompanied by the introduction of new tools, such as [[indifference curve]]s and the theory of ordinal [[utility]]. The level of mathematical sophistication of neoclassical economics increased. [[Paul Samuelson]]'s ''[[Foundations of Economic Analysis]]'' (1947) contributed to this increase in [[formal rigor]].
 
  
The interwar period in American economics has been argued to have been pluralistic, with neoclassical economics and [[institutional economics|institutionalism]] competing for allegiance. [[Frank Knight]], an early [[Chicago school (economics)|Chicago school]] economist attempted to combine both schools. But this increase in mathematics was accompanied by greater dominance of neoclassical economics in Anglo-American universities after [[World War II]].
+
Methodological instrumentalism’s roots are traceable in [[David Hume]]’s ''“Treatise of Human Nature”'' (1739/40) in which the Scottish philosopher famously divided the human decision making process in three distinct modules: Passions, Belief and Reason.  
  
Hicks' book, ''[[Value and Capital]]'' had two main parts. The second, which was arguably not immediately influential, presented a model of temporary equilibrium. Hicks was influenced directly by Hayek's notion of intertemporal coordination and paralleled by earlier work by Lindhal. This was part of an abandonment of disaggregated long run models. This trend probably reached its culmination with the [[Arrow-Debreu model]] of intertemporal equilibrium. The Arrow-Debreu model has canonical presentations in Gerard Debreu's ''Theory of Value'' (1959) and in Arrow and Hahn.
+
Passions provide the destination, Reason slavishly steers a course that attempts to get us there, drawing upon a given set of Beliefs regarding the external constraints and the likely consequences of alternative actions.
  
Many of these developments were against the backdrop of improvements in both [[econometrics]], that is the ability to measure prices and changes in goods and services, as well as their aggregate quantities, and in the creation of [[macroeconomics]], or the study of whole economies. The attempt to combine neo-classical microeconomics and [[Keynesian economics|Keynesian]] macroeconomics would lead to the [[neoclassical synthesis]]<ref> Olivier Jean Blanchard (1987). "neoclassical synthesis," ''The [[New Palgrave: A Dictionary of Economics]]'', v. 3, pp. 634-36.</ref> which has been the dominant paradigm of economic reasoning in English-speaking countries since the 1950s. Hicks and Samuelson were for example instrumental in mainstreaming Keynesian economics.
+
 +
A more recent development has taken neoclassicism, and homo economicus, onto higher levels of sophistication. The advent of psychological game theory (see Hargreaves-Heap and Varoufakis,2004, Ch.7) has brought on a reconsideration of the standard assumption that agents’ current preferences are separate from the structure of the interaction in which they are involved.  
  
Macroeconomics influenced the neoclassical synthesis from the other direction, undermining foundations of classical economic theory such as [[Say's Law]], and assumptions about [[political economy]] such as the necessity for a hard-money standard. These developments are reflected in neoclassical theory by the search for the occurrence in markets of the equilibrium conditions of [[Pareto optimality]] and self-sustainability.
+
Suddenly, what one wants hinged on what she thought others expected she would do. And when these second order beliefs (her beliefs about the expectations of others) came to depend on the social structure in which the decision is embedded, the agent’s very preferences could not be linked just with outcomes: they depended on the structure and history of the interaction as well.
  
== Criticisms ==
 
Neoclassical economics is sometimes criticized for having a [[normative]] bias. In this view, it does not focus on explaining actual economies, but instead on describing a "utopia" in which [[Pareto efficiency|Pareto optimality]] applies. Key assumptions of neoclassical economics which are criticised as unrealistic include:
 
  
The assumption that individuals act rationally may be viewed as ignoring important aspects of human behavior. Many see the "[[Homo economicus|economic man]]" as being demonstrably different from a real man on the real earth. The assumption of [[rational expectations]] which has been introduced in some more modern neo-classical models (sometimes also called [[new classical]]) can also be criticized on the grounds of realism.
+
===Methodological equilibrium===
  
Large corporations might perhaps come closer to the neoclassical ideal of profit maximization, but this is not necessarily viewed as desirable if this comes at the expense of neglect of wider social issues. The response to this is that neoclassical economics is descriptive and not normative. It addresses such problems with concepts of private versus social utility.
+
The reason for the axiomatic imposition of equilibrium is simple: '''it could not be otherwise!''' By this we mean that neoclassicism cannot demonstrate that equilibrium would emerge as a natural consequence of agents’ instrumentally rational choices.  
  
Problems with making the neoclassical [[general equilibrium]] theory compatible with an economy that develops over time and includes capital goods. This was explored in a major debate in the 1960s—the "[[Cambridge capital controversy]]"—about the validity of neoclassical economics, with an emphasis on the [[economic growth]], [[capital (economics)|capital]], aggregate theory, and the [[marginal productivity theory]] of distribution. There were also internal attempts by neoclassical economists to extend the Arrow-Debreu model to disequilibrium investigations of stability and uniqueness. However a result known as the Sonnenschein-Mantel-Debreu theorem suggests that the assumptions that must be made to insure that the equilibrium is stable and unique are quite restrictive.
+
Thus, the second best methodological alternative for the neoclassical theorist is to presume that behaviour hovers around some analytically-discovered equilibrium and then ask questions on the likelihood that, once at that equilibrium, the ‘system’ has a propensity to stick around or drift away (what is known as ''stability analysis'').
  
In the opinion of some, these developments have found fatal weaknesses in neoclassical economics. Economists, however, have continued to use highly mathematical models, and many equate neoclassical economics with economics, unqualified. Mathematical models include those in [[game theory]], [[linear programming]], and [[econometrics]], many of which might be considered non-neoclassical. So economists often refer to what has evolved out of neoclassical economics as "mainstream economics." Critics of neoclassical economics are divided in those who think that highly mathematical method is inherently wrong and those who think that mathematical method is potentially good even if contemporary methods have problems.
 
  
The basic theory of a downward sloping aggregate demand curve is criticized for its allegedly strong assumptions.
+
More generally, it is not just difficult to demonstrate that a system of theoretical markets will generate an equilibrium in each market, on the basis of rational acts on behalf of buyers and sellers; rather, it is impossible! ( see e.g. Sonnenschein, 1973,1974.)
  
In general, allegedly overly unrealistic assumptions are one of the most common criticisms towards neoclassical economics. For example, many theories assume perfect knowledge for market actors and the most common theory of finance markets assumes that debts are always paid back and that any actor can raise as much loan as he wants at any given point of time.
+
In Game Theory the same result obtains: in the most interesting socio-economic interactions (or games) common knowledge that all players are instrumentally rational seldom yields one of the interaction’s Nash equilibria. Something more is required to bring on an equilibrium. That something comes in the form of an axiom that the beliefs of all players are consistently aligned at each stage of every game (see Hargreaves-Heap and Varoufakis, 2004, Chapters 2&3).  
  
The basic theory of production in neoclassical economics is criticized for incorrect assumptions about the rationales of producers. According to the theory, increasing production costs are the reason for producers not to produce over a certain amount. Some empirical counter arguments claim that most producers are not making their production decisions in the light of increasing production costs. For example they often may have additional capacity that could be taken into use, if producing more was desirable.
+
This assumption is, of course, yet another reincarnation of methodological equilibration: for once we assume that agents’ beliefs are systematically and consistently aligned, they are assumed to be in a state of (Nash) equilibrium. Yet again, equilibrium is imposed axiomatically before stability
  
Often at individual levels, variables such as supply and demand, which are independent, are (allegedly wrongly) assumed to be independent also at aggregate level. This criticism has been applied to many central theories of neoclassical economics.
 
  
The critique of the assumption of [[rationality]] is not confined to social theorists and ecologists. Many economists, even contemporaries, have criticized this vision of economic man. [[Thorstein Veblen]] put it most sardonically. Neoclassical economics assumes a person to be,
+
==Simplified functional explanation==
  
<blockquote>"a lightning calculator of pleasures and pains, who oscillates like a homogeneous globule of desire of happiness under the impulse of stimuli that shift about the area, but leave him intact."<ref>[[Thorstein Veblen]] (1898) ''Why Is Economics Not an Evolutionary Science?'', reprinted in The Place of Science in Modern Civilization (New York, 1919), p. 73.</ref></blockquote>
 
  
[[Herbert Simon]]'s theory of [[bounded rationality]] has probably been the most influential of the [[Heterodox economics|heterodox]] approaches. Is economic man a first approximation to a more realistic psychology, an approach only valid in some sphere of human lives, or a general methodological principle for economics?  Early neoclassical economists often leaned toward the first two approaches, but the latter has become prevalent.
+
The functional explanation adds an interesting twist to the same tale of intellectual authoritarianism. If phenomenon X is functionally to explain the occurrence of phenomenon Y, this explanation has merit if and only if the following four conditions are met (see Elster, 1982):
 +
 +
*(1) Y must be beneficial for some group of agents Z.  
  
Neoclassical economics is also often seen as relying too heavily on complex mathematical models, such as those used in [[general equilibrium]] theory, without enough regard to whether these actually describe the real economy. Many see an attempt to model a system as complex as a modern economy by a mathematical model as unrealistic and doomed to failure. Famous answer to this criticism is [[Milton Friedman]]'s claim that theories should be judged by their ability to predict events rather than by the realisticity of their assumptions. Naturally, critics claim that neoclassical economics (as well as other branches of economics) has not been very good at predicting events.
+
*(2) Members of group Z must be responsible for the practices that cause X but must not intend to bring Y about through practices that result in X; indeed, Z members must remain innocent of the causal link between X and Y. Lastly,  
  
Critics of neoclassical models accuse it of copying of 19th century mechanics and the "clockwork" model of society which seems to justify elite privileges as arising "naturally" from the social order based on economic competitions. This is echoed by modern critics in the [[anti-globalization movement]] who often blame the neoclassical theory, as it has been applied by the [[IMF]] in particular, for inequities in global debt and trade relations. They assert it ignores the complexity of nature and of human creativity, and seeks mechanical ideas like equilibrium:
+
*(3) phenomenon Y, which is caused by X, must be shown to reinforce X through a feedback mechanism involving, unintentionally, members of group Z.  
  
<blockquote>"And in Poinset's ''Elements de Statique''..., which was a textbook on the theory of mechanics bristling with systems of simultaneous equations to represent, among other things, the mechanical equilibrium of the solar system, Walras found a pattern for representing the catallactic equilibrium of the market system." (William Jaffe)</blockquote>
 
  
The [[neo-Marxism|neo-Marxists]] [[Michael Hardt]] and [[Antonio Negri]] criticize neoclassical economics and its rejection of Keynesian regulation on philosophical grounds: they assert that neoclassical economics incorrectly posits money as ''[[a priori]]'' ("monetary [[Aristotle|Aristotelianism]]"), even though it is a regulatory instrument.<ref>[[Michael Hardt]] and [[Antonio Negri]] (2005). ''[[Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of Empire]]''. Hamish Hamilton.</ref>
+
In our case, Y is the discursive power of neoclassical economics, X are the practices which keep neoclassicism’s meta-axioms hidden, and Z is the set of neoclassical economists. Can a convincing functionalist explanation of how X causes Y be built along the lines sketched above? If it can, then we shall have an interesting (and possibly correct) explanation of why pluralism is absent from Economics Departments: its radical absence, which is guaranteed when an eerie silence engulfs the three neoclassical meta-axioms, emerges as a prerequisite for neoclassicism’s dominance.  
  
It is fair to say that many (but not all) of these criticisms can only be directed towards a subset of the neoclassical models (for example, there are many neoclassical models where unregulated markets fail to achieve Pareto-optimality and there has recently been an increased interest in modelling bounded rationality).
 
  
 
==References==
 
==References==
  
<references/>
+
*Elster, J. , “Belief, bias and ideology”; in: Hollis-Lukes, Rationality and Relativism, 1982., pp.123—148
 +
*Hargreaves-Heap, S. and Y. Varoufakis, Game Theory: A critical text, Routledge, London and New York, 2004
 +
*Huberman, B. and T. Hogg, "Distributed Computation as an Economic System,"Journal of Economic Perspectives, v. 9, no. 1, Winter 1995, pp. 141-152
 +
*Hume, D. A., Treatise of Human Nature: being an attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects, (1739/40,1888, ed. by L.A. Selby-Bigge), Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1888
 +
*Negishi, T. "The Stability of a Competitive Economy: A Survey Article", Econometrica, 30, 1962, pp. 635-669
 +
*Sandven, T. "Intentional Action and Pure Causality: A Critical Discussion of Some Central Conceptual Distinctions in the Work of Jon Elster", Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 25(3) September 1995, pp. 286-317
 +
*Sonnenschein, H., “Do Walras’ Identity and Continuity Characterize the Class of Community Excess Demand Functions?”, Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 1973, pp. 345-354.
 +
*Sonnenschein, H., “Market Excess Demand Functions,” Econometrica, 40, 1974, pp. 549-563.
 +
*Thompson, H. "Ignorance and Ideological Hegemony: A Critique of Neoclassical Economics", Journal of Interdisciplinary Economics, 8(4), 1997, pp. 291-305
 +
*Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman, “Rational choice and the framing of decision”, Journal of Business, 1986
 +
*Varoufakis, Y. and Ch. Arnsperger, “What Is Neoclassical Economics?”, Post-autistic economics review, Issue no. 38, 1, July 2006
 +
*Veblen, T. "The Preconceptions of Economic Science - III" The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 14, 1900
 +
*Weintraub, E. R., General Equilibrium Analysis: Studies in Appraisal, Cambridge University Press New York, 1985
 +
*Weintraub, E.R. "Surveying dynamics", Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 13(4) Summer 1991, pp. 525-543
 +
 +
 
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==

Revision as of 14:34, 1 August 2008


Neoclassical economics refers to a general approach in economics focusing on the determination of prices, outputs, and income distributions in markets through supply and demand. These are mediated through a hypothesized maximization of income-constrained utility by individuals and of cost-constrained profits of firms employing available information and factors of production. Mainstream economics is largely neoclassical in its assumptions, at least at the microeconomic level.


President Richard Nixon, defending deficit spending against the conservative charge that it was "Keynesian," is reported to have replied, "…We're all Keynesians now…..." In fact, what he should have said is "….We're all neoclassicals now, even the Keynesians…..," because what is taught to students, what is mainstream economics today, is neoclassical economics ( E. R. Weintraub, 1985.)


History of neoclassical economics

Classical economics, developed in the 18th and 19th centuries, included a value theory and distribution theory. The value of a product was thought to depend on the costs involved in producing that product. The explanation of costs in Classical economics was simultaneously an explanation of distribution. A landlord received rent, workers received wages, and a capitalist tenant farmer received profits on their investment. This classic approach included the work of Adam Smith and David Ricardo.


By the middle of the nineteenth century, English-speaking economists generally shared a perspective on value theory and distribution theory. The value of a bushel of corn, for example, was thought to depend on the costs involved in producing that bushel. The output or product of an economy was thought to be divided or distributed among the different social groups in accord with the costs borne by those groups in producing the output. This, roughly, was the "Classical Theory" developed by Adam Smith, David Ricardo, Thomas Robert Malthus, John Stuart Mill, andKarl Marx.


But there were difficulties in this approach. Chief among them was that prices in the market did not necessarily reflect the "value" so defined, for people were often willing to pay more than an object was "worth." The classical "substance" theories of value, which took value to be a property inherent in an object, gradually gave way to a perspective in which value was associated with the relationship between the object and the person obtaining the object.

Several economists in different places at about the same time (the 1870s and 1880s) began to base value on the relationship between costs of production and "subjective elements," later called "supply" and "demand." This came to be known as the Marginal Revolution in economics, and the overarching theory that developed from these ideas came to be called neoclassical economics. The first to use the term "neoclassical economics" seems to have been the American economist Thorstein Veblen ( see T. Veblen, 1900.)

It was then used by George Stigler and John Hicks broadly to include the work of Carl Menger, William Stanley Jevons, and John Bates Clark. Today it is often used to refer to mainstream economics and the Chicago school. Neoclassical economists usually assume, in other words, that human beings make the choices that give them the best possible advantage, given the circumstances they face. Circumstances include the prices of resources, goods and services, limited income, limited technology for transforming resources into goods and services, and taxes, regulations, and similar objective limitations on the choices they may make ( see E.R. Weintraub, 1985. )


Overview and Assumptions

The framework of neoclassical economics is easily summarized. Buyers attempt to maximize their gains from getting goods, and they do this by increasing their purchases of a good until what they gain from an extra unit is just balanced by what they have to give up to obtain it. In this way they maximize "utility"—the satisfaction associated with the consumption of goods and services. Likewise, individuals provide labor to firms that wish to employ them, by balancing the gains from offering the marginal unit of their services (the wage they would receive) with the disutility of labor itself—the loss of leisure. Individuals make choices at the margin. This results in a theory of demand for goods, and supply of productive factors.

Similarly, producers attempt to produce units of a good so that the cost of producing the incremental or marginal unit is just balanced by the revenue it generates. In this way they maximize profits. Firms also hire employees up to the point that the cost of the additional hire is just balanced by the value of output that the additional employee would produce.


Neoclassical economics conceptualized the agents, households and firms, as rational actors. Agents were modeled as optimizers who were led to "better" outcomes. The resulting equilibrium was "best" in the sense that any other allocation of goods and services would leave someone worse off. Thus, the social system in the neoclassical vision was free of unresolvable conflict.

The very term "social system" is a measure of the success of neoclassical economics, for the idea of a system, with its interacting components, its variables and parameters and constraints, is the language of mid-nineteenth-century physics. This field of rational mechanics was the model for the neoclassical framework. The following excerpt clears many misunderstanding:


“…..We understand that the allocation of resources is a social problem in any modern economy. Any modern economic system must somehow answer the questions posed by the allocation of resources. If we are further to understand the way in which people respond to this social problem, we have to make some assumptions about human behavior…….. The assumption at the basis of the neoclassical approach is that people are rational and (more of less) self-interested. This should be understood as an instance of positive economics (about what is) not normative economics (about what ought to be). This distinction, positive versus normative economics, is important in itself and is a key to understanding many aspects of economics…..” ( B. Huberman and T. Hogg, 1995.)


Agents, mentioned above, were like atoms; utility was like energy; utility maximization was like the minimization of potential energy, and so forth. In this way was the rhetoric of successful science linked to the neoclassical theory, and in this way economics became linked to science itself. Whether this linkage was planned by the early Marginalists, or rather was a feature of the public success of science itself, is less important than the implications of that linkage. For once neoclassical economics was associated with scientific economics, to challenge the neoclassical approach was to seem to challenge science and progress and modernity. These developments were accompanied by the introduction of new tools, such as indifference curves and the theory of ordinal utility. The level of mathematical sophistication of neoclassical economics increased. Paul Samuelson's Foundations of Economic Analysis (1947) contributed to this increase in formal rigor.


Value is linked to unlimited desires and wants colliding with constraints, or scarcity. The tensions, the decision problems, are worked out in markets. Prices are the signals that tell households and firms whether their conflicting desires can be reconciled.

EXAMPLE: At some price of cars, for example, I want to buy a new car. At that same price others may also want to buy cars. But manufacturers may not want to produce as many cars as we all want. Our frustration may lead us to "bid up" the price of cars, eliminating some potential buyers and encouraging some marginal producers. As the price changes, the imbalance between buy orders and sell orders is reduced. This is how optimization under constraint and market interdependence lead to an economic equilibrium. This is the neoclassical vision ( ibid.)


To summarize: Neoclassical economics is what is called a metatheory. That is, it is a set of implicit rules or understandings for constructing satisfactory economic theories. It is a scientific research program that generates economic theories. Its fundamental assumptions are not open to discussion in that they define the shared understandings of those who call themselves neoclassical economists, or economists without any adjective. Those fundamental assumptions include the following:


  • People have rational preferences among outcomes that can be identified and associated with a value.
  • Individuals maximize utility and firms maximize profits.
  • People act independently on the basis of full and relevant information.


Theories based on, or guided by, these assumptions are neoclassical theories. Thus, we can speak of a neoclassical theory of profits, or employment, or growth, or money. We can create neoclassical production relationships between inputs and outputs, or neoclassical theories of marriage and divorce and the spacing of births. Consider layoffs, for example. A theory which assumes that a firm's layoff decisions are based on a balance between the benefits of laying off an additional worker and the costs associated with that action will be a neoclassical theory. A theory that explains the layoff decision by the changing tastes of managers for employees with particular characteristics will not be a neoclassical theory ( ibid.)


The value of neoclassical economics can be assessed in the collection of truths to which we are led by its light. The kinds of truths about incentives—about prices and information, about the interrelatedness of decisions and the unintended consequences of choices—are all well developed in neoclassical theories, as is a self-consciousness about the use of evidence.

EXAMPLE: In planning for future electricity needs in my state, for example, the Public Utilities Commission develops a (neoclassical) demand forecast, joins it to a (neoclassical) cost analysis of generation facilities of various sizes and types (e.g., an 800-megawatt low-sulfur coal plant), and develops a least-cost system growth plan and a (neoclassical) pricing strategy for implementing that plan. Those on all sides of the issues, from industry to municipalities, from electric companies to environmental groups, all speak the same language of demand elasticities and cost minimization, of marginal costs and rates of return. The rules of theory development and assessment are clear in neoclassical economics, and that clarity is taken to be beneficial to the community of economists. The scientificness of neoclassical economics, on this view, is not its weakness but its strength ( ibid. )


Critique of neoclassical economics

The rational consumer of the mainstream economist is a working assumption that was meant to free economists from dependence on psychology (e.g. Tversky and Kahneman 1986.)

The dilemma is that the assumption of rationality as intertemporally optimising is often confused with, and regularly presented as, real, purposive behaviour. In fact, the living consumer in historical time routinely makes decisions in undefined contexts. They muddle through, they adapt, they copy, they try what worked in the past, they gamble, they take uncalculated risks, they engage in costly altruistic activities, and regularly make unpredictable, even unexplainable, decisions (Sandven 1995).


It mostly looks like that modern corporations are not even "acting as if" they equilibrate marginal cost-marginal revenue to maximise profits. Rather, they attempt to beat the average. References to the "average" or "normal" pervade the business literature - from the analysis of stock performance, through the stacking of country growth rates and risk premia, to the ranking of corporate profitability.

In these terms, according to Nitzan and Bichler, the primary goal becomes "differential pecuniary accumulation", through which the corporation seeks to control a "larger share of the societal surplus". Consequently, success has less to do with the intuitively convincing textbook equality between marginal cost and marginal revenue, than with the capture of external contested income, thereby redistributing the available social surplus ( H. Thompson, 1997.)


One neoclassical defence is to suggest that equilibrium is only a tendency towards which the system is moving. However, Weintraub (1991) reveals the manner whereby econometricians, such as Negishi, maintain that the equilibrium contained in a model is real and intuitively justified.

They do this by appealing to the "…..reality out there…in which it is known that the economy is fairly shock-proof….We know from experience that prices usually do not explode to infinity or contract to zero…" (Negishi, 1962.)

Neoclassical economics has represented, for two hundred years, the political self-representation of autonomous, self-subsistent, and self-interest-optimising individuals.

And no matter how hard neoclassical economists try to drive away the world of complexity, it too continues to confront them. Yet, to the frustration of "heterogeneous" antagonists the neoclassical paradigm remains dominant, blatantly promoting ignorance-squared. Elegance and technique have replaced relevance. What has been shown herein is that the production of that elegance has involved the opportunity cost of simultaneously producing ignorance. Ignorance-squared is replicated amongst students given the social interests of those dominant in the paradigm ( H. Thompson, 1997. )


Three axioms of the modern neoclassical economics: an answer to the critique

Neoclassical theory retains its roots firmly within liberal individualist social science. The method is still unbendingly of the analytic-synthetic type: the socio-economic phenomenon under scrutiny is to be analysed by focusing on the individuals whose actions brought it about; understanding fully their ‘workings’ at the individual level; and, finally, synthesising the knowledge derived at the individual level in order to understand the complex social phenomenon at hand. In short, neoclassical theory follows the watchmaker’s method who, faced with a strange watch, studies its function by focusing on understanding, initially, the function of each of its cogs and wheels. To the neoclassical economist, the latter are the individual agents who are to be studied, like the watchmaker’ cogs and wheels, independently of the social whole their actions help bring about (Y. Varoufakis and Ch. Arnsperger, 2006.)


Methodological individualism

So, the first feature of the body of theory we think of as neoclassical is its methodological individualism: the idea that socio-economic explanation must be sought at the level of the individual agent. Note two things: First, this was not the method of classical economists like Adam Smith and David Ricardo. Or, indeed, of Keynes or Hayek.

It is, we think, indisputable that all the new manifestations of what we term neoclassicism still subscribe to methodological individualism. While it is true that mainstream economists have, during the last few decades, acknowledged that the agent is a creature of his social context, and thus that social structure and individual agency are messily intertwined, their models retain the distinction and place the burden of explanation on the individual. Individual worker effort is nowadays often modelled as a function of sectoral unemployment (e.g. efficiency wage models), and the firms’ micro-strategies reflect the macroeconomic environment. Nevertheless, and despite these interesting linkages between the micro-agent and the macro-phenomenon, the explanatory trajectory remains one that begins from the agent and maps, unidirectionally, onto the social structure ( ibid. )


Methodological instrumentalism

We label the second feature of neoclassical economics methodological instrumentalism: all behaviour is preference-driven or, more precisely, it is to be understood as a means for maximising preference-satisfaction.

Preference is given, current, fully determining, and strictly separate from both belief (which simply helps the agent predict uncertain future outcomes) and from the means employed. Everything we do and say is instrumental to preference-satisfaction so much so that there is no longer any philosophical room for questioning whether the agent will act on her preferences.


Methodological instrumentalism’s roots are traceable in David Hume’s “Treatise of Human Nature” (1739/40) in which the Scottish philosopher famously divided the human decision making process in three distinct modules: Passions, Belief and Reason.

Passions provide the destination, Reason slavishly steers a course that attempts to get us there, drawing upon a given set of Beliefs regarding the external constraints and the likely consequences of alternative actions.


A more recent development has taken neoclassicism, and homo economicus, onto higher levels of sophistication. The advent of psychological game theory (see Hargreaves-Heap and Varoufakis,2004, Ch.7) has brought on a reconsideration of the standard assumption that agents’ current preferences are separate from the structure of the interaction in which they are involved.

Suddenly, what one wants hinged on what she thought others expected she would do. And when these second order beliefs (her beliefs about the expectations of others) came to depend on the social structure in which the decision is embedded, the agent’s very preferences could not be linked just with outcomes: they depended on the structure and history of the interaction as well.


Methodological equilibrium

The reason for the axiomatic imposition of equilibrium is simple: it could not be otherwise! By this we mean that neoclassicism cannot demonstrate that equilibrium would emerge as a natural consequence of agents’ instrumentally rational choices.

Thus, the second best methodological alternative for the neoclassical theorist is to presume that behaviour hovers around some analytically-discovered equilibrium and then ask questions on the likelihood that, once at that equilibrium, the ‘system’ has a propensity to stick around or drift away (what is known as stability analysis).


More generally, it is not just difficult to demonstrate that a system of theoretical markets will generate an equilibrium in each market, on the basis of rational acts on behalf of buyers and sellers; rather, it is impossible! ( see e.g. Sonnenschein, 1973,1974.)

In Game Theory the same result obtains: in the most interesting socio-economic interactions (or games) common knowledge that all players are instrumentally rational seldom yields one of the interaction’s Nash equilibria. Something more is required to bring on an equilibrium. That something comes in the form of an axiom that the beliefs of all players are consistently aligned at each stage of every game (see Hargreaves-Heap and Varoufakis, 2004, Chapters 2&3).

This assumption is, of course, yet another reincarnation of methodological equilibration: for once we assume that agents’ beliefs are systematically and consistently aligned, they are assumed to be in a state of (Nash) equilibrium. Yet again, equilibrium is imposed axiomatically before stability


Simplified functional explanation

The functional explanation adds an interesting twist to the same tale of intellectual authoritarianism. If phenomenon X is functionally to explain the occurrence of phenomenon Y, this explanation has merit if and only if the following four conditions are met (see Elster, 1982):

  • (1) Y must be beneficial for some group of agents Z.
  • (2) Members of group Z must be responsible for the practices that cause X but must not intend to bring Y about through practices that result in X; indeed, Z members must remain innocent of the causal link between X and Y. Lastly,
  • (3) phenomenon Y, which is caused by X, must be shown to reinforce X through a feedback mechanism involving, unintentionally, members of group Z.


In our case, Y is the discursive power of neoclassical economics, X are the practices which keep neoclassicism’s meta-axioms hidden, and Z is the set of neoclassical economists. Can a convincing functionalist explanation of how X causes Y be built along the lines sketched above? If it can, then we shall have an interesting (and possibly correct) explanation of why pluralism is absent from Economics Departments: its radical absence, which is guaranteed when an eerie silence engulfs the three neoclassical meta-axioms, emerges as a prerequisite for neoclassicism’s dominance.


References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Elster, J. , “Belief, bias and ideology”; in: Hollis-Lukes, Rationality and Relativism, 1982., pp.123—148
  • Hargreaves-Heap, S. and Y. Varoufakis, Game Theory: A critical text, Routledge, London and New York, 2004
  • Huberman, B. and T. Hogg, "Distributed Computation as an Economic System,"Journal of Economic Perspectives, v. 9, no. 1, Winter 1995, pp. 141-152
  • Hume, D. A., Treatise of Human Nature: being an attempt to introduce the experimental method of reasoning into moral subjects, (1739/40,1888, ed. by L.A. Selby-Bigge), Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1888
  • Negishi, T. "The Stability of a Competitive Economy: A Survey Article", Econometrica, 30, 1962, pp. 635-669
  • Sandven, T. "Intentional Action and Pure Causality: A Critical Discussion of Some Central Conceptual Distinctions in the Work of Jon Elster", Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 25(3) September 1995, pp. 286-317
  • Sonnenschein, H., “Do Walras’ Identity and Continuity Characterize the Class of Community Excess Demand Functions?”, Journal of Economic Theory, 6, 1973, pp. 345-354.
  • Sonnenschein, H., “Market Excess Demand Functions,” Econometrica, 40, 1974, pp. 549-563.
  • Thompson, H. "Ignorance and Ideological Hegemony: A Critique of Neoclassical Economics", Journal of Interdisciplinary Economics, 8(4), 1997, pp. 291-305
  • Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman, “Rational choice and the framing of decision”, Journal of Business, 1986
  • Varoufakis, Y. and Ch. Arnsperger, “What Is Neoclassical Economics?”, Post-autistic economics review, Issue no. 38, 1, July 2006
  • Veblen, T. "The Preconceptions of Economic Science - III" The Quarterly Journal of Economics, vol. 14, 1900
  • Weintraub, E. R., General Equilibrium Analysis: Studies in Appraisal, Cambridge University Press New York, 1985
  • Weintraub, E.R. "Surveying dynamics", Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 13(4) Summer 1991, pp. 525-543


External links

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.