Difference between revisions of "Diodorus Cronus" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{claimed}}
 
{{claimed}}
 +
The '''Tung-lin Movement''' (Dong-lin Movement) (c.1530 – c. 1630) was a political reform movement organized among the bureaucratic elite in the imperial government of the late [[Ming dynasty]] of [[China]]. At that time, corruption was rampant in the government, and members of the bureaucratic elite vied with eunuchs and court attendants to influence the policies of the emperors, who had withdrawn themselves from day-to-day political affairs. Members of the [[Confucianism|Confucian]] bureaucratic elite became concerned about this state of affairs and began to take matters into their own hands.  They established private universities in their home states to train the Confucian scholars they believed were necessary for good government, and attempted to bring about a change in the structure of the government, so that all authority would not be vested in one despotic emperor, but shared with a council of elite Confucian officials.
  
'''Diodorus Cronus''' (4th century BC) was a Greek [[philosopher]] of the [[Megarian school of philosophy|Megarian school]]. Most notable for logic innovations, in particular the [[Problem of the futures contingents|paradox of future contingents]], little is known of his life.  
+
Early in the seventeenth century, the Tung-lin Acadmey joined with neighboring academies in Wu-chin and I-hsing to form the powerful Ch’ang-chou faction. Many of its members occupied high positions in the government bureaucracy, and from 1621 -1624 they were able to influence imperial policy in Peking. In the summer of  1625, Tung-lin leaders were purged, arrested, and tortured to death by the eunuch Wei Chung-hsien, and the private academies were destroyed. After Wei’s disgrace and death in 1627, there was a resurgence of the reform factions.  The movements disappeared after the fall of the Ming dynasty to the Manchu in 1644.
 +
 +
== Politics of the Late Ming Dynasty==
 +
During the last century of the [[Ming dynasty]], between approximately 1530 and 1630, the bureaucratic elite and Chinese gentry rose up in an unprecedented reaction to “authoritarian [[Confucianism]].” Corruption was rampant among government officials, and the Ming emperors had withdrawn from day-to-day involvement in affairs of state, leaving a power vacuum that was filled by members of the imperial court, particularly eunuchs (by the end of the Ming dynasty, there were 70,000 eunuchs in the Forbidden City), and members of the bureaucratic elite and landed gentry, constantly vying for political control. Concerned about the condition of the government, many members of the bureaucratic elite began to take matters into their own hands.
 +
 +
The gentry, who wielded considerable power in their own states, began to establish private universities to train the Confucian scholars they believed were necessary for good government. At the same time they began attempting to bring about a change in the structure of the imperial government, in order to establish a system in which all authority would not be vested in one despotic emperor, but in a council of elite Confucian officials who would make decisions and oversee the daily affairs of government.
  
[[Diogenes Laertius]] tells a story that, while staying at the court of [[Ptolemy Soter]], Diodorus was asked to solve a dialectical subtlety by [[Stilpo]]. Not being able to answer on the spur of the moment, he was given a nickname by Ptolemy meaning the God, equivalent to slowcoach. The story goes that he died of shame at his failure. Strabo, however, says that he took the name from [[Apollonius]], his master.  
+
==The Tung-lin Movement==
 +
The largest of these movements was the '''Tung-lin''', associated with the Tung-lin Academy. Early in the seventeenth century, the Tung-lin Academy joined with neighboring academies in Wu-chin and I-hsing to form the powerful Ch’ang-chou faction. Many of its members occupied high positions in the government bureaucracy, and they were able to influence imperial policy in Peking. They reached the height of their influence between 1621 and 1624.
  
Like the rest of the Megarian school he revelled in verbal quibbles, proving that motion and existence are impossible. The impossible cannot result from the possible; a past event cannot become other than it is; but if an event, at a given moment, had been possible, from this possible would result something impossible; therefore the original event was impossible. This problem was taken up by [[Chrysippus]], who admitted that he could not solve it.
+
In 1621, the young T'ien-ch'i Emperor came to the throne, and fell under the influence of the eunuch Wei Chung-hsien. Wei Chung-hsien had been a hoodlum and gambler, who had made himself a eunuch and changed his name to Li Chin-chung in order to escape from his debtors. Entering the imperial palace, he had managed to get into the service of Madam Ke (客氏) the wet-nurse of the future [[Ming Dynasty|Ming]] emperor. The couple began manipulating the young and illiterate Tianqi Emperor, who later made Wei his Grand Secretary of the State, giving him absolute power over the court. Wei gave  himself the name, ''Nine-Thousand Years' (九千歲), symbolizing that he was second only to the emperor, who was called the ''Ten-Thousand Years''(萬歲). Wei also built a number of shrines (生祠), placing god-like statues of himself in them. This was exactly the kind of situation that the Confucian officials abhorred, but they were powerless against it. Wei’s faction at court gradually undermined the power of the Tung-lin officials, and despite their high positions, they were dismissed from office. In the summer of  1625, Tung-lin leaders were purged, arrested, and tortured to death.  
  
==The problem of the future's contingents==
+
The private academies were denounced as politically subversive organizations, and the emperor ordered them destroyed throughout the empire, especially those in Ch'ang-chou and Su-chou prefectures because these were assumed to be part of the Tung-lin organization. The halls of the Tung-lin Academy, partially destroyed in 1625, were completely torn down by imperial order in 1626.  
The '''problem of the future's contingents''' is a [[logical]] [[paradox]] first posed by [[Diodorus Cronus]] from the [[Megarian school of philosophy]], under the name of the "dominator", and then reactualized by [[Aristotle]] in chapter 9 of ''[[De Interpretatione]]''. It was later taken on by [[Leibniz]]. It concerns the [[contingency]] of a future event. [[Deleuze]] used it to oppose a "logic of the event" to a "logic of [[signification]]". Diodorus' problem concerned the question: "Will there be a sea battle tomorrow?" According to this question, two propositions are possible: "yes, there will be a sea battle tomorrow" or "no, there will not be a sea battle tomorrow." This was a paradox in Diodorus' eyes, since either there would be a battle tomorrow or there wouldn't be one: according to the basic [[principle of bivalence]] (''A'' is either true or false), one of the two proposition had to be right and therefore excluded the other. But this poses a problem, since the judgment on the proposition (whether it is right or wrong) can only be made when the event has happened. In Deleuze's words, "time is the crisis of truth" <ref> [[Gilles Deleuze]], ''Cinema 2: The Time-Image'' (1989), chapter VI, section 1 </ref>. This problem thus concerns the [[ontology|ontological]] status of the future, and therefore of human action: is our future determined or not? The future, putting in stakes the category of [[possibility]], here poses problems to logic which are discussed to the present time.
 
  
== Aristotle's solution ==
+
Wei Chung-hsien’s reign of terror ended abruptly with the death of the Tianqi Emperor, whose successor, the Chongzhen Emperor promptly dismissed him. He was killed and his corpse was disemboweled. The accession of the Chongzhen Emperor restored the fortunes of the Donglin faction. Later during Chongzhen's reign, Donglin partisans found themselves opposed to the Grand Secretary Wen Tiren, and eventually arranged his dismissal in 1637.
  
According to the [[principle of bivalence]], something concerning [[reality]] is either true or false (''A'' is ''B'' or ''A'' is not ''B''). Logic is thus based on [[disjunctive syllogism]]. But this poses a problem when logic is applied to future [[possibility|possibilities]] instead of present reality. Diodorus' famous propositions are: "Will there be a sea battle tomorrow?" and/or "Will there not be a sea battle tomorrow?" This problems concerns the [[ontology|ontological]] statute of the future, and therefore of human action: is future [[determinism|determined]] or not? Logical necessity seems to be defeated by real necessity.
+
==Fu She==
 +
After Wei fell into disgrace in 1627, the private academies and associations re-emerged and engaged in the factionalism and political controversies which destabilized the last governments of the Ming dynasty. The '''Fu She''' (Return [to Antiquity] Society) movement, based in Su-chou during the 1620s and 1630s, represented the largest and most sophisticated political interest group ever organized within the imperial bureaucratic structure. It supported its members in the factional struggles that dominated late Ming politics.
  
One can either say that the proposition is neither true nor false: some possible futures make it true and others wrong; this may be called "indeterminacy intuition". Or one can say that the truth-value of the proposition will be only given in the future, that is until the future unfolds. Thus, it is always ''will be given'' but never presently given.  
+
When the Ming dynasty fell in 1644, first to peasant rebels and then to Manchu conquerors, the activities of the Fu She ceased and the factionalism within the imperial government disappeared. The elite gentry, fearing peasant rebellion more than they feared Manchu occupation, recognized that their social and economic privileges depended on the political power of the state, and many of them quickly entered the administration of the Ch’ing dynasty. The new Ch’ing emperors actively participated in government affairs, keeping power struggles under control.
  
Aristotle solved the problem by asserting that the principle of bivalence found its [[exception]] in this paradox of the sea battles: in this specific case, what is impossible is that both alternatives can be possible at the same time: either there ''will'' be a battle, or there won't. Both options can't be simultaneously taken. Today, they are neither true nor false; but if one is true, then the other becomes false. According to Aristotle, it is impossible to say today if the proposition is correct: we must wait for the contingent realization (or not) of the battle, logic realizes itself afterwards:
+
==Significance of the Tung-lin Movement==
:''One of the two propositions in such instances must be true and the other false, but we cannot say determinately that this or that is false, but must leave the alternative undecided. One may indeed be more likely to be true than the other, but it cannot be either actually true or actually false. It is therefore plain that it is not necessary that of an affirmation and a denial, one should be true and the other false. For in the case of that which exists potentially, but not actually, the rule which applies to that which exists actually does not hold good.'' ([http://etext.library.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/interpretation/ §9])
+
The appearance of a widespread, organized opposition movement among the officials within an imperial government was unprecedented in Chinese history. Confucian tradition dictated that the emperor exercised supreme power, and that the strength of the empire depended on the obedience and loyalty of officials to the imperial throne.  However, the actual political situation had become so distant from Confucian ideals of government that many officials feared that the Ming empire would lose its “mandate” and meet its downfall. The Tung-lin movement aimed to remedy imperial abuses of power, and to protect the empire from incapable leaders by investing political authority in a group of professional Confucian officials who would assist the emperor in government.
  
For Diodorus, the future battle was either [[impossible]] or [[necessary]]. Aristotle added a third term, [[contingency]], which saves logic while in the same time leaving place for indetermination in reality. What is necessary is not that there will or that there won't be a battle tomorrow, but the alternative itself is necessary:
+
[[Confucianism|Confucian]] scholars of the time attributed the fall of the [[Ming dynasty]] to the despotism of the emperors, but also to the factionalism within the government. Many cultivated Confucians feared that it was wrong to establish separate political organizations for the advancement of personal interests, and perceived Wei Chung-hsien’s brutal purge of the Tung-lin movement as a sign of heaven’s displeasure. Factionalism went against the emperor, who according to the Confucian ideal represented the public interest.
:''A sea-fight must either take place to-morrow or not, but it is not necessary that it should take place to-morrow, neither is it necessary that it should not take place, yet it is necessary that it either should or should not take place to-morrow." ''[[De Interpretatione]]'''' [http://etext.library.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/interpretation/ 9, 19 a 30.]
 
  
Thus, the event always comes in the form of the future, indetermined event; logic always come afterwards. [[Hegel]] would say the same thing by claiming that wisdom came at the dusk. For Aristotle, this is also a practical, [[ethic]]al question: to pretend that future is determined would have unacceptable consequences on man.
+
Modern historians and scholars see the Tung-lin movement as the natural outcome of a situation in which an autocratic government attempts to exercise too much control over a large population with expanding urban centers. The Tung-lin movement and the political thought associated with it are also perceived as an advancement in Confucian political theory. Some Western scholars have speculated that Tung-lin efforts to reform the late Ming state "showed features strikingly similar to the trend against absolute monarchy and toward parliamentary rule in the West," <ref> Struve, Lynn A. 2005. Time, temporality, and imperial transition: East Asia from Ming to Qing., v. 9, pt 1 </ref>and that the continuation of the traditional imperial system after the Manchu conquest represents a point at which the political history of China diverged from that of Europe.
  
== Leibniz ==
+
==The '''Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy''' ==  
  
[[Leibniz]] gave another response to the paradox in [http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/Leibniz-Discourse.htm#VI §6] of ''[[Discourse on Metaphysics]]'': "That God does nothing which is not orderly, and that it is not even possible to conceive of events which are not regular." Thus, even a [[miracle]], the Event by excellence, does not break the regular order of things. What is seen as irregular is only a default of perspective, but does not appear so in relation to universal order. Possible exceeds human logics. Leibniz encounters this paradox because according to him:
+
The '''Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy'''  (東林書院 ''Dōnglín Shūyuàn'' — literally meaning "Eastern Grove Academy"), also known as the '''Guishan Academy''' (龜山書院 ''Guīshān Shūyuàn''), was originally built in 1111 C.E. during the Northern Song (北宋) dynasty at present-day Wuxi in [[China]]. It was originally the school where the [[neo-Confucianism|neo-Confucian]] scholar Yang Shi taught, but later fell into disuse. In 1604, during the Wanli era, Gu Xiancheng (顧憲成 Gù Xiànchéng, (1550-1612), a Ming Grand Secretary, along with Gao Panlong (高攀龍 Gāo Pānlóng, 1562-1626), a scholar, restored the Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy on the same site with the financial backing of local gentry and officials.  
:''Thus the quality of king, which belonged to Alexander the Great, an abstraction from the subject, is not sufficiently determined to constitute an individual, and does not contain the other qualities of the same subject, nor everything which the idea of this prince includes. God, however, seeing the individual concept, or [[haecceity]], of Alexander, sees there at the same time the basis and the reason of all the predicates which can be truly uttered regarding him; for instance that he will conquer Darius and Porus, even to the point of knowing a priori (and not by experience) whether he died a natural death or by poison,- facts which we can learn only through history. When we carefully consider the connection of things we see also the possibility of saying that there was always in the soul of Alexander marks of all that had happened to him and evidences of all that would happen to him and traces even of everything which occurs in the universe, although God alone could recognize them all.'' ([http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/Leibniz-Discourse.htm#VIII §8])
 
If everything which happens to Alexander derives from the haecceity of Alexander, then [[fatalism]] threatens Leibniz's construction:
 
:''We have said that the concept of an individual substance includes once for all everything which can ever happen to it and that in considering this concept one will be able to see everything which can truly be said concerning the individual, just as we are able to see in the nature of a circle all the properties which can be derived from it. But does it not seem that in this way the difference between contingent and necessary truths will be destroyed, that there will be no place for human liberty, and that an absolute fatality will rule as well over all our actions as over all the rest of the events of the world? To this I reply that a distinction must be made between that which is certain and that which is necessary.'' ([http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/Leibniz-Discourse.htm#VI §13])
 
Against Aristotle's separation between the [[subject (grammar)|subject]] and the [[Predicate (grammar)|predicate]], Leibniz states: "Thus the content of the subject must always include that of the predicate in such a way that if one understands perfectly the concept of the subject, he will know that the predicate appertains to it also." ([http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/Leibniz-Discourse.htm#VIII §8]). The predicate (what happens to Alexander) must be completely included in the subject (Alexander) "if one understands perfectly the concept of the subject". Leibniz henceforth distinguish two types of necessity: necessary necessity and contingent necessity, or universal necessity vs singular necessity. Universal necessity concerns universal truths, while singular necessity concerns something necessary which could not be (it is thus a "contingent necessity"). Leibniz hereby uses the concept of [[compossible]] worlds. According to Leibniz, contingent acts such as "Caesar crossing the Rubicon" or "Adam eating the apple" are necessary: that is, they are singular necessities, contingents and accidentals, but which concerns the [[principle of sufficient reason]]. Furthermore, this leads Leibniz to conceive of the [[subject (philosophy)|subject]] not as a universal, but as a singular: it is true that "Caesar crosses the Rubicon", but it is true only of ''this'' Caesar at this ''time'', not of any dictator nor of Caesar at any time (§8, 9, 13). Thus Leibniz conceives of [[substance]] as plural: there is a plurality of singular substances, which he calls [[monads]]. Leibniz hence creates a [[concept]] of the [[individual]] as such, and attributes to it events. There is a universal necessity, which is universally applicable, and a singular necessity, which applies to each singular substance, or event. There is one proper noun for each singular event: Leibniz creates a logic of singularity, which Aristotle thought impossible (he considered that there could only be knowledge of generality).
 
  
== References ==
+
The motivation for founding the Tung-lin Academy was concern about the state of the bureaucracy and its inability to bring about improvement. The Academy represented a return to Confucian moral traditions as a means of arriving at fresh moral evaluations. In the late Ming and early Ch’ing periods, the Academy became a center of dissent for those involved in public affairs Many supporters of Tung-lin (Donglin) were members of  the bureaucracy, and it become deeply involved in factional politics.
{{reflist}}
 
== See also ==
 
  
*In [[Jorge Luis Borges|Borges]]' ''[[The Garden of Forking Paths]]'', both alternatives happen, thus leading to what Deleuze calls "incompossible worlds"
+
During the reign of the Emperor Tianqi, Tung-lin (Donglin) opposition to the eunuch Wei Zhongxian resulted in the closure of the Academy in 1622 and the torture and execution of its head, Yang Lian, and five other members in 1624. The accession of the Chongzhen Emperor restored the fortunes of the Tung-lin (Donglin) faction. Later during Chongzhen's reign, Tung-lin ( Donglin) partisans found themselves opposed to the Grand Secretary Wen Tiren, and eventually arranged his dismissal in 1637.
  
== External links ==
+
The Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy can be found at 867, Jiefang Donglu, Wuxi City.
*[http://www.ephilosopher.com/article496.html Ephilosopher], ''Sea Battles, Futures Contingents, and Relative Truth'' and ''Future Contingent and Relative Truth'' by John MacFarlane, ''[[The Philosophical Quarterly]]'' 53 (2003), 321-36
+
==Notes==
*[http://www.cerphi.net/lec/even2.htm CERPHI] {{fr icon}}
 
  
[[Category:Modal logic]]
 
[[Category:Philosophical logic]]
 
  
{{credit2|Diodorus_Cronus|120835828|Problem_of_the_future%27s_contingents|125541087}}
+
==References==
*This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.
+
*Conference on Seventeenth-Century Chinese Thought, and William Theodore De Bary. 1975. ''The unfolding of Neo-Confucianism. Studies in oriental culture'', no. 10. New York: Columbia University Press ISBN: 0231038283 9780231038287 0231038291 9780231038294 |  
 +
*Lao, Siguang. 1970. ''The split within the Tung-Lin movement and its consequences.''
 +
*Hucker, Charles O. 1975. ''China's imperial past: an introduction to Chinese history and culture.'' Stanford, Calif: Stanford University Press. ISBN: 0804708878 : 780804708876
 +
*Spence, Jonathan D., and John E. Wills. 1979. ''From Ming to Ch’ing: conquest, region, and continuity in seventeenth-century China.'' New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN: 0300022182 9780300022186
 +
*Struve, Lynn A. 2005. ''Time, temporality, and imperial transition: East Asia from Ming to Qing. Asian interactions and comparisons.'' Honolulu: Association for Asian Studies and University of Hawai'i Press. ISBN: 0824828275 9780824828271
 +
 
 +
[[category:Confucianism]]
 +
[[Category:Chinese culture]]
 +
[[Category:Education in China]]
 +
[[Category:Imperial China]]
 +
[[Category:1111 establishments]]
 +
[[Category:History of education]]
 +
[[Category:Chinese philosophy]]
 +
{{credit|124620508}}

Revision as of 16:48, 18 May 2007

The Tung-lin Movement (Dong-lin Movement) (c.1530 – c. 1630) was a political reform movement organized among the bureaucratic elite in the imperial government of the late Ming dynasty of China. At that time, corruption was rampant in the government, and members of the bureaucratic elite vied with eunuchs and court attendants to influence the policies of the emperors, who had withdrawn themselves from day-to-day political affairs. Members of the Confucian bureaucratic elite became concerned about this state of affairs and began to take matters into their own hands. They established private universities in their home states to train the Confucian scholars they believed were necessary for good government, and attempted to bring about a change in the structure of the government, so that all authority would not be vested in one despotic emperor, but shared with a council of elite Confucian officials.

Early in the seventeenth century, the Tung-lin Acadmey joined with neighboring academies in Wu-chin and I-hsing to form the powerful Ch’ang-chou faction. Many of its members occupied high positions in the government bureaucracy, and from 1621 -1624 they were able to influence imperial policy in Peking. In the summer of 1625, Tung-lin leaders were purged, arrested, and tortured to death by the eunuch Wei Chung-hsien, and the private academies were destroyed. After Wei’s disgrace and death in 1627, there was a resurgence of the reform factions. The movements disappeared after the fall of the Ming dynasty to the Manchu in 1644.

Politics of the Late Ming Dynasty

During the last century of the Ming dynasty, between approximately 1530 and 1630, the bureaucratic elite and Chinese gentry rose up in an unprecedented reaction to “authoritarian Confucianism.” Corruption was rampant among government officials, and the Ming emperors had withdrawn from day-to-day involvement in affairs of state, leaving a power vacuum that was filled by members of the imperial court, particularly eunuchs (by the end of the Ming dynasty, there were 70,000 eunuchs in the Forbidden City), and members of the bureaucratic elite and landed gentry, constantly vying for political control. Concerned about the condition of the government, many members of the bureaucratic elite began to take matters into their own hands.

The gentry, who wielded considerable power in their own states, began to establish private universities to train the Confucian scholars they believed were necessary for good government. At the same time they began attempting to bring about a change in the structure of the imperial government, in order to establish a system in which all authority would not be vested in one despotic emperor, but in a council of elite Confucian officials who would make decisions and oversee the daily affairs of government.

The Tung-lin Movement

The largest of these movements was the Tung-lin, associated with the Tung-lin Academy. Early in the seventeenth century, the Tung-lin Academy joined with neighboring academies in Wu-chin and I-hsing to form the powerful Ch’ang-chou faction. Many of its members occupied high positions in the government bureaucracy, and they were able to influence imperial policy in Peking. They reached the height of their influence between 1621 and 1624.

In 1621, the young T'ien-ch'i Emperor came to the throne, and fell under the influence of the eunuch Wei Chung-hsien. Wei Chung-hsien had been a hoodlum and gambler, who had made himself a eunuch and changed his name to Li Chin-chung in order to escape from his debtors. Entering the imperial palace, he had managed to get into the service of Madam Ke (客氏) the wet-nurse of the future Ming emperor. The couple began manipulating the young and illiterate Tianqi Emperor, who later made Wei his Grand Secretary of the State, giving him absolute power over the court. Wei gave himself the name, Nine-Thousand Years' (九千歲), symbolizing that he was second only to the emperor, who was called the Ten-Thousand Years(萬歲). Wei also built a number of shrines (生祠), placing god-like statues of himself in them. This was exactly the kind of situation that the Confucian officials abhorred, but they were powerless against it. Wei’s faction at court gradually undermined the power of the Tung-lin officials, and despite their high positions, they were dismissed from office. In the summer of 1625, Tung-lin leaders were purged, arrested, and tortured to death.

The private academies were denounced as politically subversive organizations, and the emperor ordered them destroyed throughout the empire, especially those in Ch'ang-chou and Su-chou prefectures because these were assumed to be part of the Tung-lin organization. The halls of the Tung-lin Academy, partially destroyed in 1625, were completely torn down by imperial order in 1626.

Wei Chung-hsien’s reign of terror ended abruptly with the death of the Tianqi Emperor, whose successor, the Chongzhen Emperor promptly dismissed him. He was killed and his corpse was disemboweled. The accession of the Chongzhen Emperor restored the fortunes of the Donglin faction. Later during Chongzhen's reign, Donglin partisans found themselves opposed to the Grand Secretary Wen Tiren, and eventually arranged his dismissal in 1637.

Fu She

After Wei fell into disgrace in 1627, the private academies and associations re-emerged and engaged in the factionalism and political controversies which destabilized the last governments of the Ming dynasty. The Fu She (Return [to Antiquity] Society) movement, based in Su-chou during the 1620s and 1630s, represented the largest and most sophisticated political interest group ever organized within the imperial bureaucratic structure. It supported its members in the factional struggles that dominated late Ming politics.

When the Ming dynasty fell in 1644, first to peasant rebels and then to Manchu conquerors, the activities of the Fu She ceased and the factionalism within the imperial government disappeared. The elite gentry, fearing peasant rebellion more than they feared Manchu occupation, recognized that their social and economic privileges depended on the political power of the state, and many of them quickly entered the administration of the Ch’ing dynasty. The new Ch’ing emperors actively participated in government affairs, keeping power struggles under control.

Significance of the Tung-lin Movement

The appearance of a widespread, organized opposition movement among the officials within an imperial government was unprecedented in Chinese history. Confucian tradition dictated that the emperor exercised supreme power, and that the strength of the empire depended on the obedience and loyalty of officials to the imperial throne. However, the actual political situation had become so distant from Confucian ideals of government that many officials feared that the Ming empire would lose its “mandate” and meet its downfall. The Tung-lin movement aimed to remedy imperial abuses of power, and to protect the empire from incapable leaders by investing political authority in a group of professional Confucian officials who would assist the emperor in government.

Confucian scholars of the time attributed the fall of the Ming dynasty to the despotism of the emperors, but also to the factionalism within the government. Many cultivated Confucians feared that it was wrong to establish separate political organizations for the advancement of personal interests, and perceived Wei Chung-hsien’s brutal purge of the Tung-lin movement as a sign of heaven’s displeasure. Factionalism went against the emperor, who according to the Confucian ideal represented the public interest.

Modern historians and scholars see the Tung-lin movement as the natural outcome of a situation in which an autocratic government attempts to exercise too much control over a large population with expanding urban centers. The Tung-lin movement and the political thought associated with it are also perceived as an advancement in Confucian political theory. Some Western scholars have speculated that Tung-lin efforts to reform the late Ming state "showed features strikingly similar to the trend against absolute monarchy and toward parliamentary rule in the West," [1]and that the continuation of the traditional imperial system after the Manchu conquest represents a point at which the political history of China diverged from that of Europe.

The Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy

The Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy (東林書院 Dōnglín Shūyuàn — literally meaning "Eastern Grove Academy"), also known as the Guishan Academy (龜山書院 Guīshān Shūyuàn), was originally built in 1111 C.E. during the Northern Song (北宋) dynasty at present-day Wuxi in China. It was originally the school where the neo-Confucian scholar Yang Shi taught, but later fell into disuse. In 1604, during the Wanli era, Gu Xiancheng (顧憲成 Gù Xiànchéng, (1550-1612), a Ming Grand Secretary, along with Gao Panlong (高攀龍 Gāo Pānlóng, 1562-1626), a scholar, restored the Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy on the same site with the financial backing of local gentry and officials.

The motivation for founding the Tung-lin Academy was concern about the state of the bureaucracy and its inability to bring about improvement. The Academy represented a return to Confucian moral traditions as a means of arriving at fresh moral evaluations. In the late Ming and early Ch’ing periods, the Academy became a center of dissent for those involved in public affairs Many supporters of Tung-lin (Donglin) were members of the bureaucracy, and it become deeply involved in factional politics.

During the reign of the Emperor Tianqi, Tung-lin (Donglin) opposition to the eunuch Wei Zhongxian resulted in the closure of the Academy in 1622 and the torture and execution of its head, Yang Lian, and five other members in 1624. The accession of the Chongzhen Emperor restored the fortunes of the Tung-lin (Donglin) faction. Later during Chongzhen's reign, Tung-lin ( Donglin) partisans found themselves opposed to the Grand Secretary Wen Tiren, and eventually arranged his dismissal in 1637.

The Tung-lin (Donglin) Academy can be found at 867, Jiefang Donglu, Wuxi City.

Notes

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Conference on Seventeenth-Century Chinese Thought, and William Theodore De Bary. 1975. The unfolding of Neo-Confucianism. Studies in oriental culture, no. 10. New York: Columbia University Press ISBN: 0231038283 9780231038287 0231038291 9780231038294 |
  • Lao, Siguang. 1970. The split within the Tung-Lin movement and its consequences.
  • Hucker, Charles O. 1975. China's imperial past: an introduction to Chinese history and culture. Stanford, Calif: Stanford University Press. ISBN: 0804708878 : 780804708876
  • Spence, Jonathan D., and John E. Wills. 1979. From Ming to Ch’ing: conquest, region, and continuity in seventeenth-century China. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN: 0300022182 9780300022186
  • Struve, Lynn A. 2005. Time, temporality, and imperial transition: East Asia from Ming to Qing. Asian interactions and comparisons. Honolulu: Association for Asian Studies and University of Hawai'i Press. ISBN: 0824828275 9780824828271

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.

  1. Struve, Lynn A. 2005. Time, temporality, and imperial transition: East Asia from Ming to Qing., v. 9, pt 1