Difference between revisions of "Fallacy" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m
 
(14 intermediate revisions by 6 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
A '''fallacy''' is a component of an [[argument]] that is demonstrably flawed in its [[logic]] or form, thus rendering the argument [[validity|invalid]] (except in the case of begging the question) in whole.
+
{{Copyedited}}{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{submitted}}
In [[logical argument]]s, fallacies are either ''formal'' or ''informal.'' Because the validity of a deductive argument depends on its form, a ''formal fallacy'' (or [[logical fallacy]]) is a deductive argument that has an invalid form, whereas an ''informal fallacy'' is any other invalid mode of reasoning whose flaw is not in the form of the argument.
+
A '''fallacy''' is an error in an [[argument]]. There are two main kinds of fallacies, corresponding to the distinction between formal and informal [[logic]]. If a formal argument is fallacious, it is invalid. If an informal argument is fallacious, its rational persuasive power is greatly reduced. It is often difficult to detect fallacies, for while they are not rationally persuasive, they may be psychologically persuasive, employing rhetorical strategies, emotional manipulation, or reasoning similar to valid forms, thus making the argument appear stronger than it is.
 +
{{toc}}
 +
Since [[Aristotle]]'s discussion in ''Sophistic Refutations'', there have been many systems of classifying fallacies. In this article, the only classification is the distinction between formal and informal fallacies.  
  
Beginning with [[Aristotle]], informal fallacies have generally been placed in one of several categories, depending on the source of the fallacy. There are fallacies of relevance, fallacies involving causal reasoning, and fallacies resulting from ambiguities.
+
== Formal fallacies ==
A similar approach to understanding and classifying fallacies is provided by [[argumentation theory]].
+
A formal fallacy involves an application of a fallacious rule of inference. Because of this, formal fallacies depend on a particular system of logic. There are, for example, fallacies of [[syllogism]], [[propositional logic]], and quantificational logic. Below are a few fallacies that occur frequently in contexts outside of strict logical proofs.
In this approach, an argument is regarded as part of an interactive [[Protocol (diplomacy)|protocol]] between individuals who are attempting to resolve a disagreement. The protocol is regulated by certain rules of interaction and violations of these rules are fallacies.
 
  
Recognizing fallacies in actual arguments may be difficult since arguments are often structured using [[rhetoric]]al patterns that obscure the logical connections between assertions. As we illustrate with various examples, fallacies may also exploit the [[emotion]]s or intellectual or [[psychology|psychological]] weaknesses of the interlocutor. Having the capability of recognizing logical fallacies in arguments will hopefully reduce the likelihood of such an occurrence.
+
* '''Affirming the Consequent'''
 +
One of the most basic rules of logic is called ''modus ponens''. If you know that ''p'' and you know that ''if p then q'', you can conclude ''q''. The fallacy of affirming the consequent concludes ''p'' from the conditional and ''q'' (the consequent). For example,
 +
:“Everyone under 21 had orange juice. Gussie had orange juice, so he must be under 21.”
 +
Gussie may be a 30-year old teetotaler. If the first sentence is true, then we can know what someone drank given that person’s age, but we cannot know how old a person is given what that person drank.
  
== Aristotelian fallacies ==
+
* '''Denying the Antecedent'''
=== Material fallacies ===
+
This fallacy is similar to the fallacy of affirming the consequent. For example.
The classification of ''material fallacies'' widely adopted by modern logicians and based on that of Aristotle, Organon (Sophistici elenchi), is as follows:
+
:“Everyone under 21 had orange juice. Bertie is 30, so Bertie must not have had orange juice.”
* [[Accident (fallacy)|Fallacy of Accident]] (also called destroying the exception or a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid) meaning to argue erroneously from a general rule to a particular case, without proper regard to particular conditions that vitiate the application of the general rule; e.g. if manhood suffrage be the law, arguing that a criminal or a lunatic must, therefore, have a vote
+
Bertie may have simply chosen to have orange juice (perhaps out of camaraderie with Gussie). If the first sentence is true, we do know that anyone who has something other than orange juice must be over 21, but we do not know anything about what those over 21 had to drink.
  
* [[Converse accident|Converse Fallacy of Accident]] (also called reverse accident, destroying the exception, or a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter) meaning to argue from a special case to a general rule
+
* '''Quantifier fallacies'''
 +
Quantifiers are words like ‘everyone,’ ‘something,’ and ‘no one.’ Quantifier fallacies involve improperly shuffling quantifiers. For example:
 +
:“Everyone is loved by someone or other. So someone loves everyone.”
 +
It may of course be true that someone (God, perhaps) loves everyone, but this does not follow from the fact that everyone is loved by someone (everyone is loved by her mother, perhaps). The fallacy arises in lack of caution with the quantifiers ‘everyone’ and ‘someone.’ Notice, however, that the converse is not fallacious. If someone (God) loves everybody, then everybody is loved by somebody (namely, God). An incautious cosmological argument may commit this fallacy:
 +
:“Everything has a cause, so there must be something that is the cause of everything.”
  
* [[Ignoratio elenchi|Irrelevant Conclusion]] (also called Ignoratio Elenchi), wherein, instead of proving the fact in dispute, the arguer seeks to gain his point by diverting attention to some extraneous fact (as in the legal story of "No case. Abuse the plaintiff's attorney"). The fallacies are common in platform oratory, in which the speaker obscures the real issue by appealing to his audience on the grounds of
+
== Informal fallacies ==
**purely personal considerations ([[Ad hominem|argumentum ad hominem]])
+
There are many fallacious forms of reasoning. The following list is not exhaustive, containing only a few important or egregious fallacies. Often an assumption or way of thinking is called a fallacy without being a fallacy in the strict sense used here (for example, the genetic fallacy). The entries on the list are not mutually exclusive, since often a particular bad bit of reasoning may be an instance of more than one fallacy.
**popular sentiment ([[Appeal to the majority|argumentum ad populum]], appeal to the majority)
 
**fear ([[argumentum ad baculum]])
 
**conventional propriety ([[Appeal to authority|argumentum ad verecundiam]])
 
:This fallacy has been illustrated by ethical or theological arguments wherein the fear of punishment is subtly substituted for abstract right as the sanction of moral obligation.  
 
  
* [[Begging the question]] (also called Petitio Principii or Circulus in Probando—arguing in a circle) consists in demonstrating a conclusion by means of premises that pre-suppose that conclusion. [[Jeremy Bentham]] points out that this fallacy may lurk in a single word, especially in an epithet, e.g. if a measure were condemned simply on the ground that it is alleged to be "un-English".
+
* '''Accident'''
 +
The fallacy of accident occurs when one fails to take note that the “accidental” features of a specific example render a general claim inapplicable. Many general claims have exceptions or special cases in which they are not applicable. (All generalizations have exceptions, including this one.) This is often the case in moral arguments. Lying is wrong. But it would be a fallacy of accident to conclude from this rule that it would be wrong to lie in order to save someone’s life.
  
* Fallacy of the Consequent, really a species of Irrelevant Conclusion, wherein a conclusion is drawn from premises that do not really support it.
+
The converse fallacy is sometimes called “hasty generalization.” It is a kind of inductive argument, but the cases examined are too few or too atypical to warrant the generalization.
  
* Fallacy of False Cause, or [[Non sequitur (logic)|Non Sequitur]] (L., it does not follow), wherein one thing is incorrectly assumed as the cause of another, as when the ancients attributed a public calamity to a meteorological phenomenon (a special case of this fallacy also goes by the Latin term ''[[post hoc ergo propter hoc]]''; the fallacy of believing that temporal succession implies a causal relation).
+
* '''''Ad hominem'''''
 +
(Literally, “against the person”). An ''ad hominem'' argument responds to an argument by attacking the person who presented the argument, or by attacking that person’s right to present the argument. For example:
 +
:“Jim argues that there’s no God. Yet another self-styled intellectual making the same old claim.”
 +
The response to Jim’s argument ignores the argument itself and instead attacks the person, in this case lumping him into a group whose arguments needn’t be heard. This type of ''ad hominem'' is often called “abusive,” but note that simple abuse (e.g., name-calling) does not make something a fallacy. One must argue that a given position is false because of some (irrelevant) fault of the person who holds the position.
  
* [[Fallacy of many questions|Fallacy of Many Questions]] (Plurium Interrogationum), wherein several questions are improperly grouped in the form of one, and a direct categorical answer is demanded, e.g. if a prosecuting counsel asked the prisoner " What time was it when you met this man? " with the intention of eliciting the tacit admission that such a meeting had taken place. Another example is the classic line, "Have you stopped beating your wife?"
+
Another example:
 +
:“Jane argues that God exists. But Jane is an employee of the church with an economic interest at stake.”
 +
Here again, the response ignores the argument and directs the attention to the presenter of the argument. This response differs, however, in that it does not dismiss Jane entirely but instead questions her appropriateness or her vested interest in the outcome of the argument. This type of ''ad hominem'' is often called “circumstantial” or ''tu quoque''. It should be distinguished from a non-fallacious caution that a person’s presentation of facts may be skewed because of vested interests.  
  
=== Verbal fallacies ===
+
* '''Amphiboly'''
''Verbal fallacies'' are those in which a false conclusion is obtained by improper or ambiguous use of words. They are generally classified as follows.
+
In general, an amphiboly is a structural ambiguity. Often, a single sentence might be taken more than one way. This is common in headlines, with their need for space conservation, and in poetry, where the freer word order allows this ambiguous prophecy in Shakespeare’s ''Henry IV'':
* [[Equivocation]] consists in employing the same word in two or more senses, e.g. in a [[syllogism]], the middle term being used in one sense in the major and another in the minor premise, so that in fact there are four not three terms ("All fair things are honourable; This woman is fair; therefore this woman is honourable," the second "fair" being in reference to complexion).
+
:“The duke yet lives that Henry shall depose.
* [[Amphibology]] is the result of ambiguity of grammatical structure, e.g. of the position of the adverb "only" in careless writers ("He only said that," in which sentence, as experience shows, the adverb has been intended to qualify any one of the other three words).  
+
It is ambiguous whether Henry shall depose the duke, or the duke shall depose Henry. As a premise in an argument, amphiboly would be fallacious if the plausibility of the premise required one reading, while the conclusion required another.
* [[Fallacy of composition|Fallacy of Composition]] is a species of Amphibology that results from the confused use of collective terms.  e.g. "The angles of a triangle are less than two right angles" might refer to the angles separately or added together.
 
* [[Fallacy of division|Division]], the converse of the preceding, which consists in employing the middle term distributively in the minor and collectively in the major premise.
 
* Accent, which occurs only in speaking and consists of emphasizing the wrong word in a sentence. E.g., "He is a fairly good pianist," according to the emphasis on the words, may imply praise of a beginner's progress, or an expert's depreciation of a popular hero, or it may imply that the person in question is a deplorable violinist).
 
* Figure of Speech, the confusion between the metaphorical and ordinary uses of a word or phrase.
 
  
=== Logical fallacies ===
+
* '''Appeal to Authority'''
The standard Aristotelian [[logical fallacies]] are:
+
In general, it is not fallacious to appeal to authority. If the majority of cardiologists claim that aerobic exercise helps prevent heart disease, it is not fallacious to argue based on this assertion. However, if the majority of cardiologists claim that God does not exist, it is fallacious to argue based on this assertion. Appeal to authority is fallacious when the authority cited is not an authority in the field. Of course, even when the authority cited is a leading light in the field, appealing to this authority does not prove the case. Textbooks change every few years as new knowledge becomes available. Like nearly all informal arguments, a non-fallacious appeal to authority does not prove the conclusion, but it does lend it considerable weight.
* [[Fallacy of four terms|Fallacy of Four Terms]] (Quaternio terminorum)
 
* [[Fallacy of the undistributed middle|Fallacy of Undistributed Middle]]
 
* Fallacy of Illicit process of the [[Illicit major|major]] or the [[Illicit minor]] term;
 
* [[Affirmative_conclusion_from_a_negative_premise|Fallacy of Negative Premises]].
 
  
== Other systems of classification ==
+
* '''Appeal to Emotion'''
Of other classifications of fallacies in general the most famous are those of [[Francis Bacon (philosopher)|Francis Bacon]] and [[John Stuart Mill|J. S. Mill]]. Bacon (''[[Novum Organum]]'', Aph. 33, 38 sqq.) divided fallacies into four Idola (Idols, i.e. False Appearances), which summarize the various kinds of mistakes to which the human intellect is prone. With these should be compared the Offendicula of Roger Bacon, contained in the Opus maius, pt. i. J. S. Mill discussed the subject in book v. of his Logic, and Jeremy Bentham's Book of Fallacies (1824) contains valuable remarks. See Rd. Whateley's Logic, bk. v.; A. de Morgan, Formal Logic (1847) ; A. Sidgwick, Fallacies (1883) and other textbooks.
+
In an appeal to emotion, one presents an emotional, rather than rational, case for one’s conclusion. There are many kinds of appeals to emotion, including
 +
Appeal to fear:
 +
:“Believe in God or burn in Hell.
 +
Flattery:
 +
:“Surely someone as smart as you can see that there’s no God.
 +
Appeal to pity:
 +
:“Find him innocent, ladies and gentlemen of the jury, because he has a wife and three children.
 +
In a sense, many fallacies are appeals to emotion, since a fallacy often gets its appeal by psychological, rather than rational, persuasion.  
  
==Fallacies in the media and politics==
+
* '''Appeal to novelty'''
 +
In an appeal to novelty, one claims that one’s position is correct because it is modern and new.
 +
For example:
 +
:“It was quite right for our ancestors to believe in God, but this belief is out of place in our enlightened times.”
  
Fallacies are used frequently by [[Pundit (politics)|pundit]]s in the [[mass media|media]] and [[politics]].  When one politician says to another, "You don't have the moral authority to say ''X''", this could be an example of the ''[[ad hominem|argumentum ad hominem]]'' or ''[[personal attack]]'' fallacy; that is, attempting to disprove ''X'', not by addressing validity of ''X'' but by attacking the person who asserted ''X''. Arguably, the politician is not even attempting to make an argument against ''X'', but is instead offering a moral rebuke against the interlocutor. For instance, if ''X'' is the assertion:
+
* '''Appeal to tradition'''
 +
This is the flip side of an appeal to novelty. In an appeal to tradition, one claims that one’s position is correct because it has been believed for so long.
 +
For example:
 +
:“Our ancestors who founded our nation believed in God. Are we better than they were?”
  
: The military uniform is a symbol of national strength and honor.
+
* '''Appeal to ignorance'''
 +
In an appeal to ignorance, one claims that a conclusion is true because it has not been proven false, or false because it has not been proven true.
 +
For example:
 +
:“Scientists and philosophers have been trying for centuries to prove that God exists. They have failed. So God does not exist.”
 +
Like many fallacies, this is related to a good form of reasoning. Informal induction is a form of reasoning that progresses from the truth of something in some cases to its truth in general. If, say, a police search-and-rescue unit were looking for a shoe under a bed and did not find it, it would be compelling to assume the shoe was not there.  
  
Then ostensibly, the politician is not trying to prove the contrary assertion. If this is the case, then  there is no logically fallacious argument, but merely a personal opinion about moral worth. Thus identifying logical fallacies may be difficult and dependent upon context.
+
* '''Bandwagon'''
 +
A bandwagon fallacy attempts to persuade based on the popularity of a claim.
 +
For example:
 +
:“70 percent of Americans believe in God. Why don’t you?”
  
In the opposite direction is the fallacy of [[appeal to authority|argument from authority]]. A classic example is the ''[[ipsedixitism|ipse dixit]]''—"He himself said it" argument—used throughout the [[Middle Ages]] in reference to [[Aristotle]]. A modern instance is "celebrity spokespersons" in advertisements: a product is good and you should buy/use/support it because your favorite celebrity endorses it.
+
* '''Begging the Question'''
 +
(Sometimes called ''petitio principii''; an argument that begs the question is often called “circular”.) One begs the question when one assumes what one is trying to prove. For example:
 +
:“God exists because the Bible says God exists, and the Bible is the word of God and so must be true.
  
An appeal to authority is always a logical fallacy, though it can be an appropriate form of [[rationality|rational]] argument if, for example, it is an appeal to [[expert testimony]]. In this case, the expert witness must be recognized as such and all parties must agree that the testimony is appropriate to the circumstances. This form of argument is common in legal situations.
+
* '''Composition'''
 +
A pair of fallacies are both known as the fallacy of composition. The first fallacy concludes that a whole has a certain property because each part of it has that property. For example, since a drop of water is smaller than a person, the ocean (which is made of drops of water) is smaller than a person. A subtler example is in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, in which he argues that since every part of a person (eye, hand, foot) has a function, a person also must have a function.
 +
The second fallacy is sometimes called the fallacy of division. It consists in concluding that every part has a property from the fact that the whole has that property. It would be hard to read every book in the New York Public Library. But it would be a fallacy of composition to conclude that city of God is difficult to read.
  
By definition, arguments with logical fallacies are [[validity|invalid]], but they can often be (re)written in such a way that they fit a valid [[argument form]]. The challenge to the interlocutor is, of course, to discover the [[false premise]], that is the premise that makes the argument [[soundness|unsound]].
+
* '''Equivocation'''
 +
Many words have more than one meaning. When an argument turns on two (or more) different meanings of a single word, the argument is equivocal. For example:
 +
:“The end of a thing is its perfect; death is the end of life; hence, death is the perfection of life.”
 +
This argument confuses two senses of “end,” which can mean either “goal” or “conclusion.” The first premise takes “end” in the first sense; the second premise takes it in the second sense.
  
== General list of fallacies ==
+
* '''False cause'''
The entries in the following list are neither exhaustive nor mutually exclusive; that is, several distinct entries may refer to the same pattern. As noted in the introduction, these fallacies describe erroneous or at least suspect patterns of argument in general, not necessarily argument based on formal logic. Many of the fallacies listed are traditionally recognized and discussed in works on critical thinking; others are more specialized.
+
Commonly called by its Latin name ''post hoc ergo propter hoc'' (literally, “after which therefore because of which”), one commits this fallacy in assuming that since X follows Y, X must cause Y. For example,
 +
:“Everyone who ate carrots before 1900 is dead. So carrots were poisonous before 1900.
  
* [[Ad hominem]] (also called ''argumentum ad hominem'' or ''personal attack'') including:
+
* '''Ignoratio Elenchi'''
** ''ad hominem abusive'' (also called ''argumentum ad personam'')
+
(Sometimes called “irrelevant conclusion”). This fallacy occurs when one argues for a conclusion, but then presents a different conclusion as the result of the argument. For example:
** ''ad hominem circumstantial'' (also called ''ad hominem circumstantiae'')
+
:“Fossil evidence shows that there has been life on the planet for millions of years, so God does not exist.”
** ''ad hominem tu quoque'' (also called ''you-too argument'')
+
The conclusion of this argument has little if any relation to the premises. In an example as obvious as this, the fallacy is very noticeable, but often the conclusion is slightly stronger than the evidence supports, and it takes a bit of thought to see that the argument does not support so strong a conclusion.
* [[Amphibology]] (also called ''amphiboly'')
 
* [[Appeal to authority]] (also called ''argumentum ad verecundiam'' or ''argument by authority'')
 
* [[Appeal to emotion]] including:
 
** [[Appeal to consequences]] (also called ''argumentum ad consequentiam'')
 
** [[Appeal to fear]] (also called ''argumentum ad metum'' or ''argumentum in terrorem'')
 
** [[Appeal to flattery]]
 
** [[Appeal to pity]] (also called ''argumentum ad misericordiam'')
 
** [[Appeal to ridicule]]
 
** [[Appeal to spite]] (also called ''argumentum ad odium'')
 
** [[Two wrongs make a right (fallacy)|Two wrongs make a right]]
 
** [[Wishful thinking]]
 
* [[Appeal to the majority]] (also called ''Appeal to belief, Argumentum ad numerum, Appeal to popularity, Appeal to the people, Bandwagon fallacy, Argumentum ad populum, Authority of the many, Consensus gentium, Argument by consensus'')
 
* [[Appeal to motive]]
 
* [[Appeal to novelty]] (also called ''argumentum ad novitatem'')
 
* [[Appeal to probability]]
 
* [[Appeal to tradition]] (also called ''argumentum ad antiquitatem'' or ''appeal to common practice'')
 
* [[Argument from fallacy]] (also called ''argumentum ad logicam'')
 
* [[Argument from ignorance]] (also called ''argumentum ad ignorantiam'' or ''argument by lack of imagination'')
 
* [[Argument from silence]] (also called ''argumentum ex silentio'')
 
* [[Appeal to force]] (also called ''argumentum ad baculum'')
 
* [[Appeal to wealth]] (also called ''argumentum ad crumenam'')
 
* [[Appeal to poverty]] (also called ''argumentum ad lazarum'')
 
* [[Argument from repetition]] (also called ''argumentum ad nauseam'')
 
* [[Argumentum ad vox absurda]]
 
* [[Base rate fallacy]]
 
* [[Begging the question]] (also called ''petitio principii'', ''circular argument'' or ''circular reasoning'')
 
* [[Conjunction fallacy]]
 
* [[Continuum fallacy]] (also called ''fallacy of the beard'')
 
* [[Correlative based fallacies]] including:
 
** [[Fallacy of many questions]] (also called ''complex question'', ''fallacy of presupposition'', ''loaded question'' or ''plurium interrogationum'')
 
** [[False dilemma]] (also called ''false dichotomy'' or ''bifurcation'')
 
** [[Denying the correlative]]
 
** [[Suppressed correlative]]
 
* [[Definist fallacy]]
 
* [[Dicto simpliciter]], including:
 
** [[Accident (fallacy)|Accident]] (also called ''a dicto simpliciter ad dictum secundum quid'')
 
** [[Converse accident]] (also called ''a dicto secundum quid ad dictum simpliciter'')
 
* [[Equivocation]]
 
* [[Fallacy of distribution|Fallacies of distribution]]:
 
** [[Composition (logical fallacy)|Composition]]
 
** [[Division (logical fallacy)|Division]]
 
** [[Ecological fallacy]]
 
* [[Fallacy of Presumption|Fallacies of Presumption]]
 
* [[False analogy]]
 
* [[False premise]]
 
* [[False compromise]]
 
* [[Faulty generalization]] including:
 
** [[Biased sample]]
 
** [[Hasty generalization]] (also called ''fallacy of insufficient statistics'', ''fallacy of insufficient sample'', ''fallacy of the lonely fact'', ''leaping to a conclusion'', ''hasty induction'', ''secundum quid'')
 
** [[Overwhelming exception]]
 
** [[Statistical special pleading]]
 
* [[Gambler's fallacy]]/[[Inverse gambler's fallacy]]
 
* [[Genetic fallacy]]
 
* [[Guilt by association]]
 
* [[Historian's fallacy]]
 
* [[Homunculus fallacy]]
 
* [[If-by-whiskey]] (argues both sides)
 
* [[Ignoratio elenchi]] (also called ''irrelevant conclusion'')
 
* Inappropriate interpretations or applications of statistics including:
 
** [[Biased sample]]
 
** [[Correlation implies causation (logical fallacy)|Correlation implies causation]]
 
** [[Gambler's fallacy]]
 
** [[Prosecutor's fallacy]]
 
** [[Screening test fallacy]]
 
* [[Incomplete comparison]]
 
* [[Inconsistent comparison]]
 
* [[Invalid proof]]
 
* [[Judgemental language]]
 
* [[Juxtaposition]]
 
* [[Lump of labour fallacy]] (also called ''the fallacy of labour scarcity'')
 
* [[Meaningless statement]]
 
* [[Middle ground]] (also called ''argumentum ad temperantiam'')
 
* [[Misleading vividness]]
 
* [[Naturalistic fallacy]]
 
* [[Negative proof]]
 
* [[Non sequitur (logic)|Non sequitur]] including:
 
** [[Affirming the consequent]]
 
** [[Denying the antecedent]]
 
* [[No true Scotsman]]
 
* [[Package deal fallacy]]
 
* [[Perfect solution fallacy]]
 
* [[Poisoning the well]]
 
* [[Progressive fallacy]] ("New is improved")
 
* [[Proof by assertion]]
 
* [[Proof by verbosity]]
 
* [[Questionable cause]] (also called ''non causa pro causa'') including:
 
** [[Correlation implies causation (logical fallacy)|Correlation implies causation]] (also called ''cum hoc ergo propter hoc'')
 
** [[Fallacy of the single cause]]
 
** [[Joint effect]]
 
** [[Post hoc]] (also called ''post hoc ergo propter hoc'')
 
** [[Regression fallacy]]
 
** [[Texas sharpshooter fallacy]]
 
** [[Wrong direction]]
 
* [[Red herring (fallacy)|Red herring]] (also called ''irrelevant conclusion'')
 
* [[Reification]] (also called ''hypostatization'')
 
* [[Relativist fallacy]] (also called ''subjectivist fallacy'')
 
* [[Retrospective determinism]] (it happened so it was bound to)
 
* Shifting the [[Burden of proof (logical fallacy)|burden of proof]]
 
* [[Slippery slope]]
 
* [[Special pleading]]
 
* [[Straw man]]
 
* [[Style over substance fallacy]]
 
* [[Syllogistic fallacy|Syllogistic fallacies]], including:
 
** [[Affirming a disjunct]]
 
** [[Affirmative conclusion from a negative premise]]
 
** [[Existential fallacy]]
 
** [[Fallacy of exclusive premises]]
 
** [[Fallacy of four terms]] (also called ''quaternio terminorum'')
 
** [[Fallacy of the undistributed middle]]
 
** [[Illicit major]]
 
** [[Illicit minor]]
 
  
== General examples ==
+
* '''Non sequiter'''
Fallacious arguments involve not only [[formal logic]] but also [[causality]].
+
(literally, “it does not follow.”) This is a general term that can apply to any fallacy, to indicate that the conclusion does not follow from the premises. It is often applies to the fallacies of ignoratio elenchi and false cause.
Others involve psychological ploys
+
== References ==
such as use of power relationships between proposer and interlocutor,
+
* [[Aristotle]]. [http://etext.library.adelaide.edu.au/a/aristotle/sophistical/ On Sophistical Refutations], ''De Sophistici Elenchi''.
appeals to patriotism and morality, appeals to ego etc., to establish
+
* Bacon, Francis. ''The doctrine of the idols in ''Novum Organum Scientiarum''. [http://fly.hiwaay.net/%7Epaul/bacon/organum/aphorisms1.html Aphorisms concerning The Interpretation of Nature and the Kingdom of Man, XXIIIff].
necessary intermediate (explicit or implicit) premises for an argument.
+
* Buridan, John. ''Summulae de dialectica'' Book VII.
Indeed, fallacies very often lay in unstated assumptions or [[Implication (pragmatics)|implied]]
+
* Copi, Irving M. ''Introduction to Logic''. Macmillan, 1982.
premises in arguments that are not always obvious at first glance.
+
* Fearnside, W. Ward and William B. Holther, [http://www.ditext.com/fearnside/fallacy.html Fallacy: The Counterfeit of Argument], 1959.
One way to obscure a premise is through [[enthymeme]].
+
* Fischer, D. H. ''Historians' Fallacies: Toward a Logic of Historical Thought''. Harper Torchbooks, 1970.
 +
* Hamblin, C. L. [http://www.ditext.com/hamblin/fallacies.html ''Fallacies'']. Methuen London, 1970.
 +
* Mill, John Stuart. [http://www.la.utexas.edu/research/poltheory/mill/sol/ A System of Logic - Raciocinative and Inductive]. [http://www.la.utexas.edu/research/poltheory/mill/sol/sol.b05.c07.html Book 5, Chapter 7, Fallacies of Confusion]
 +
* Schopenhauer, Arthur. The Art of Controversy | [http://coolhaus.de/art-of-controversy/ ''Die Kunst, Recht zu behalten - The Art Of Controversy'' (bilingual)].
 +
* Walton, Douglas N. ''Informal logic: A handbook for critical argumentation''. Cambridge University Press, 1989.
 +
* van Eemeren, F. H. and R. Grootendorst. ''Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies: A Pragma-Dialectical Perspective'', Lawrence Erlbaum and Associates, 1992.
 +
* Warburton, Nigel. ''Thinking from A to Z'', Routledge, 1998.
 +
* [[William of Ockham]]. ''Summa of Logic'' (c. 1323) Part III. 4.
  
We now give a few examples illustrating common errors in reasoning.  Note that providing a critique of an argument has no relation to the truth of the conclusion. The conclusion could very well be true, while the argument itself is not valid. See [[argument from fallacy]].
+
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved March 23, 2024.
  
In the following, we view an argument as a dialogue between a ''proposer'' and an ''interlocutor''.
+
* [http://www.iep.utm.edu/f/fallacy.htm Fallacy, The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy - lists 171 common fallacies]
 +
* [http://www.virtuescience.com/logicalfallacies.html Logical Fallacies-a semi ordered list with definitions]
 +
* [http://www.csun.edu/~dgw61315/fallacies.html Logical Fallacies and the Art of Debate]
 +
* [http://humbugonline.blogspot.com/2005/01/fallacy-list.html List of fallacies] with links to real examples.  
  
===Example 1: Material Fallacy===
+
;General Philosophy Sources
 
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
James argues:
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
# Cheese is food.
+
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
# Food is delicious.
 
# Therefore, cheese is delicious.
 
 
 
This argument claims to prove that cheese is delicious. This particular argument has the form of a [[categorical syllogism]]. Any argument must have ''premises'' as well as a conclusion. In this case we need to ask what the premises are, that is the set of assumptions the proposer of the argument can expect the interlocutor  to grant. The first assumption is almost true by definition: [[cheese]] is a foodstuff edible by humans. The second assumption is less clear as to its meaning.  Since the assertion has no [[quantifier]]s of any kind, it could mean any one of the following:
 
 
 
* All food is delicious.
 
* Most food is delicious.
 
* All food is delicious, except for spoiled or moldy food.
 
* Some food is disgusting.
 
 
 
In any of the last three interpretations, the above syllogism would then fail to have validated its second premise. James may try to assume that his interlocutor believes that all food is delicious; if the interlocutor grants this then the argument is valid.  In this case, the interlocutor is essentially conceding the point to James.  However, the interlocutor is more likely to believe that some food is disgusting, such as a sheep's liver white chocolate torte; and in this case James is not much better off than he was before he formulated the argument, since he now has to prove the assertion that cheese is a unique type of universally delicious food, which is a disguised form of the original thesis.  From the point of view of the interlocutor, James commits the logical fallacy of [[begging the question]].
 
 
 
===Example 2: Verbal Fallacy===
 
 
 
Barbara argues:
 
 
 
# Andre is a good tennis player.
 
# Therefore, Andre is 'good', that is to say a ''morally'' good person.
 
 
 
Here the problem is that the word ''[[good (disambiguation)|good]]'' has different meanings, which is to say that it is an ''[[Ambiguity|ambiguous]]'' word.  In the premise, Barbara says that Andre is good at some particular activity, in this case tennis.  In the conclusion, she says that Andre is a morally good person.  These are clearly two different senses of the word "good".  The premise might be true but the conclusion can still be false: Andre might be the best tennis player in the world but a rotten person morally. However, it is not legitimate to infer he is a bad person on the ground there has been a fallacious argument on the part of Barbara. Nothing concerning Andre's moral qualities is to be inferred from the premise. Appropriately, since it plays on an ambiguity, this sort of fallacy is called the fallacy of [[equivocation]], that is, equating two incompatible terms or claims.
 
 
 
===Example 3: Verbal Fallacy===
 
 
 
Ramesh argues:
 
 
 
# Nothing is better than eternal happiness.
 
# Eating a hamburger is better than nothing.
 
# Therefore, eating a hamburger is better than eternal happiness.
 
 
 
This argument has the appearance of an inference that applies [[transitive relation|transitivity]] of the two-placed relation ''is better than'', which in this critique we grant is a valid property. The argument is an example of ''syntactic ambiguity''.  In fact, the first premise semantically does not predicate an attribute of the subject, as would for instance the assertion
 
 
 
: A potato is better than eternal happiness.
 
 
 
In fact it is semantically equivalent to the following [[universal quantification]]:
 
 
 
: Everything fails to be better than eternal happiness.
 
 
 
So instantiating this fact with ''eating a hamburger'', it logically follows that
 
 
 
: Eating a hamburger fails to be better than eternal happiness.
 
 
 
Note that the premise ''A hamburger is better than nothing'' does not  provide anything to this argument. This fact really means something such as
 
 
 
: Eating a hamburger is better than eating nothing at all.
 
 
 
Thus this is a [[fallacy of composition]].
 
 
 
===Example 4: Logical Fallacy===
 
In the strictest sense, a logical fallacy is the incorrect application of a valid logical principle or an application of a nonexistent principle:
 
 
 
# Some drivers are men.
 
# Some drivers are women.
 
# Therefore, some drivers are both men and women.
 
 
 
This is fallacious. Indeed, there is no logical principle that states
 
 
 
# For some x, P(x).
 
# For some x, Q(x).
 
# Therefore for some x, P(x) and Q(x).
 
 
 
An easy way to show the above inference is invalid is by using [[Venn diagram]]s. In logical parlance, the inference is invalid, since under at least one interpretation of the predicates it is not validity preserving.
 
 
 
==See also==
 
* [[Logical fallacy]]
 
  
 
[[Category:Logic]]
 
[[Category:Logic]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
  
{{credit|48358993}}
+
{{credit2|Fallacy|48358993|Logical_fallacy|62514064}}

Latest revision as of 00:35, 25 March 2024

A fallacy is an error in an argument. There are two main kinds of fallacies, corresponding to the distinction between formal and informal logic. If a formal argument is fallacious, it is invalid. If an informal argument is fallacious, its rational persuasive power is greatly reduced. It is often difficult to detect fallacies, for while they are not rationally persuasive, they may be psychologically persuasive, employing rhetorical strategies, emotional manipulation, or reasoning similar to valid forms, thus making the argument appear stronger than it is.

Since Aristotle's discussion in Sophistic Refutations, there have been many systems of classifying fallacies. In this article, the only classification is the distinction between formal and informal fallacies.

Formal fallacies

A formal fallacy involves an application of a fallacious rule of inference. Because of this, formal fallacies depend on a particular system of logic. There are, for example, fallacies of syllogism, propositional logic, and quantificational logic. Below are a few fallacies that occur frequently in contexts outside of strict logical proofs.

  • Affirming the Consequent

One of the most basic rules of logic is called modus ponens. If you know that p and you know that if p then q, you can conclude q. The fallacy of affirming the consequent concludes p from the conditional and q (the consequent). For example,

“Everyone under 21 had orange juice. Gussie had orange juice, so he must be under 21.”

Gussie may be a 30-year old teetotaler. If the first sentence is true, then we can know what someone drank given that person’s age, but we cannot know how old a person is given what that person drank.

  • Denying the Antecedent

This fallacy is similar to the fallacy of affirming the consequent. For example.

“Everyone under 21 had orange juice. Bertie is 30, so Bertie must not have had orange juice.”

Bertie may have simply chosen to have orange juice (perhaps out of camaraderie with Gussie). If the first sentence is true, we do know that anyone who has something other than orange juice must be over 21, but we do not know anything about what those over 21 had to drink.

  • Quantifier fallacies

Quantifiers are words like ‘everyone,’ ‘something,’ and ‘no one.’ Quantifier fallacies involve improperly shuffling quantifiers. For example:

“Everyone is loved by someone or other. So someone loves everyone.”

It may of course be true that someone (God, perhaps) loves everyone, but this does not follow from the fact that everyone is loved by someone (everyone is loved by her mother, perhaps). The fallacy arises in lack of caution with the quantifiers ‘everyone’ and ‘someone.’ Notice, however, that the converse is not fallacious. If someone (God) loves everybody, then everybody is loved by somebody (namely, God). An incautious cosmological argument may commit this fallacy:

“Everything has a cause, so there must be something that is the cause of everything.”

Informal fallacies

There are many fallacious forms of reasoning. The following list is not exhaustive, containing only a few important or egregious fallacies. Often an assumption or way of thinking is called a fallacy without being a fallacy in the strict sense used here (for example, the genetic fallacy). The entries on the list are not mutually exclusive, since often a particular bad bit of reasoning may be an instance of more than one fallacy.

  • Accident

The fallacy of accident occurs when one fails to take note that the “accidental” features of a specific example render a general claim inapplicable. Many general claims have exceptions or special cases in which they are not applicable. (All generalizations have exceptions, including this one.) This is often the case in moral arguments. Lying is wrong. But it would be a fallacy of accident to conclude from this rule that it would be wrong to lie in order to save someone’s life.

The converse fallacy is sometimes called “hasty generalization.” It is a kind of inductive argument, but the cases examined are too few or too atypical to warrant the generalization.

  • Ad hominem

(Literally, “against the person”). An ad hominem argument responds to an argument by attacking the person who presented the argument, or by attacking that person’s right to present the argument. For example:

“Jim argues that there’s no God. Yet another self-styled intellectual making the same old claim.”

The response to Jim’s argument ignores the argument itself and instead attacks the person, in this case lumping him into a group whose arguments needn’t be heard. This type of ad hominem is often called “abusive,” but note that simple abuse (e.g., name-calling) does not make something a fallacy. One must argue that a given position is false because of some (irrelevant) fault of the person who holds the position.

Another example:

“Jane argues that God exists. But Jane is an employee of the church with an economic interest at stake.”

Here again, the response ignores the argument and directs the attention to the presenter of the argument. This response differs, however, in that it does not dismiss Jane entirely but instead questions her appropriateness or her vested interest in the outcome of the argument. This type of ad hominem is often called “circumstantial” or tu quoque. It should be distinguished from a non-fallacious caution that a person’s presentation of facts may be skewed because of vested interests.

  • Amphiboly

In general, an amphiboly is a structural ambiguity. Often, a single sentence might be taken more than one way. This is common in headlines, with their need for space conservation, and in poetry, where the freer word order allows this ambiguous prophecy in Shakespeare’s Henry IV:

“The duke yet lives that Henry shall depose.”

It is ambiguous whether Henry shall depose the duke, or the duke shall depose Henry. As a premise in an argument, amphiboly would be fallacious if the plausibility of the premise required one reading, while the conclusion required another.

  • Appeal to Authority

In general, it is not fallacious to appeal to authority. If the majority of cardiologists claim that aerobic exercise helps prevent heart disease, it is not fallacious to argue based on this assertion. However, if the majority of cardiologists claim that God does not exist, it is fallacious to argue based on this assertion. Appeal to authority is fallacious when the authority cited is not an authority in the field. Of course, even when the authority cited is a leading light in the field, appealing to this authority does not prove the case. Textbooks change every few years as new knowledge becomes available. Like nearly all informal arguments, a non-fallacious appeal to authority does not prove the conclusion, but it does lend it considerable weight.

  • Appeal to Emotion

In an appeal to emotion, one presents an emotional, rather than rational, case for one’s conclusion. There are many kinds of appeals to emotion, including Appeal to fear:

“Believe in God or burn in Hell.”

Flattery:

“Surely someone as smart as you can see that there’s no God.”

Appeal to pity:

“Find him innocent, ladies and gentlemen of the jury, because he has a wife and three children.”

In a sense, many fallacies are appeals to emotion, since a fallacy often gets its appeal by psychological, rather than rational, persuasion.

  • Appeal to novelty

In an appeal to novelty, one claims that one’s position is correct because it is modern and new. For example:

“It was quite right for our ancestors to believe in God, but this belief is out of place in our enlightened times.”
  • Appeal to tradition

This is the flip side of an appeal to novelty. In an appeal to tradition, one claims that one’s position is correct because it has been believed for so long. For example:

“Our ancestors who founded our nation believed in God. Are we better than they were?”
  • Appeal to ignorance

In an appeal to ignorance, one claims that a conclusion is true because it has not been proven false, or false because it has not been proven true. For example:

“Scientists and philosophers have been trying for centuries to prove that God exists. They have failed. So God does not exist.”

Like many fallacies, this is related to a good form of reasoning. Informal induction is a form of reasoning that progresses from the truth of something in some cases to its truth in general. If, say, a police search-and-rescue unit were looking for a shoe under a bed and did not find it, it would be compelling to assume the shoe was not there.

  • Bandwagon

A bandwagon fallacy attempts to persuade based on the popularity of a claim. For example:

“70 percent of Americans believe in God. Why don’t you?”
  • Begging the Question

(Sometimes called petitio principii; an argument that begs the question is often called “circular”.) One begs the question when one assumes what one is trying to prove. For example:

“God exists because the Bible says God exists, and the Bible is the word of God and so must be true.”
  • Composition

A pair of fallacies are both known as the fallacy of composition. The first fallacy concludes that a whole has a certain property because each part of it has that property. For example, since a drop of water is smaller than a person, the ocean (which is made of drops of water) is smaller than a person. A subtler example is in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, in which he argues that since every part of a person (eye, hand, foot) has a function, a person also must have a function. The second fallacy is sometimes called the fallacy of division. It consists in concluding that every part has a property from the fact that the whole has that property. It would be hard to read every book in the New York Public Library. But it would be a fallacy of composition to conclude that city of God is difficult to read.

  • Equivocation

Many words have more than one meaning. When an argument turns on two (or more) different meanings of a single word, the argument is equivocal. For example:

“The end of a thing is its perfect; death is the end of life; hence, death is the perfection of life.”

This argument confuses two senses of “end,” which can mean either “goal” or “conclusion.” The first premise takes “end” in the first sense; the second premise takes it in the second sense.

  • False cause

Commonly called by its Latin name post hoc ergo propter hoc (literally, “after which therefore because of which”), one commits this fallacy in assuming that since X follows Y, X must cause Y. For example,

“Everyone who ate carrots before 1900 is dead. So carrots were poisonous before 1900.”
  • Ignoratio Elenchi

(Sometimes called “irrelevant conclusion”). This fallacy occurs when one argues for a conclusion, but then presents a different conclusion as the result of the argument. For example:

“Fossil evidence shows that there has been life on the planet for millions of years, so God does not exist.”

The conclusion of this argument has little if any relation to the premises. In an example as obvious as this, the fallacy is very noticeable, but often the conclusion is slightly stronger than the evidence supports, and it takes a bit of thought to see that the argument does not support so strong a conclusion.

  • Non sequiter

(literally, “it does not follow.”) This is a general term that can apply to any fallacy, to indicate that the conclusion does not follow from the premises. It is often applies to the fallacies of ignoratio elenchi and false cause.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

External links

All links retrieved March 23, 2024.

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.