Difference between revisions of "Proclus" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m ({{Contracted}})
 
(18 intermediate revisions by 7 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Contracted}}
+
{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{copyedited}}
 
{{Otheruses1|Proclus Diadochus, the Neoplatonist philosopher}}
 
{{Otheruses1|Proclus Diadochus, the Neoplatonist philosopher}}
  
'''Proclus''' Lycaeus ([[February 8]], [[412]] – [[April 17]], [[485]]),  surnamed "The Successor" or "diadochos" ([[Greek language|Greek]] Πρόκλος ὁ Διάδοχος ''Próklos ho Diádokhos''), was a [[Greek philosophy|Greek]] [[Neoplatonist]] [[philosophy|philosopher]], one of the last major Greek philosophers (see [[Damascius]]).  His is one of the most elaborate, complex, and fully developed Neoplatonic systems.  He stands near the end of the pagan Greek development of philosophy, and was extremely influential on later Christian (Greek and Latin) and Islamic thought.
+
'''Proclus''' Lycaeus (February 8, 412 - April 17, 485),  surnamed "The Successor" or "''diadochos''" ([[Greek language|Greek]] Πρόκλος ὁ Διάδοχος ''Próklos ho Diádokhos''), was the last major [[Greek philosophy|Greek]] [[Neoplatonism|Neoplatonist]] [[philosophy|philosopher]].  His systematized and refined the cosmologies of [[Plotinus]] and [[Iamblichus]], and produced one of the most elaborate, complex, and fully developed Neoplatonic systems. His careful documentation of early Greek mathematicians in his commentary on [[Euclid]]’s ''Elements of Geometry'' is a valuable historical source.   
 +
{{toc}}
 +
Proclus’ greatest concern was the elevation of the human [[soul]] to unity with its divine origins.  Believing that reason could dominate the physical passions but was incapable of grasping higher levels of spiritual knowledge, he promoted [[theurgy]], the use of material objects and mathematical symbols in religious rites intended to awaken the soul to its own divinity. His works influenced later [[Christianity|Christian]] (Greek and Latin), [[Islam|Islamic]], and [[Judaism|Jewish]] thought. His ideas were adapted by [[Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite|Pseudo-Dionysius]] to add a new dimension to Christian theology, and translations of his works were widely studied by medieval and [[Renaissance]] scholars. 
  
::"Wherever there is number, there is beauty."
+
== Life ==
:Proclus, quoted by [[Morris Kline|M. Kline]], ''Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times''
+
Proclus was born 410 or 411 C.E. (his birth year is deduced from a horoscope cast by a disciple, Marinus) in [[Constantinople]] to a high-ranking family from Lycia.  His father, Patricius, was a prominent legal official in the court system of the [[Byzantine Empire]]. Proclus was raised in Xanthus, on the south coast of Lycia.  He went to [[Alexandria]], in Egypt, and studied [[logic|rhetoric]], [[philosophy]], and [[mathematics]] with the intention of pursuing a judicial position like his father. During his studies, he returned to Constantinople with his mentor Leonas, who had business there, and successfully practiced law for a short time.  From this experience he realized that he preferred philosophy to law. He returned to Alexandria, and began a determined study of the works of [[Aristotle]] under Olympiodorus the Elder, and of mathematics under a teacher named Heron (no relation to Hero of Alexandria).
  
==Biography==
+
Eventually, dissatisfied with the level of philosophical instruction available in Alexandria, Proclus went to [[Athens]] in 431 to study at the Academy founded eight hundred years earlier (387 B.C.E.) by [[Plato]].  There he was taught by [[Plutarch]] of Athens and Syrianus; in 450 he succeeded Syrianus as head of the Academy and received the title ''diadochus'' ("successor" to Plato).  He lived in Athens for the remainder of his life, except for one year of voluntary exile to escape political pressures. He spent his exile traveling in Asia and being initiated into various mystery cults, before returning to his post at the Academy in Athens.  His biographers report that he was very active; every day he gave five lectures or discussions, and wrote seven hundred lines.  Proclus never married; he was prosperous, gave generously to his friends, and was much sought after as a scholar and adviser.  He was a vegetarian and practiced theurgy and a number of religious rites, including the annual observation of the birthdays of Plato and [[Socrates]], fasting in honor of the Egyptian gods, and monthly ceremonies for the Great Mother.  Simplicius, writing one hundred years later, reported that all of the philosophers who associated with Proclus accepted his doctrine except for his student Asclepiodorus, who remained a free thinker and skeptic.
Proclus was born 410 or 411 C.E. (his birth year is deduced from a horoscope cast by a disciple, [[Marinus of Neapolis|Marinus]], and hence is to a degree uncertain) in [[Constantinople]] to a family of high social status in [[Lycia]]- his father Particius was a high legal official, very important in the [[Byzantine Empire]]'s court system- and raised in [[Xanthus]], he studied [[rhetoric]], [[philosophy]] and [[mathematics]] in [[Alexandria]] of [[Egypt]], with the intent of pursuing a judicial position like his father. He came back to Constantinopole part-way through his studies when his rector, his principal instructor (one [[Leonas]]) had business there, and was a successful praticing lawyer for a period.
 
  
Actually experiencing the practice of law made Proclus realize that he truly preferred philosophy. He returned to Alexandria, and began determinedly studying the works of [[Aristotle]] under [[Olympiodorus the Elder]] (he also began studying mathematics during this period as well with a teacher named Heron- no relation to [[Hero of Alexandria]] who was also known as Heron). Eventually, this gifted student became dissatisfied with the level of philosophical instruction available in Alexandria, and went to [[Athens]], the preeminent philosophical center of the day, in [[431]] to study at the Neoplatonic successor of the famous  [[Academy]] founded 800 years (in 387 B.C.E.) before by [[Plato]]; there he was taught by [[Plutarch of Athens]] and [[Syrianus]]; he succeeded Plutarch as head of the Academy, and would in turn be succeeded on his death by Syrianus. He died aged ~73, and was buried near [[Mount Lycabettus]] in a tomb.
+
Proclus died April 17, 485, and was buried in a tomb next to his teacher Syrianus, not far from Mount Lycabettus.  An epigram on the tomb reads: "I am Proclus, Lycian whom Syrianus brought up to teach his doctrine after him. This tomb reunites both our bodies. May an identical sejourn be reserved to our both souls!"
  
He lived in Athens as an unmarried vegetarian bachelor, prosperous and generous to his friends, until the end of his life, except for a voluntary one year exile, which was designed to lessen the pressure put on him by his political-philosophical activity, little appreciated by the Christian rulers; he spent the exile travelling and being initiated into various [[mystery cults]] as befitted his universalist approach to religion, trying to become "a priest of the entire universe."
+
== Works ==
 +
Proclus was a systematic writer, able to sustain clarity through long and elaborate explanations.  His works provided a careful recapitulation of the views of his predecessors, as well as his own astute analysis.  Since many of his original sources were later lost, his writings provide a valuable record of ancient thought.
  
==Works==
+
Proclus believed the true philosopher should pay homage to the gods of all nations, and become "a priest of the entire universe." He defended paganism and opposed Christianity, with its doctrine that the world was finiteHis open-minded approach gave his philosophical system a richness and depth that provided inspiration for many future thinkers.   
The majority of Proclus' works are commentaries on dialogues of [[Plato]] (''Alcibiades'', ''Cratylus'', ''Parmenides'', ''Republic'', ''Timaeus'').  In these commentaries he presents his own philosophical system as a faithful interpretation of Plato, and in this he did not differ from other Neoplatonists.  He was able to think of his own system in this way, much more complex and elaborate than the thought of Plato, because he considered the Platonic texts to be divinely inspired (''ho theios Platon'' — The divine Plato), and to speak often of things under a veil, hiding the truth from the philosophically uninitiateThis does not mean that his commentaries have nothing to do with the Platonic texts.  Proclus was a very close reader of Plato, and quite often makes very astute points about his Platonic sources.  However, one must expect for the most part to find the system of Proclus, rather than Plato, in these worksA number of his Platonic commentaries are lost.
 
  
Proclus also wrote a very influential commentary on the first book of [[Euclid]]'s ''Elements of Geometry''.  This commentary is one of the most valuable sources we have for the history of ancient mathematics, and its Platonic account of the status of mathematical objects was very influential.
+
The majority of Proclus' works are presented as commentaries on the dialogues of [[Plato]] (''Alcibiades,'' ''Cratylus,'' ''Parmenides,'' ''Republic,'' ''Timaeus'')Like other Neoplatonists, Proclus presented his own philosophical system, which was much more elaborate and complex, as a faithful interpretation of Plato.  He considered the Platonic texts to be divinely inspired (''ho theios Platon,'' “the divine Plato”), and believed that they contained a deeper meaning which was hidden from the philosophically uninitiated.
  
In addition to his commentaries, Proclus wrote two major systematic works.  The ''Elements of Theology'' is a singular work in the history of ancient philosophy.  It consists of 211 propositions, each followed by a proof, beginning from the existence of the One (the first principle of all things) and ending with the descent of individual souls into the material worldThe ''Platonic Theology'' is a systematisation of material from Platonic dialogues, showing from them the characteristics of the divine orders, the part of the universe which is closest to the One.
+
Proclus also wrote a valuable commentary on the first book of [[Euclid]]'s ''Elements of Geometry.'' This commentary is one of the most complete surviving sources for the history of ancient mathematics, presenting an overview of one thousand years of Greek mathematicsIts Platonic account of the status of mathematical objects was very influential.
  
We also have three small works, extant only in Latin translation: ''Ten doubts concerning providence''; ''On providence and fate''; ''On the existence of evils''.
+
In addition to his commentaries, Proclus wrote two major systematic works.  The ''Elements of Theology'' is a singular work in the history of ancient philosophy.  It consists of 211 [[Neoplatonism|Neoplatonic]] propositions, each followed by a proof, beginning from the existence of the One (the first principle of all things) and ending with the descent of individual souls into the material world.  The ''Platonic Theology'' is a systematization of material from Platonic dialogues, illustrating the characteristics of the divine orders, the part of the universe closest to the One.
  
He also wrote a number of minor works, which are listed in the bibliography below.
+
''Hypotyposis''  introduced the astronomical theories of [[Hipparchus]] and [[Ptolemy]] and described the mathematical theory of the planets based on epicycles and on eccentrics. Proclus gave a geometrical proof that the epicycle theory of planetary movement (in which Earth is the center of a circle with smaller circles rotating around its circumference)  is equivalent to the eccentric theory (in which the planets move in circles which do not have Earth as the center).  
  
==System==
+
Three small works, ''Ten Doubts Concerning Providence,'' ''On Providence and Fate,'' and ''On the Existence of Evils'' are extant only in Latin translation.   
Proclus' system, like that of the other Neoplatonists, is a combination of Platonic, Aristotelian, and Stoic elements.  In its broad outlines, Proclus' system agrees with that of [[Plotinus]].  However, following [[Iamblichus]], [[Plutarch]] of Athens (not to be confused with [[Plutarch of Chaeronea]]), and his master [[Syrianus]], Proclus presents a much more elaborate universe than Plotinus, subdividing the elements of Plotinus' system into their logically distinct parts, and positing these parts as individual things.  This multiplication of entities is balanced by the [[monism]] which is common to all Neoplatonists.  What this means is that, on the one hand the universe is composed of hierarchically distinct things, but on the other all things are part of a single continuous emanation of power from the One.  From this latter perspective, the many distinctions to be found in the universe are a result of the divided perspective of the human soul, which needs to make distinctions in its own thought in order to understand unified realitiesThe idealist tendency is taken further in John Scotus [[Eriugena]]
 
  
There is a double motivation found in Neoplatonic systems.  The first is a need to account for the origin and character of all things in the universe.  The second is a need to account for how we can know this origin and character of things.  These two aims are related: they begin from the assumption that we can know reality, and then ask the question of what reality must be like, in its origin and unfolding, so that we can know it.  An important element in the Neoplatonic answer to these questions is its reaction to [[Scepticism]].  In response to the sceptical position that we only know the appearances presented by our senses, and not the world as it is, Plotinus placed the object of knowledge inside the soul itself, and accounted for this interior truth through the soul's kinship with its own productive principles.
+
Proclus was a poet as well as philosopher and mathematician, and wrote a number of religious hymns.
  
'''The One'''
+
==Philosophy==
 +
=== Cosmology ===
 +
Proclus, like the other Neoplatonists, combined [[Plato|Platonic]], [[Aristotle|Aristotelian]], and [[Stoicism|Stoic]] elements in his thought.  He refined and systematized the elaborate metaphysical speculations of [[Iamblichus]].  In contrast to the skeptic position that the material universe is outside the human consciousness and can only be known through sensory impressions, the Neoplatonists emphasized the underlying unity of all things and placed the human soul and the material universe in a hierarchy of emanation from a universal being, in which every level is a reflection of that being.
  
The first principle in Neoplatonism is the One (''to Hen'')It is the principle which produces all Being.  For this reason, the Neoplatonists thought that the One could not itself be a being.  If it were a being, it would have a particular nature, and so could not be universally productive of all being.  Because it is ''beyond being'' (''epekeina tes ousias'' is a phrase from Plato's ''Republic'' 509b), it is also beyond thought, because thinking requires the determinations which belong to being: the division between subject and object, and the distinction of one thing from another.  For this reason, even the name ''The One'' isn't a positive name, but rather the most non-multiple name we can think of, a name derived from our own inadequate conception of the simplicity of the first principle.  The One causes all things by conferring unity on them, and in Neoplatonism existence, unity, and form tend to become equivalent.  The One causes things to exist by donating unity, and the particular manner in which a thing is one is its form (a dog and a house are one in different manners, for example)Because the One makes things exist by giving them the unity which makes them what they are, the Neoplatonists thought of it also as the source of the good of everything.  So the other name for the One is the Good.  The first principle isn't double, however.  Instead, all things have a double relation to it, as coming from it (One) and then being oriented back towards it to receive their perfection or completion (Good).
+
===  The One ===
 +
In [[Neoplatonism]], the first principle is the One ''(to Hen)''.  Since the One produces all Being, it cannot itself be a being.  The One is also beyond thought, because thinking requires the determinations which belong to being: The division between subject and object, and the distinction of one thing from another.  Even the appellation "the One" is derived from his own inadequate conception of the simplicity of the first principle.  The One confers unity on all things through forms, the intangible essences (ideas) which give each being its unique qualities.  Neoplatonists thought of the One as the source of the good, or perfection, of everything.   
  
The particular characteristic of Proclus' system is his insertion of a level of individual ones, called ''henads'' between the One itself and the divine Intellect, which is the second principle.  The henads are beyond being, like the One itself, but they stand at the head of chains of causation (''seirai'' or ''taxeis'') and in some manner give to these chains their particular character.  They are also identified with the traditional Greek gods, so one henad might be Apollo and be the cause of all things apollonian, while another might be Helios and be the cause of all ''sunny'' things.  The henads serve both to protect the One itself from any hint of muliplicity, and to draw up the rest of the universe towards the One, by being a connecting, intermediate stage between absolute unity and determinate multiplicity.
+
Proclus inserted a level of individual “ones,called ''henads'' between the ultimate One and the divine Intellect, which is the second principle.  The henads are beyond being, like the One itself, but they stand at the head of chains of causation ''(seirai'' or ''taxeis)'' and in some manner give to these chains their particular character.  They are also identified with the traditional Greek gods, so one henad might be Apollo and be the cause of all things apollonian, while another might be Helios and be the cause of all "sunny" things.  The henads serve both to protect the One itself from any hint of multiplicity, and to draw up the rest of the universe towards the One, by being a connecting, intermediate stage between absolute unity and determinate multiplicity.
  
In terms of his sources, the One is like a combination of the Platonic Form of the Good, because it confers being and intelligibility on all things, and Aristotle's Unmoved Mover, which is the ''final cause'' of all things.
+
The “One” of Proclus resembles a combination of the Platonic Form of the Good, which confers being and intelligibility on all things, and Aristotle's Unmoved Mover, which is the "final cause" of all things.
  
Coming between the One and the henads (some scholars think after the henads) are the two principle of First Limit and First Infinity, which are the principles of the fertile production (Infinity or Unlimited, ''apeiron'') and the controlled nature of the production (Limit, ''peras'') of all things.
+
Between the One and the henads (some scholars place it after the henads) are the two principles of First Limit (''peras,'' oneness) and First Infinity ''(apeiron)''.
  
'''Intellect'''
+
=== Intellect ===
 +
According to Proclus, the One produces a divine mind, Intellect ''(nous)'', which exists below the level of the henads.  Intellect is both Thinking and Being.  As Being, Intellect is the product of the One.  In Thinking, the Intellect attempts to grasp its cause, the One, as its Good (perfection).  The simplicity of the One does not allow the Intellect to grasp it, so the Intellect generates a succession of different perspectives of the One, which are the Platonic Forms, the first determinations into which all things fall.
  
The principle which is produced below the level of the One and the Henads is the divine Intellect (''Nous'').  The One cannot have a determinate nature if it to be the source of all determinate natures, so what it produces is the totality of all determinate natures, or BeingBy determination is meant existence within boundaries, being ''this'' and not ''that''.  The most important determinate natures are the ''Greatest Kinds'' from Plato's ''Sophist'' (Being, Same, Other, Rest, Motion) and Aristotle's ten categories (Quantity, Quality, etc.).  In other words, the One produces what Plato called the Forms, and the Forms are understood to be the first determinations into which all things fallThe One produces the Forms through the activity of thinking.  The One itself does not think, but instead produces a divine mind, Intellect, whose thoughts are themselves the Forms.  Intellect is both Thinking and Being.  It is a mind which has its own contents as its object.  All things relate to the first principle as both One and GoodAs Being, Intellect is the product of the One.  But it also seeks to return to its cause, and so in Thinking it attempt to grasp the One as its Good.  But because the simplicity of the One/Good does not allow Intellect to grasp it, what Intellect does is generate a succession of perspectives around its simple source.  Each of these perspectives is itself a Form, and is how Intellect generates for itself its own content.
+
[[Plotinus]] and [[Iamblichus]] spoke of the Intellect’s attempt to return to the One by Thinking as a form of desiringProclus systematized this concept into a three-fold motion of remaining (or abiding), procession, and return ''(mone, proodos, epistrophe)''Intellect remains in the One, as its origin.  It proceeds from the One, coming into being as a separate entitySimultaneously it returns to the One, so that it does not separate from its source, but receives its identity, its good (ideal state of being), from the One.  Proclus extended this three-fold motion of remaining, procession, and return to all the levels of being between the One and matter.
  
Plotinus speaks about the generation of Intellect from the One, and Intellect's attempt to return to the One in a thinking which is also a desiringProclus systematises this production through a three-fold movement of remaining, procession, and return (''mone, proodos, epistrophe'').  Intellect remains in the One, which means that it has the One as its origin.  It proceeds from the One, which means that it come to be as a separate entity.  But it returns to the One, which means that it doesn't cut itself off from its source, but receives the good which is its identity from the OneThis threefold motion is used by Proclus to structure all levels of his system below the One and above material reality, so that all things except those mentioned remain, proceed, and return.
+
Proclus elaborated his account of Intellect much farther than [[Plotinus]] had. Plotinus’ account of Intellect distinguished between Being and Thinking; Proclus added a third distinction in keeping with the structure of remaining, procession, and return.  Intellect was distinguished into Intellectual (the thinking subject), Intelligible (the object of thought), and Intelligible-Intellectual (the capacity of the object to be grasped by the thinking subject)These three distinctions were further elaborated: The intelligible was a triad of Being, Eternity, and the Living Being (or Paradigm, from Plato's ''Timaeus''); the intelligible-intellectual moment was also a triad; and the intellectual moment was a hebdomad (seven elements) including the Demiurge from Plato's ''Timaeus'' and also the monad of Time (which is before temporal things).  Proclus attempted give a hierarchical order to the various metaphysical elements and principles of earlier philosophers have discussed.
  
Proclus also gives a much more elaborate account of Intellect than does PlotinusIn Plotinus we find the distinction between Being and Thinking in IntellectProclus, in keeping which his triadic structure of remaining, procession, and return, distinguishes three moments in Intellect:  Intelligible, Intelligible-Intellectual, and IntellectualThe correspond to the object of thought, the power of the object to be grasped by the subject, and the thinking subjectThese three divisions are elaborated further, so that the intelligible moment consists of three triads (Being, Eternity, and the Living Being or Paradigm from Plato's ''Timaeus'').  The intelligible-intellectual moment also consists of three triads, and the intellectual moment is a hebdomad (seven elements), among which is numbered the Demiurge from Plato's ''Timaeus'' and also the monad of Time (which is before temporal things).  In this elaboration of Intellect as a whole, Proclus is attempting to give a hierarchical ordering to the various metaphysical elements and principles that other philosophers have discussed, by containing them within a single triadic logic of unfolding.
+
Proclus' universe unfolded from unity to multiplicity in the smallest possible stepsWith Intellect emerged the multiplicity which allowed one being to be different from another beingAs a divine mind, Intellect had a complete grasp of all its moments in one act of thought, and was therefore outside of TimeAs the second principle, Intellect also gave rise to individual intellects which occupied various positions within the cosmosEach level of the hierarchy “participated” in the level above it, and each level had a “universal” aspect, its Unparticipated Monad, which which was the culmination and unity of all the levels below it.
  
Proclus' universe unfolds according to the smallest steps possible, from unity to multiplicity. With Intellect emerges the multiplicity which allows one being to be different from another being.  But as a divine mind, Intellect has a complete grasp of all its moments in one act of thought.  For this reason, Intellect is outside of Time.
+
=== Soul ===
 +
Soul ''(Psyche)'' was the third principle in the Neoplatonic system, produced by Intellect.   Like Intellect, it was a mind, but it did grasp all of its own content as once.  Therefore Time came into existence, as a measure of Soul's movement from one object of thought to anotherIntellect tried to grasp the One, and produced its own ideas as its content.  Soul attempted to grasp Intellect in its return, and ended up producing its own secondary unfoldings of the Forms in Intellect.  Soul, in turn, produced Body, the material world.
  
Intellect as the second principle also gives rise to individual intellects, which hold various places within Proclus' cosmos.
+
In his commentary on Plato's ''Timaeus'' Proclus explained the role of the Soul as a principle in mediating the Forms in Intellect to the body of the material world.  The Soul is constructed through certain portions, described mathematically in the ''Timaeus'', which allow it to make Body as a divided image of its own arithmetical and geometrical ideas.
  
In terms of his sources, Intellect is a like taking the Platonic Forms and placing them in the self-thinking thought which is Aristotle's Unmoved Mover.
+
Individual souls had the same basic structure as the principle of Soul, but they were fascinated with the material world, overpowered by it, and united with a material body through birth.  In an embodied soul, passions had a tendency to overwhelm reason.  According to Proclus, philosophy was the activity which could liberate the soul from being subject to bodily passions; remind it of its origin in Soul, Intellect, and the One; and prepare it not only to ascend to the higher levels while still in this life, but to avoid falling immediately back into a new body after death.
  
'''Soul'''
+
The highest goal, however, was not the elevation of reason, but unity of the individual soul with the Intellect. The faculty of reason belonged to the level of the individual soul and therefore could not elevate it beyond this level.  Proclus believed that the practice of theurgy directed the attention of an embodied soul towards its origin in the intelligible world.  The characteristics of the gods (the ''henads'') were imprinted on each level of their series of causation down to the material world.  By contemplating certain objects and symbols, and performing certain rites, the soul could rediscover these characteristics in itself and gradually ascend the causal series to its origin.  The rites of theurgy also attracted the assistance, or elevating power, of the appropriate ''henads.'' Proclus himself was a devotee of all of the pagan cults in Athens, considering that the power of the gods was present in all these various ways.
  
Soul (''Psuche'') is produced by Intellect, and so is the third principle in the Neoplatonic system.  It is a mind, like Intellect, but it does not grasp all of its own content as once.  Therefore with Soul, Time comes to be, as a measure of Soul's movement from one object of thought to anotherIntellect tries to grasp the One, and ends up producing its own ideas as its contentSoul attempts to grasp Intellect in its return, and ends up producing its own secondary unfoldings of the Forms in Intellect.  Soul, in turn, produces Body, the material world.
+
=== Ethics ===
 +
For Neoplatonists, an understanding of the cosmos was a necessary guide to achieving a life of goodness, and therefore, [[happiness]]Since the “One” was also the “Good,” the goodness of anything could be determined by how well it reflected its origin and fulfilled its purpose in natureProclus took an interest in diverse subjects, and also perceived music and literary works such as Homer as sources of truth.
  
In his commentary on Plato's ''Timaeus'' Proclus explains the role the Soul as a principle has in mediating the Forms in Intellect to the body of the material world as a whole.  The Soul is constructed through certain portions, described mathematically in the ''Timaeus'', which allow it to make Body as a divided image of its own arithmetical and geometrical ideas.
+
== Influence ==
 +
Proclus was the last major Greek philosopher, and was influential in spreading Neoplatonic ideas throughout the post-pagan Byzantine, Islamic, and Roman worlds.
  
Individual souls have the same overall structure as the principle of Soul, but they are weakerThey have a tendency to be fascinated with the material world, and be overpowered by it.  It is at this point that individual souls are united with a material body (i.e. when they are born). Once in the body, our passions have a tendency to overwhelm our reasonAccording to Proclus, philosophy is the activity which can liberate the soul from a subjection to bodily passions, remind it of its origin in Soul, Intellect, and the One, and prepare it not only to ascend to the higher levels while still in this life, but to avoid falling immediately back into a new body after death.
+
Proclus' works had a great influence on the history of western philosophyAround 500 C.E., a Christian Neoplatonist presenting himself as Dionysius the Aeropagite, an Athenian convert of St. Paul, wrote several treatises and letters adapting Proclus’ cosmology and his ideas regarding religious purification to a Christian world viewThe writings of Pseudo-Dionysius were regarded as having almost apostolic authority, and made their way into the doctrine of the Christian church.
  
Because the soul's attention, while inhabiting a body, is turned so far away from its origin in the intelligible world, Proclus thinks that we need to make use of bodily reminders of our spiritual origin. In this he agrees with the doctrines of [[theurgy]] put forward by Iamblichus.  Theurgy is possible because the powers of the gods (the ''henads'') extend through their series of causation even down to the material world.  And by certain power-laden words, acts, and objects, the soul can be drawn back up the series, so to speakProclus himself was a devotee of all of the pagan cults in Athens, considering that the power of the gods was present in all these various ways.
+
[[Boethius]]'s (480–525) ''Consolation of Philosophy,'' written in prison while awaiting execution, contains several principles and themes drawn from Proclus. The central poem of Book III is a precis of Proclus' ''Commentary on the Timaeus,'' and Book V contains the principle that things are known not according to their own nature, but according to the character of the knowing subject''Consolation of Philosophy'' was popular at the court of King [[Charlemagne]] during the ninth century and was later translated into English by [[Chaucer]]. It was studied throughout Europe from the fifteenth century onwards.
  
From Proclus philosophy is important, because it is one of the primary ways to rescue the soul from a fascination with the body, and restore it to its stationHowever, beyond its own station, the soul has Intellect as its goal, and ultimately has unification with the One as it goal.  So higher than philosophy is the non-discursive reason of Intellect, and the pre-intellectual unity of the One.  Philosophy is therefore a means of its own overcoming, in that it points the soul beyond itself.
+
A summary of Proclus' ''Elements of Theology'' circulated under the name ''Liber de Causis'' (the ''Book of Causes'') in the Arabic world as a work of Aristotle.  When translated into Latin it had great authority because of its supposed Aristotelian origin, and it was only when Proclus' ''Elements'' were translated into Latin that [[Thomas Aquinas]] realized its true sourceIn the thirteenth century, William of Moerbeke's Latin translation of the ''Elements of Theology'' (as ''Institutio Theologica'') became the principal sources for medieval knowledge of Platonic philosophy, and helped to lay the foundation for the [[Renaissance]] revival of [[Neoplatonism]].
  
==Influence==
+
The German-Jewish scholar [[Leo Baeck]] (1873-1956) suggested that the Gnostic-Proto-Kabbalistic text, the ''Sefer Yetzirah,'' "in its thought as well as in its terminology, is dependent upon the teaching of Proclus, the last great Neoplatonist. Furthermore, the decisive passages of the Sefer Yetzirah are none other than the transference of this Greek scholastic's system into Jewish thought and biblical language."
Proclus' works had a great influence on the history of western philosophy.  The extent of this influence, however, is obscured by the channels through which it was exercised.  By far the greatest transmission of Procline ideas was through the [[Pseudo-Dionysius]].  This 5th century Christian Greek author wrote under the pseudonym [[Dionysius]] the Areopagite, the figure converted by St. Paul in Athens.  Because of this fiction, his writings were taken to have almost apostolic authority.  He is an original thinker, and a Christian rather than a pagan, but in his writings can be found a great number of Procline metaphysical principles.  Another important source for Procline influence on the Middle Ages is [[Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius|Boethius]]' ''Consolation of Philosophy'', which has a number of Proclus principles and motifs.  The central poem of Book III is a precis of Proclus' ''Commentary on the Timaeus'', and Book V contains the important Procline principle that things are known not according to their own nature, but according to the character of the knowing subject.  A precis of Proclus' ''Elements of Theology'' circulated under the name ''Liber de Causis'' (the ''Book of Causes'').  This book is of uncertain origin, but circulated in the Arabic world as a work of Aristotle, and was translated into Latin as such.  It had great authority because of its supposed Aristotelian origin, and it was only when Proclus' ''Elements'' were translated into Latin that Thomas Aquinas realised its true origin.  Proclus' works also exercised an influence during the Renaissance through figures such as George Gemistios [[Plethon]] and Marsilio [[Ficino]].  Before the contemporary period, the most ardent promoter of Proclus in the English speaking world was [[Thomas Taylor]], who produced English translations of a number of his works.
 
  
His work inspired the New England Transcendentalists, including Ralph Waldo Emerson, who declared in 1843 that, in reading Proclus, "I am filled with hilarity & spring, my heart dances, my sight is quickened, I behold shining relations between all beings, and am impelled to write and almost to sing."
+
Proclus' works also exercised an influence during the [[Renaissance]] through figures such as [[George Gemistios Plethon]] and [[Marsilio Ficino]].  Before the contemporary period, the most ardent promoter of Proclus in the English speaking world was [[Thomas Taylor]], who produced English translations of a number of his works.
  
Modern scholarship on Proclus essentially begins with E.R. Dodd's edition of the ''Elements of Theology'' in 1933.  Since then he has atracted considerable attention, especially in the French-speaking world.  Procline scholarship, however, still (2006) falls far short of the attention paid to Plotinus.
+
The works of Proclus inspired the [[New England Transcendentalists]], including [[Ralph Waldo Emerson]], who declared in 1843 that, in reading Proclus, "I am filled with hilarity & spring, my heart dances, my sight is quickened, I behold shining relations between all beings, and am impelled to write and almost to sing."
  
The following epigram is engraved on the tomb which houses Proclus and his master Syrianus:
+
The Moon's Proclus Crater is named after him.
 
 
:''"I am Proclus,''
 
:''Lycian whom Syrianus brought up to teach his doctrine after him.''
 
:''This tomb reunites both our bodies.''
 
:''May an identical sejourn be reserved to our both souls!"''
 
 
 
The Moon's [[Proclus (crater)|Proclus crater]] is named after him.
 
  
 
==Bibliography==
 
==Bibliography==
 
'''Proclus' Works'''
 
'''Proclus' Works'''
*''Platonic Theology'': A long (six volumes in the [[Collection Budé|Budé]] edition) systematic work, using evidence from Plato's dialogues to describe the character of the various divine orders
+
*''Platonic Theology:''  A long (six volumes in the Budé edition) systematic work, using evidence from Plato's dialogues to describe the character of the various divine orders
*''Elements of Theology'': A systematic work, with 211 propositions and proofs, describing the universe from the first principle, the One, to the descent of souls into bodies
+
*''Elements of Theology:''  A systematic work, with 211 propositions and proofs, describing the universe from the first principle, the One, to the descent of souls into bodies
 
*''Elements of Physics''
 
*''Elements of Physics''
 
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Alcibiades I"'' (it is disputed whether or not this dialogue was written by Plato, but the Neoplatonists thought it was)
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Alcibiades I"'' (it is disputed whether or not this dialogue was written by Plato, but the Neoplatonists thought it was)
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Cratylus"''
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Cratylus"''
Line 93: Line 91:
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Republic"''
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Republic"''
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Timaeus"''
 
*''Commentary on Plato's "Timaeus"''
 
 
*''Commentary on the first book of Euclid's "Elements of Geometry"''
 
*''Commentary on the first book of Euclid's "Elements of Geometry"''
  
*Three small works:  ''Ten doubts concerning providence''; ''On providence and fate''; ''On the existence of evils''
+
*Three small works:  ''Ten Doubts Concerning Providence''; ''On Providence and Fate''; ''On the Existence of Evils''
  
 
*Various ''Hymns'' (fragments)
 
*Various ''Hymns'' (fragments)
 
*''Commentary on the Chaldaean Oracles'' (fragments)
 
*''Commentary on the Chaldaean Oracles'' (fragments)
  
*''The life of Proclus, or On Happiness'': written by his pupil, Marinus
+
*''The Life of Proclus, or On Happiness'': written by his pupil, Marinus
  
 
A number of other minor works or fragments of works survive.  A number of major commentaries have been lost.
 
A number of other minor works or fragments of works survive.  A number of major commentaries have been lost.
  
The ''Liber de Causis'' (Book of Causis) is not a work by Proclus, but a précis of his work the ''Elements of Theology'', likely written by an Arabic interpreter.  It was mistakenly thought in the Middle Ages to be a work of Aristotle, but was recognised by Aquinas not to be so.
+
The ''Liber de Causis'' (Book of Causis) is not a work by Proclus, but a précis of his work the ''Elements of Theology,'' likely written by an Arabic interpreter.  It was mistakenly thought in the Middle Ages to be a work of Aristotle.
  
[http://www.hiw.kuleuven.ac.be/dwmc/plato/proclus/proeditions.htm Here is a complete list of editions and translations of works that survive]
+
== References ==
 
+
*Bos, E. P. and P.A. Meijer (Eds). ''On Proclus and His Influence in Medieval Philosophy.'' (Philosophia antiqua 53), Leiden-Köln-New York: Brill, 1992.
'''Secondary Sources: Monographs'''
+
*Cleary, J. ''The Perennial Tradition of Neoplatonism.'' Leuven: Leuven University Press, 1997.
*''Proklos: Grundzüge seiner Metaphysik'', by Werner Bierwaltes
+
*Dodds, E. R. (Ed). ''The Elements of Theology: A Revised Text with Translation, Introduction, and Commentary.'' Oxford University Press, 1992.
*''L'Un et L'Âme selon Proclos'', by Jean Trouillard
+
*Proclus; Morrow, Glenn R. (Translator). ''Proclus.'' Princeton University Press; Reprint edition, 1992.  
*''La mystagogie de Proclos'', by Jean Trouillard
+
*Proclus; Morrow, Glenn R. (Translator), Dillon, John M. (Translator). ''Proclus' Commentary on Plato's "Parmenides."'' Princeton University Press; Reprint edition, 1992.
*''KINESIS AKINETOS: A study of spiritual motion in the philosophy of Proclus'', by Stephen Gersh
+
*Siorvanes, Lucas. ''Proclus: Neo-Platonic Philosophy and Science.'' Yale University Press, 1997.
*''From Iamblichus to Eriugena. An investigation of the prehistory and evolution of the Pseudo-Dionysius tradition'', by Stephen Gersh
+
*Taylor, Thomas. ''Proclus the Neoplatonic Philosopher.'' Kessinger Publishing; Facsimile Ed edition, 1997.  
*''L'architecture du divin. Mathématique et Philosophie chez Plotin et Proclus'', by Annick Charles-Saget
+
*Taylor, Thomas. ''Commentaries of Proclus on the Timæus of Plato, Part 1''. Kessinger Publishing, 2002.
*''Proclus: Neoplatonic philosophy and science'', by Lucas Siorvanes
 
'''Collections of essays'''
 
*''Proclus et son influence, actes du Colloque de Neuchatel, Juin, 1985.''  Zürich:  Éditions du Grand Midi, 1987.
 
*''Proclus lecteur et interprète des anciens.  Actes du Colloque internationale du C.N.R.S., Paris 2-4 oct. 1985.''  J. Pépin et H.-D. Saffrey.  Paris: C.N.R.S., 1987.
 
*''On Proclus and his Influence in Medieval Philosophy'', ed. by E.P. Bos and P.A. Meijer (Philosophia antiqua 53), Leiden-Köln-New York: Brill, 1992.
 
*''The perennial tradition of neoplatonism'', ed. by J. Cleary (Ancient and medieval philosophy, Series I 24), Leuven: Leuven University Press, 1997.
 
*''Proclus et la Théologie platonicienne: actes du colloque international de Louvain (13-16 mai 1998) en l'honneur de H. D. Saffrey et L. G. Westerink'', éd. par A.-Ph. Segonds et C. Steel (Ancient and medieval philosophy, Series I 26), Leuven-Paris: Leuven University Press / Les Belles Lettres, 2000.
 
'''Bibliography'''
 
*''Proclo, negli ultimi quarant' anni. Bibliografia ragionata delle letteratura primaria e secondaria riguardante il pensiero procliano e i suoi influssi storici (anni 1949-1992)'', by Nicoletta Scotti Muth
 
*[http://www.hiw.kuleuven.ac.be/dwmc/plato/proclus/probiblio.htm Bibliography from 1990 to 2002]
 
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
*[http://search.eb.com.ezproxy.rit.edu/eb/article-9061472 Article] by [[Encyclopædia Britannica]]
+
All links retrieved November 30, 2022.
*{{MacTutor|id=Proclus}}
+
*[http://www.goddess-athena.org/Encyclopedia/Friends/Proclus/ Article at The Encyclopedia of Goddess Athena].  
*[http://www.goddess-athena.org/Encyclopedia/Friends/Proclus/ Article] at "The Encyclopedia of Goddess Athena"[http://www.goddess-athena.org/Encyclopedia/index.htm]
+
*[http://web.archive.org/web/20001210155000/http://dspace.dial.pipex.com/chthonios/proclus-signs.htm ''On the Signs of Divine Possession''] - (partial translation of Proclus' work).
*[http://www.kheper.net/topics/Neoplatonism/Proclus-lifeof.html Proclus's Life and Teachings]
+
*[http://web.archive.org/web/20001210145900/http://dspace.dial.pipex.com/chthonios/proclus-sacred.htm ''On the Sacred Art''] - (translation and discussion of this surviving extract from a larger work by Proclus).
*[http://www.hiw.kuleuven.ac.be/dwmc/plato/proclus/index.htm Index page] of the Proclus section for the "[http://www.hiw.kuleuven.ac.be/dwmc/plato/about/theproject.htm Plato Transformed]" project
 
*[http://web.archive.org/web/20001210155000/http://dspace.dial.pipex.com/chthonios/proclus-signs.htm ''On the Signs of Divine Possession''] - (partial translation of Proclus' work)
 
*[http://web.archive.org/web/20001210145900/http://dspace.dial.pipex.com/chthonios/proclus-sacred.htm ''On the Sacred Art''] - (translation and discussion of this surviving extract from a larger work by Proclus)
 
 
 
[[Category:Ancient philosophers]]
 
[[Category:Roman era philosophers]]
 
[[Category:Late Antiquity]]
 
[[Category:Neoplatonists]]
 
[[Category:Byzantine philosophers]]
 
[[Category:412 births]]
 
[[Category:487 deaths]]
 
[[Category:Anti-Gnosticism]]
 
  
[[ca:Procle]]
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
[[de:Proklos (Philosoph)]]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
[[fr:Proclos]]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
[[it:Proclo]]
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
[[nl:Proclus]]
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
[[pl:Prokul]]
 
[[pt:Proclo]]
 
[[ru:Прокл]]
 
[[sk:Proklos]]
 
[[sl:Prokl]]
 
[[fi:Proklos]]
 
[[sv:Proklos]]
 
  
 +
[[Category:Philosophers]]
 +
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
  
 
{{Credit|77860999}}
 
{{Credit|77860999}}

Latest revision as of 23:05, 30 November 2022

Proclus Lycaeus (February 8, 412 - April 17, 485), surnamed "The Successor" or "diadochos" (Greek Πρόκλος ὁ Διάδοχος Próklos ho Diádokhos), was the last major Greek Neoplatonist philosopher. His systematized and refined the cosmologies of Plotinus and Iamblichus, and produced one of the most elaborate, complex, and fully developed Neoplatonic systems. His careful documentation of early Greek mathematicians in his commentary on Euclid’s Elements of Geometry is a valuable historical source.

Proclus’ greatest concern was the elevation of the human soul to unity with its divine origins. Believing that reason could dominate the physical passions but was incapable of grasping higher levels of spiritual knowledge, he promoted theurgy, the use of material objects and mathematical symbols in religious rites intended to awaken the soul to its own divinity. His works influenced later Christian (Greek and Latin), Islamic, and Jewish thought. His ideas were adapted by Pseudo-Dionysius to add a new dimension to Christian theology, and translations of his works were widely studied by medieval and Renaissance scholars.

Life

Proclus was born 410 or 411 C.E. (his birth year is deduced from a horoscope cast by a disciple, Marinus) in Constantinople to a high-ranking family from Lycia. His father, Patricius, was a prominent legal official in the court system of the Byzantine Empire. Proclus was raised in Xanthus, on the south coast of Lycia. He went to Alexandria, in Egypt, and studied rhetoric, philosophy, and mathematics with the intention of pursuing a judicial position like his father. During his studies, he returned to Constantinople with his mentor Leonas, who had business there, and successfully practiced law for a short time. From this experience he realized that he preferred philosophy to law. He returned to Alexandria, and began a determined study of the works of Aristotle under Olympiodorus the Elder, and of mathematics under a teacher named Heron (no relation to Hero of Alexandria).

Eventually, dissatisfied with the level of philosophical instruction available in Alexandria, Proclus went to Athens in 431 to study at the Academy founded eight hundred years earlier (387 B.C.E.) by Plato. There he was taught by Plutarch of Athens and Syrianus; in 450 he succeeded Syrianus as head of the Academy and received the title diadochus ("successor" to Plato). He lived in Athens for the remainder of his life, except for one year of voluntary exile to escape political pressures. He spent his exile traveling in Asia and being initiated into various mystery cults, before returning to his post at the Academy in Athens. His biographers report that he was very active; every day he gave five lectures or discussions, and wrote seven hundred lines. Proclus never married; he was prosperous, gave generously to his friends, and was much sought after as a scholar and adviser. He was a vegetarian and practiced theurgy and a number of religious rites, including the annual observation of the birthdays of Plato and Socrates, fasting in honor of the Egyptian gods, and monthly ceremonies for the Great Mother. Simplicius, writing one hundred years later, reported that all of the philosophers who associated with Proclus accepted his doctrine except for his student Asclepiodorus, who remained a free thinker and skeptic.

Proclus died April 17, 485, and was buried in a tomb next to his teacher Syrianus, not far from Mount Lycabettus. An epigram on the tomb reads: "I am Proclus, Lycian whom Syrianus brought up to teach his doctrine after him. This tomb reunites both our bodies. May an identical sejourn be reserved to our both souls!"

Works

Proclus was a systematic writer, able to sustain clarity through long and elaborate explanations. His works provided a careful recapitulation of the views of his predecessors, as well as his own astute analysis. Since many of his original sources were later lost, his writings provide a valuable record of ancient thought.

Proclus believed the true philosopher should pay homage to the gods of all nations, and become "a priest of the entire universe." He defended paganism and opposed Christianity, with its doctrine that the world was finite. His open-minded approach gave his philosophical system a richness and depth that provided inspiration for many future thinkers.

The majority of Proclus' works are presented as commentaries on the dialogues of Plato (Alcibiades, Cratylus, Parmenides, Republic, Timaeus). Like other Neoplatonists, Proclus presented his own philosophical system, which was much more elaborate and complex, as a faithful interpretation of Plato. He considered the Platonic texts to be divinely inspired (ho theios Platon, “the divine Plato”), and believed that they contained a deeper meaning which was hidden from the philosophically uninitiated.

Proclus also wrote a valuable commentary on the first book of Euclid's Elements of Geometry. This commentary is one of the most complete surviving sources for the history of ancient mathematics, presenting an overview of one thousand years of Greek mathematics. Its Platonic account of the status of mathematical objects was very influential.

In addition to his commentaries, Proclus wrote two major systematic works. The Elements of Theology is a singular work in the history of ancient philosophy. It consists of 211 Neoplatonic propositions, each followed by a proof, beginning from the existence of the One (the first principle of all things) and ending with the descent of individual souls into the material world. The Platonic Theology is a systematization of material from Platonic dialogues, illustrating the characteristics of the divine orders, the part of the universe closest to the One.

Hypotyposis introduced the astronomical theories of Hipparchus and Ptolemy and described the mathematical theory of the planets based on epicycles and on eccentrics. Proclus gave a geometrical proof that the epicycle theory of planetary movement (in which Earth is the center of a circle with smaller circles rotating around its circumference) is equivalent to the eccentric theory (in which the planets move in circles which do not have Earth as the center).

Three small works, Ten Doubts Concerning Providence, On Providence and Fate, and On the Existence of Evils are extant only in Latin translation.

Proclus was a poet as well as philosopher and mathematician, and wrote a number of religious hymns.

Philosophy

Cosmology

Proclus, like the other Neoplatonists, combined Platonic, Aristotelian, and Stoic elements in his thought. He refined and systematized the elaborate metaphysical speculations of Iamblichus. In contrast to the skeptic position that the material universe is outside the human consciousness and can only be known through sensory impressions, the Neoplatonists emphasized the underlying unity of all things and placed the human soul and the material universe in a hierarchy of emanation from a universal being, in which every level is a reflection of that being.

The One

In Neoplatonism, the first principle is the One (to Hen). Since the One produces all Being, it cannot itself be a being. The One is also beyond thought, because thinking requires the determinations which belong to being: The division between subject and object, and the distinction of one thing from another. Even the appellation "the One" is derived from his own inadequate conception of the simplicity of the first principle. The One confers unity on all things through forms, the intangible essences (ideas) which give each being its unique qualities. Neoplatonists thought of the One as the source of the good, or perfection, of everything.

Proclus inserted a level of individual “ones,” called henads between the ultimate One and the divine Intellect, which is the second principle. The henads are beyond being, like the One itself, but they stand at the head of chains of causation (seirai or taxeis) and in some manner give to these chains their particular character. They are also identified with the traditional Greek gods, so one henad might be Apollo and be the cause of all things apollonian, while another might be Helios and be the cause of all "sunny" things. The henads serve both to protect the One itself from any hint of multiplicity, and to draw up the rest of the universe towards the One, by being a connecting, intermediate stage between absolute unity and determinate multiplicity.

The “One” of Proclus resembles a combination of the Platonic Form of the Good, which confers being and intelligibility on all things, and Aristotle's Unmoved Mover, which is the "final cause" of all things.

Between the One and the henads (some scholars place it after the henads) are the two principles of First Limit (peras, oneness) and First Infinity (apeiron).

Intellect

According to Proclus, the One produces a divine mind, Intellect (nous), which exists below the level of the henads. Intellect is both Thinking and Being. As Being, Intellect is the product of the One. In Thinking, the Intellect attempts to grasp its cause, the One, as its Good (perfection). The simplicity of the One does not allow the Intellect to grasp it, so the Intellect generates a succession of different perspectives of the One, which are the Platonic Forms, the first determinations into which all things fall.

Plotinus and Iamblichus spoke of the Intellect’s attempt to return to the One by Thinking as a form of desiring. Proclus systematized this concept into a three-fold motion of remaining (or abiding), procession, and return (mone, proodos, epistrophe). Intellect remains in the One, as its origin. It proceeds from the One, coming into being as a separate entity. Simultaneously it returns to the One, so that it does not separate from its source, but receives its identity, its good (ideal state of being), from the One. Proclus extended this three-fold motion of remaining, procession, and return to all the levels of being between the One and matter.

Proclus elaborated his account of Intellect much farther than Plotinus had. Plotinus’ account of Intellect distinguished between Being and Thinking; Proclus added a third distinction in keeping with the structure of remaining, procession, and return. Intellect was distinguished into Intellectual (the thinking subject), Intelligible (the object of thought), and Intelligible-Intellectual (the capacity of the object to be grasped by the thinking subject). These three distinctions were further elaborated: The intelligible was a triad of Being, Eternity, and the Living Being (or Paradigm, from Plato's Timaeus); the intelligible-intellectual moment was also a triad; and the intellectual moment was a hebdomad (seven elements) including the Demiurge from Plato's Timaeus and also the monad of Time (which is before temporal things). Proclus attempted give a hierarchical order to the various metaphysical elements and principles of earlier philosophers have discussed.

Proclus' universe unfolded from unity to multiplicity in the smallest possible steps. With Intellect emerged the multiplicity which allowed one being to be different from another being. As a divine mind, Intellect had a complete grasp of all its moments in one act of thought, and was therefore outside of Time. As the second principle, Intellect also gave rise to individual intellects which occupied various positions within the cosmos. Each level of the hierarchy “participated” in the level above it, and each level had a “universal” aspect, its Unparticipated Monad, which which was the culmination and unity of all the levels below it.

Soul

Soul (Psyche) was the third principle in the Neoplatonic system, produced by Intellect. Like Intellect, it was a mind, but it did grasp all of its own content as once. Therefore Time came into existence, as a measure of Soul's movement from one object of thought to another. Intellect tried to grasp the One, and produced its own ideas as its content. Soul attempted to grasp Intellect in its return, and ended up producing its own secondary unfoldings of the Forms in Intellect. Soul, in turn, produced Body, the material world.

In his commentary on Plato's Timaeus Proclus explained the role of the Soul as a principle in mediating the Forms in Intellect to the body of the material world. The Soul is constructed through certain portions, described mathematically in the Timaeus, which allow it to make Body as a divided image of its own arithmetical and geometrical ideas.

Individual souls had the same basic structure as the principle of Soul, but they were fascinated with the material world, overpowered by it, and united with a material body through birth. In an embodied soul, passions had a tendency to overwhelm reason. According to Proclus, philosophy was the activity which could liberate the soul from being subject to bodily passions; remind it of its origin in Soul, Intellect, and the One; and prepare it not only to ascend to the higher levels while still in this life, but to avoid falling immediately back into a new body after death.

The highest goal, however, was not the elevation of reason, but unity of the individual soul with the Intellect. The faculty of reason belonged to the level of the individual soul and therefore could not elevate it beyond this level. Proclus believed that the practice of theurgy directed the attention of an embodied soul towards its origin in the intelligible world. The characteristics of the gods (the henads) were imprinted on each level of their series of causation down to the material world. By contemplating certain objects and symbols, and performing certain rites, the soul could rediscover these characteristics in itself and gradually ascend the causal series to its origin. The rites of theurgy also attracted the assistance, or elevating power, of the appropriate henads. Proclus himself was a devotee of all of the pagan cults in Athens, considering that the power of the gods was present in all these various ways.

Ethics

For Neoplatonists, an understanding of the cosmos was a necessary guide to achieving a life of goodness, and therefore, happiness. Since the “One” was also the “Good,” the goodness of anything could be determined by how well it reflected its origin and fulfilled its purpose in nature. Proclus took an interest in diverse subjects, and also perceived music and literary works such as Homer as sources of truth.

Influence

Proclus was the last major Greek philosopher, and was influential in spreading Neoplatonic ideas throughout the post-pagan Byzantine, Islamic, and Roman worlds.

Proclus' works had a great influence on the history of western philosophy. Around 500 C.E., a Christian Neoplatonist presenting himself as Dionysius the Aeropagite, an Athenian convert of St. Paul, wrote several treatises and letters adapting Proclus’ cosmology and his ideas regarding religious purification to a Christian world view. The writings of Pseudo-Dionysius were regarded as having almost apostolic authority, and made their way into the doctrine of the Christian church.

Boethius's (480–525) Consolation of Philosophy, written in prison while awaiting execution, contains several principles and themes drawn from Proclus. The central poem of Book III is a precis of Proclus' Commentary on the Timaeus, and Book V contains the principle that things are known not according to their own nature, but according to the character of the knowing subject. Consolation of Philosophy was popular at the court of King Charlemagne during the ninth century and was later translated into English by Chaucer. It was studied throughout Europe from the fifteenth century onwards.

A summary of Proclus' Elements of Theology circulated under the name Liber de Causis (the Book of Causes) in the Arabic world as a work of Aristotle. When translated into Latin it had great authority because of its supposed Aristotelian origin, and it was only when Proclus' Elements were translated into Latin that Thomas Aquinas realized its true source. In the thirteenth century, William of Moerbeke's Latin translation of the Elements of Theology (as Institutio Theologica) became the principal sources for medieval knowledge of Platonic philosophy, and helped to lay the foundation for the Renaissance revival of Neoplatonism.

The German-Jewish scholar Leo Baeck (1873-1956) suggested that the Gnostic-Proto-Kabbalistic text, the Sefer Yetzirah, "in its thought as well as in its terminology, is dependent upon the teaching of Proclus, the last great Neoplatonist. Furthermore, the decisive passages of the Sefer Yetzirah are none other than the transference of this Greek scholastic's system into Jewish thought and biblical language."

Proclus' works also exercised an influence during the Renaissance through figures such as George Gemistios Plethon and Marsilio Ficino. Before the contemporary period, the most ardent promoter of Proclus in the English speaking world was Thomas Taylor, who produced English translations of a number of his works.

The works of Proclus inspired the New England Transcendentalists, including Ralph Waldo Emerson, who declared in 1843 that, in reading Proclus, "I am filled with hilarity & spring, my heart dances, my sight is quickened, I behold shining relations between all beings, and am impelled to write and almost to sing."

The Moon's Proclus Crater is named after him.

Bibliography

Proclus' Works

  • Platonic Theology: A long (six volumes in the Budé edition) systematic work, using evidence from Plato's dialogues to describe the character of the various divine orders
  • Elements of Theology: A systematic work, with 211 propositions and proofs, describing the universe from the first principle, the One, to the descent of souls into bodies
  • Elements of Physics
  • Commentary on Plato's "Alcibiades I" (it is disputed whether or not this dialogue was written by Plato, but the Neoplatonists thought it was)
  • Commentary on Plato's "Cratylus"
  • Commentary on Plato's "Parmenides"
  • Commentary on Plato's "Republic"
  • Commentary on Plato's "Timaeus"
  • Commentary on the first book of Euclid's "Elements of Geometry"
  • Three small works: Ten Doubts Concerning Providence; On Providence and Fate; On the Existence of Evils
  • Various Hymns (fragments)
  • Commentary on the Chaldaean Oracles (fragments)
  • The Life of Proclus, or On Happiness: written by his pupil, Marinus

A number of other minor works or fragments of works survive. A number of major commentaries have been lost.

The Liber de Causis (Book of Causis) is not a work by Proclus, but a précis of his work the Elements of Theology, likely written by an Arabic interpreter. It was mistakenly thought in the Middle Ages to be a work of Aristotle.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Bos, E. P. and P.A. Meijer (Eds). On Proclus and His Influence in Medieval Philosophy. (Philosophia antiqua 53), Leiden-Köln-New York: Brill, 1992.
  • Cleary, J. The Perennial Tradition of Neoplatonism. Leuven: Leuven University Press, 1997.
  • Dodds, E. R. (Ed). The Elements of Theology: A Revised Text with Translation, Introduction, and Commentary. Oxford University Press, 1992.
  • Proclus; Morrow, Glenn R. (Translator). Proclus. Princeton University Press; Reprint edition, 1992.
  • Proclus; Morrow, Glenn R. (Translator), Dillon, John M. (Translator). Proclus' Commentary on Plato's "Parmenides." Princeton University Press; Reprint edition, 1992.
  • Siorvanes, Lucas. Proclus: Neo-Platonic Philosophy and Science. Yale University Press, 1997.
  • Taylor, Thomas. Proclus the Neoplatonic Philosopher. Kessinger Publishing; Facsimile Ed edition, 1997.
  • Taylor, Thomas. Commentaries of Proclus on the Timæus of Plato, Part 1. Kessinger Publishing, 2002.

External links

All links retrieved November 30, 2022.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.