Difference between revisions of "Consequentialism" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Consequentialism''' refers to those moral theories that hold that the consequences of a particular action form the basis for any valid moral judgement about that action. Thus, on a consequentialist account, a morally right action is an action which produces good consequences.
+
Consequentialism
  
==Defining consequentialism==
+
OVERVIEW:
[[Image:JohnStuartMill.jpg|thumb|left|John Stuart Mill]]
 
The term "consequentialism" was coined by [[G.E.M. Anscombe]] in her essay "Modern Moral Philosophy" in 1958, and has since become common throughout English-language moral theory. Its historical roots are in [[utilitarianism]], although earlier ethical theories often considered the consequences of actions relevant to ethical deliberation. Because of this historical tie to utilitarianism these two approaches are sometimes conflated. This conflation is not necessarily inaccurate as utilitarianism has the important formal character of all consequentialist theories: a focus on the consequences.
 
  
As its name suggests, consequentialism focuses on the outcomes of actions, emphasizing the results rather than the kinds of acts involved. Most consequentialist theories focus on maximizing good states — after all, if something is good, then more seems better. However, not all consequentialist theories adopt this stance.
+
One central aim of normative ethics is to provide general principles of right conduct that specify the conditions under which an action is right or wrong. A consequentialist moral theory defines normative properties such as rightness, praiseworthiness, and virtuousness in terms of the promotion of valuable states of affairs. Classical Utilitarianism as advanced by Bentham and Mill provides a clear example of consequentialism, defining right actions as those maximising the happiness of sentient beings. Consequentialism epitomises the intuition that morality should be concerned with improving the quality of people’s lives, and, as such, can seem to be little more than common sense. However, consequentialism has problems accounting for intuitions concerning justice and rights, the existence of special obligations, and a distinction between what is morally required and morally supererogatory.
  
Apart from this basic outline, there is little else that can be unequivocally said about consequentialism. There are, however, some general themes that reappear in a number of consequentialist theories. These include questions such as:
+
MORAL THEORIES: TELEOLOGICAL AND NON-TELEOLOGICAL
  
* What determines the value of consequences? In other words, what counts as a good state of affairs?
+
Moral theories include two components: a theory of value (a theory of the good) and a theory of the right. A theory of value provides an account of what things are intrinsically good, or what states of affairs we would like to have realised. For example, hedonism is a theory of value according to which the happiness (qualitative states) of sentient beings is the only intrinsic good. The second component of a moral theory is the specification of how moral agents ought to responds to the valuable properties specified by the theory of value. This is most often understood in terms of a theory of right action, for modern ethical thinking has tended to focus centrally concerned with what is done, as over above, (e.g.) what sort of persons we should become. (See entry on Virtue Ethics)
* Who or what is the primary beneficiary of moral action?
 
* Who judges what the consequences of an action are and how?
 
  
===What kinds of consequences===
+
On a standard taxonomy, moral theories may be classified according to how they specify the relation between the theory of value and the theory of right action. The Greek word telos means goal, end, or purpose; teleology is the study of goals, ends and purposes; teleological ethical theories, therefore, emphasise that morality is oriented toward bringing about a certain goal. Consequentialism is one important sort of teleological moral theory. Consequentialism in its most general form is the claim that a normative property (such as ‘rightness’, ‘wrongness’ ‘virtuousness’ etc) depends on the value of consequences. More particularly, according to act consequentialism the rightness of an action derives from the value of the consequences, that is, what is brought about by the action. Act consequentialism holds that the right act for a particular agent is the one that produces the greatest balance of good over bad. Rule consequentialism justifies moral rules according to the value that the rules tend to promote. Motive consequentialism is the thesis that the moral qualities of an action depend on the overall consequences of actions done from a particular motive. This article will focus most centrally on act consequentialism.
One way to divide various consequentialisms is by the types of consequences that are taken to matter most, that is, which consequences count as good states of affairs.  
 
  
According to hedonistic [[utilitarianism]], a good action is one that results in any increase in [[pleasure]], and the best action is one that results the most pleasure possible. Closely related is [[eudaimonia|eudaimonic]] consequentialism, according to which a full, flourishing life, which may or may not be the same as enjoying a great deal of pleasure, is the ultimate aim. Similarly, one might adopt an aesthetic consequentialism, in which the ultimate aim is to produce beauty.
+
Interpretations of what is to be included under the rubric of consequentialism are not entirely standard in the philosophical literature. One significant area of disagreement is whether consequentialism must be regarded as an agent neutral theory. Agent neutrality is the thesis that when comparisons are made as to the overall goodness or badness of actions, this judgment must be made from an objective perspective, without taking the agent’s particular circumstances into account. This is important insofar a most consequentialists would want to differentiate their theory from ethical egoism, which has a superficially similar structure to consequentialism as outline above. Ethical egoism may be understood as the moral theory according to which right actions are those that bring about the greatest overall good for the agent him or herself. The ethical egoist does not consider the best state of the world overall, but the best state of the world from his perspective. In this article, I shall assume that a moral theory that does not include the thesis of agent neutrality is nonetheless legitimately classified as consequentialist moral theory.  
  
However, one might fix on non-psychological goods as the relevant effect. Thus, one might pursue an increase in [[Equality of outcome|material equality]] or [[Freedom (political)|political liberty]] instead of something like the more ephemeral "pleasure".
+
CLASSICAL UTLITARIANISM AND CONSEQUENTIALISM:
  
A theory might even adopt a package of several goods, all to be promoted equally. Since there would be no overarching consequence to aim for, conflicts between goods are to be adjudicated not by some ultimate consequentialist principle, but by the fine contextual discernment and intuition of the agent. Even in a consequentialist system that focuses on a single type of good, though, such conflicts and tensions are to be expected.
+
The most well known example of a consequentialist ethical theory is Classical Utilitarianism, as articulated in the seminal writings of Bentham and Mill. Consequentialism may be helpfully understood in terms of its relation to Classical Utilitarianism. Classical Utilitarianism is hedonistic act consequentialism. This means that Classical Utilitarianism is a consequentialist ethical theory that endorses hedonism as a theory of value, and focuses on actions (as opposed to rules, motives, character traits). This is clearly evident in Principle of Utility, which Mill articulates as follows:
  
One might even take the course advocated by [[G.E. Moore]] and argue that "the good" is unanalyzable, and thus argue that good states of affairs do not necessarily share any other property than "goodness" itself {{smref|Moore}}.
+
The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness; wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.  
  
===Consequences for whom===
+
The Hedonism of Classical Utilitarianism has always been controversial, and many philosophers have rejected Hedonism as a theory of value without rejecting the insight the morality ought to be concerned with promoting valuable states of affairs. Philosophers have then tended to articulate alternative accounts of value, without abandoning the consequentialism in Classical Utilitarianism. More generally, the varieties of consequentialism are helpfully understood as revisions of Classical Utilitarianism in an attempt to accommodate its basic insight whilst avoiding the objections to which Classical Utilitarianism seems susceptible.
Moral action always has an effect on certain people or things, the consequences. Various kinds of consequentialism can be differentiated by the person or thing that is supposed to benefit from the good consequences. That is, one might ask "Consequences for whom?"
 
  
====Agent-Centered or Agent Neutral====
+
All Utilitarian theories are versions of consequentialism, since consequentialism is one element of Utilitarianism. However, Utilitarianism is sometimes understood as a brand of consequentialism which endorses theory of value that is specifically concerned with the welfare of individual human beings. On this definition, Utilitarianism is welfarist consequentialism. Some welfarist theories are subjectivist, including Hedonism and desire and preference satisfaction theories. Other welfarist theories are objective, including G.E. Moore’s Ideal Utilitarianism. Perfectionist Consequentialist theories would not, on this definition count as forms of Utilitarianism. But this usage is not standard across the philosophical literature.
A fundamental distinction along these lines is between theories that demand that agents act for ends in which they have some personal interest or [[motivation]] to pursue (actually or counterfactually) and theories that demand that agents act for ends perhaps disconnected from their own interests and drives. These are called "agent-focused" and "agent-neutral" theories respectively.
 
  
Agent-neutral consequentialism ignores the specific value a state of affairs has for any particular agent. Thus, in an agent-neutral theory, my own personal goals do not count any more than anyone elses goals in evaluating what action I should take. Agent-focused consequentialism, on the other hand, focuses on the particular needs of the moral agent. Thus, in an agent-focused account, such as one that Peter Railton outlines, I might be concerned with the general welfare, but I am more concerned with the immediate welfare of myself and my friends and family{{smref|Sch1}}.
 
  
These two approaches could be reconciled by acknowledging the tension between an agent's interests as an individual and as a member of various groups, and seeking to somehow optimize among all of these interests.  For example, it may be meaningful to speak of an action as being good for someone as an individual but bad for them as a citizen of their town.
+
OBJECTIONS TO CONSEQUENTIALISM
  
====Human-centered?====
+
Consequentialism is in conflict with ordinary moral thinking in a number of ways.  
Most consequentialist theories seem primarily concerned with human beings and their relationships with other human beings. However, some philosophers argue that we should not limit our ethical consideration to the interests of human beings alone.  
 
  
No less a person than [[Jeremy Bentham]], who is regarded as the founder of [[Utilitarianism]], regarded animals as a serious object of moral concern, arguing that they evinced at least some response to pleasure and pain, and thus, the consequences a certain course of action would have on animals was directly relevant{{smref|Ben}}. More recently, [[Peter Singer]] has argued that it is unreasonable that we do not treat animals in the same way we are inclined to treat human beings{{smref|Sing}}.
+
Firstly, consequentialism seems unable to accommodate justice and rights. In J.J.C Smart’s (1978) formulates the problem for consequentialism with respect to justice as follows: “The most poignant sort of case, of course, is that of the punishment of an innocent man. Suppose that in order to prevent a riot in which thousands would certainly be killed a sheriff were to frame and execute an innocent man. On utilitarian principles would not the sacrifice of one life in order to save thousands be justified?” (Smart’s discussion is with particular reference to Utilitarianism, but Utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism.) If the sheriff frames the stranger he will bring about more good consequences than bad consequences. We may simply stipulate that this is so. According to consequentialism, therefore, this is the right action to perform. However, an innocent man does not deserve to be punished. So, it seems, consequentialism does not accommodate justice.  
  
Some [[environmentalism | environmentalists]] and [[ecocentric | ecocentrists]] hold that the environment or particular ecosystems are the relevant object(s) of concern. Thus, an action can only be considered acceptable if it has a positive (or at least non-negative) impact on a particular ecosystem. Theoretically, even the entire universe might be the relevant object of concern, the best action being the one that brings the most value into the universe, whatever that value might be.
+
A structurally very similar problem arises with respect to consequentialism and rights. The concept of a ‘right’ has to do with protecting a person’s important interests. Rights place limits on how an individual may be treated, regardless of the good purposes that might be accomplished” (Rachels 2003, p. 108). Once again, a consequentialist moral theory is apparently committed to the claim that nothing that is ultimately prohibited, so long as the good consequences of this action outweigh the bad. Rape, torture, and all manner of horrific acts may in principle be required whenever the overall consequences are good enough.
  
===Action Guidance===
+
Another problem for consequentialism is accounting for the existence of special ties of obligation. Special obligations include those acquired by entering into contracts, obligations acquired in virtue of occupying a certain occupational role, and family ties. For example, a teacher is obligated to certain sorts of actions related to satisfying occupational duties, and these actions are required of him or her only because of the special duties incumbent on a teacher. Similarly, a mother or father is usually thought to be obligated to her or his children in a way she or he is not obligated to other people’s children. These are sometime called agent-relative duties. Consequentialism, however, is usually understood to be an agent neural moral theory, and so, one is obligated to bring about good for those who would benefit from it most, irrespective of their relationship to oneself. This consequence is at odds with ordinary thinking in that it seems that a person reasonably displays concern for her family that she does not display for others. But consequentialism requires one to promote the good in general, and does therefore not accommodate the common sense intuition that special obligations generate special duties, and that (e.g.) a father is required to do things for his own family that he is not required to do for people in general.
One important characteristic of many normative moral theories such as consequentialism is the ability to produce practical moral judgements. At the very least, any moral theory needs to define the standpoint from which the goodness of the consequences are to be determined. What is primarily at stake here is the ''responsibility'' of the agent.
 
  
====The Ideal Observer====
+
On a closely related point, W.D. Ross has argued that if breaking a promise brings about slightly more happiness, then the Classical Utilitarian must prescribe that the promise is to be broken. Imagine that you’ve made a promise to give me a ride to the airport. However, at the last moment someone asks you to come away for the weekend, making it impossible to give me the ride. Imagine that there would be a slightly greater balance of gain for everyone concerned – you really are a bundle of fun – if you broke your promise. Ross’s point is that consequentialism says you should break your promise even if the gain is only slightly more. But this seems to imply that consequentialism cannot accommodate the point that one is obligated by the promise, and a slight gain in overall pleasure does not seem to trump this obligation.
One common tactic among consequentialists, particularly those committed to an [[Altruism|altruistic]] account of consequentialism, is to talk about an ideal, neutral observer from which moral judgements can be made (this is a bit like [[WP:NPOV]]). [[John Rawls]], a critic of utilitarianism, argues that utilitarianism, in common with other forms of consequentialism, relies on the perspective of such an ideal observer{{smref|Sch1}}. The particular characteristics of this ideal observer can vary from an omniscient observer, who would grasp all the consequences of any action, to an ideally informed observer, who knows as much as could reasonably be expected, but not necessarily all the circumstances or all the possible consequences. Consequentialist theories that adopt this paradigm hold that right action is the action that will bring about the best consequences from this ideal observer's perspective.
 
  
====The Real Observer====
+
Another important objection to consequentialism is that it is too demanding as a moral theory. To understand this objection, it is necessary to spend a moment considering some key features of our common moral beliefs. In ordinary morality, there is a distinction between what we are morally required to do (or not do) and what is good or morally significant to do, but what is not strictly required. For example, ‘Thou shall not murder’ entails that we are required to refrain from intentionally killing innocent people. By contrast, acts of charity are morally praiseworthy, but we are not, it is usually thought, strictly required to be charitable. Rather, charity is something that goes beyond the bounds of duty.  One would not normally be blamed for failing to give to charity, although one would be morally praised for acts of charity. Actions that are morally admirable to do but not strictly required of us are called supererogatory actions.  
Of course, in practice, it seems very difficult to always adopt the point of view of an ideal observer. An individual moral agent, after all, only knows a certain number of things about the situation they are in, and thus the possible consequences of a particular course of action. Thus, some theorists have argued that consequentialist theories can only require an agent to choose the best action in line with what they know about the situation.
 
  
However, this idea, naïvely adopted, could lead to very bad results, if the moral agent does not go out of the way to inform themselves about the situation. Acting in a situation without first informing oneself of the circumstances of the situation can lead to even the most well-intended actions to have miserable consequences. As a result, certain theorists have argued that there is a moral imperative for an agent to inform themselves as much as possible about a situation before judging the appropriate course of action. This imperative, of course, is derived from consequentialism: a better informed agent is able to bring about better consequences.
+
The problem for consequentialism is that it eliminates the distinction between actions that are morally required of us and morally supererogatory actions. The Consequentialist criterion (in its barest formulation) for right action is maximisation of a specified value: one is doing the right thing only insofar as one is maximising the good. However, we often take ourselves to be acting in a way that is morally permissible even when it clearly is not one which brings about the most good. Spending money on a holiday, for example, seems to be a candidate for a morally permissible action although there are other courses of action that would serve a much greater good overall. For instance, giving the money to an agency like the United Nations Children’s Fund (UNICEF) may help to save lives, a much greater good than a few days spent lazing about on a beach. If we are doing the right thing only if we are maximising the good, it seems that almost all of our actions are wrong. Critics contend that entails that consequentialism is too demanding as a moral theory. It does not seem right to say that one is doing wrong by going out for dinner on Friday night, or sitting around chatting with friends.  
  
<!--====How many consequences?====
+
Consequentialist replies to objections
The world as we normally experience it does seem to exhibit some kind of causal [[determinism]]. Thus, the effects of a particular action might have a virtually unlimited chain of other consequences. This raises a serious question for consequentialism: how long along the causal chain can one still be held morally accountable for the consequences of an action?
 
  
Moral theorists have a wide range of opinions on this matter. Some hold that the agent is responsible for ''all'' the consequences resulting from their action, whether foreseen or not. Others hold that the agent is only responsible for the consequences that they intended to bring about, regardless of what actually happens. Still others hold that the agent is responsible for any consequences they could have reasonably expected from their actions.
+
The conflict between the prescriptions of a moral theory and our ordinary way of thinking raises a question about how moral theories are to be evaluated. If a moral theory conflicts with our commonsense, pre-reflective morality, it could be that the theory is wrong or our moral convictions are wrong (or both). Do we revise our practices, our morality, to accord with the theory? Or do we reject the theory, and try to find another one that fits better with our moral convictions? The responses consequentialists are inclined to give to the above objections may be interpreted within this framework.  
  
Some consequentialists might hold that agents are wrong to commit acts that have unforeseen bad consequences, but shouldn't be condemned for them.  [[Utilitarian]] [[Peter Singer]] says that "Comfortably off Americans who give, say, 10 percent of their income to overseas aid organizations are so far ahead of most of their equally comfortable fellow citizens that I wouldn't go out of my way to chastise them for not doing more," even though "they should be doing much more" — presumably, he holds his tongue because criticizing donors would discourage people from donating, and thus have bad consequences ([http://people.brandeis.edu/~teuber/singermag.html see article]).  By the same basic principle — that condemnation shouldn't be given out when it has bad conseqences — it might be wrong to condemn people for wrong actions that they couldn't have known were wrong.—>
+
Revisionism
==Varieties of Consequentialism==
 
Consequentialism is a nefariously multi-headed beast, capable of adopting quite a variety of guises. However, there are certain consequentialist theories that serve as paradigms of consequentialism.
 
  
===Utilitarianism===
+
Some hard line consequentialists argue that moral common sense is mistaken and ought to be revised. Smart expresses this view as follows:
{{main|Utilitarianism}}
 
[[Image:Bentham.jpg|thumb|right|Jeremy Bentham]]
 
[[Utilitarianism | Hedonistic Utilitarianism]] is, historically, the paradigmatic example of a consequentialist moral theory. It holds that right action produces the most happiness for all agents. "Happiness" on this account is defined as the maximization of pleasure and the minimization of pain. This form of utilitarianism holds that what matters is the aggregate happiness; the happiness of everyone and not the happiness of any particular person.
 
  
[[John Stuart Mill]], in his exposition of hedonistic utilitarianism, proposed a hierarchy of pleasures, meaning that the pursuit of certain kinds of pleasure is more highly valued than the pursuit of other pleasures{{smref|Mill}}.
+
“Admittedly utilitarianism does have consequences which are incompatible with the common moral consciousness, but I tended to take the view “so much the worse for the common moral consciousness”. That is, I was inclined to reject the common methodology of testing general ethical principles by seeing how they square with our feelings in particular instances.” (J.J.C Smart)
  
Some contemporary utilitarians, such as [[Peter Singer]] are concerned to maximise the satisfaction of preferences, hence the expression "[[preference utilitarianism]]". Other contemporary forms of utilitarianism mirror the forms of consequentialism outlined below.
+
With respect to the case in which an innocent man was framed in order to avert a riot in which many more people would be killed, a consequentialist might point out that all options are terrible in this sort of scenario and insofar as our common sense moral judgments dictate that framing an innocent man ought not to be done, there is no reason to suppose that these common sense judgments are to be preferred over the result given by consequentialism. Similarly, with respect to the problem that consequentialist is committed to saying that since almost all our actions (including watching TV) fail to maximize utility, almost all our actions are wrong, some philosophers are inclined to accept this consequence. Peter Singer is probably the most influential defender of this sort of position.
  
===Ethical Egoism===
+
This sort of hard line commitment to the revision of our moral practices is probably not the most popular response taken by consequentialists. Most philosophers are uncomfortable with a large-scale revisionism of our moral practices as a result of a moral theory. As a result, they attempt to modify the theory to bring closer to ordinary moral thinking on certain key matters. The philosophical literature on consequentialism is enormous, proliferating with attempts to avoid the problems outlined above, and others, and bring consequentialism more into line with moral common sense. Only two of the most influential strategies of reply will be articulated below.
{{main|Ethical egoism}}
 
[[Ethical egoism]] can be understood as a consequentialist theory according to which the consequences for the individual agent are taken to matter more than any other result. Thus, egoism may license actions which are good for the agent, but are detrimental to general welfare. However, some advocates of egoism, most notably [[Ayn Rand]], have argued that the pursuit of selfish ends ultimately works out best for everyone (see [[Objectivist ethics]]).
 
  
===Rule Consequentialism===
 
In general, consequentialist theories focus on actions, however, this need not be the case. Rule consequentialism is a theory that is sometimes seen as an attempt to reconcile [[deontology]] and consequentialism. Like deontology, rule consequentialism holds that moral behavior involves following certain rules. However, rule consequentialism chooses rules based on the consequences that the selection of those rules have.
 
  
Various theorists are split as to whether the rules are the only the only determinant of moral behavior or not. For example, [[Robert Nozick]] holds that a certain set of minimal rules, which he calls "side-constraints", are necessary to ensure appropriate actions{{smref|Sch1}}. There are also differences as to how absolute these moral rules are. Thus, while Nozick's side-constraints are absolute restrictions on behavior, [[Amartya Sen]] proposes a theory which recognizes the importance of certain rules, but these rules are not absolute {{smref|Sch1}}. That is, they may be violated if strict adherence to the rule would lead to much more undesirable consequences.
 
  
===Negative Consequentialism===
+
1. RULE CONSEQUENTIALISM
Most consequentialist theories focus on ''promoting'' some sort of good consequences. However, one could equally well lay out a consequentialist theory that focuses solely on minimizing bad consequences. Of course, the maximization of good consequences could also involve the minimization of bad consequences, but the promotion of good consequences is usually of primary import.  
 
  
One major difference between these two approachess is the agent's responsibility. Postive consequentialism demands that we bring about good states of affairs, whereas negative consequentialism may only require that we avoid bad ones. A more strenuous version of negative consequentialism may actually require active intervention, but only to prevent harm from being done.
+
One common move in bringing consquentialism more in line with ordinary moral thinking is to specify the relation between consequences and right action indirectly. Classical Utilitarianism defines rightness directly. An act is right if and only if it increases aggregate happiness. Direct act consequentialism says that the moral rightness of an action depends on the consequences of that very action. By contrast, indirect act consequentialism says that the moral rightness of an act depends on the consequences of something else, such as motives or rules. (The direct / indirect distinction may be applied to any normative property.)
  
==Consequentialism and other moral theories==
+
One influential form of indirect consequentialism is rule utilitarianism. According to rule utilitarianism, the moral rightness of an act depends on its conformity with a rule, which itself is justified because it produces the best consequences overall. So rule consequentialism defines right action indirectly in terms of rules that tend to promote the non-moral good. In order to ascertain whether an action is right, one has to take into account the consequences of following the rule against which the action is assessed. In this respect, Rule Utilitarianism is indirect act consequentialism because it makes the rightness of an action dependent on the results of following a rule, rather than the action itself. A right action is one which conforms to a rule, which is justified because the consequences of following this rule are better than the consequences of following alternative rules.
Though many philosophers regard consequentialism as the most commonly held moral theory, it is not the only moral theory. Critiques raised by moral theorists who hold other moral theories have shaped the forms consequentialism takes in recent literature.
 
  
===Deontology===
+
Rule Consequentialism seems to be able to answer the objections from rights and justice outlined above. With respect to the framing of an innocent man in order to prevent a riot, a rule Utilitarian will reason that a society in which people adhere to the rule ‘don’t punish the innocent’ is bound to be better that a society in which this rule is not followed. The rule ‘don’t punish the innocent’ produces greater overall good. Punishing the innocent man is wrong because it does not accord with the rule which would bring about the best consequences overall. Secondly, the rule consequentialist may accommodate intuitions about special obligations by arguing that the consequences of following these sorts of rules will tend to be better than those generated by not adhering to agent relative duties. It seems reasonable to think that rule consequentialism will generate moral prescriptions quite closely in accordance with those of common sense.
Consequentialism is often contrasted with [[deontological ethics]]. Deontological theories focus on types of actions rather than the particular consequences of those actions. Thus, deontological theories hold that certain actions are wrong simply because of the nature of that action. Consequently, a deontologist might argue that we should stick to our duty regardless of the consequences. For example, [[Kant]] famously argued that we had a moral duty to always tell the truth, even to a murderer asking where their would-be victim is.  
 
  
However, consequentialist and deontological theories are not necessarily mutually exclusive. For example, [[T.M. Scanlon]] advances the idea that human rights, which are commonly considered a "deontological" concept, can only be justified with reference to the consequences of having those rights{{smref|Sch1}}. Similarly, [[Robert Nozick]] argues for a theory that is mostly consequentialist, but incorporates inviolable "side-constraints" which restrict the sort of actions agents are permitted to do{{smref|Sch1}}.
+
Justification and Deliberation
  
===Virtue Ethics===
+
A second popular consequentialist response to the above objections is to distinguish between a criterion of rightness and a decision procedure. This line of response goes back to Mill’s Utilitarianism, and his response to the objection that “There is not enough time, previous to action, for calculating and weighing any line of conduct on the general happiness.” Mill’s reply is to say that the “… there is ample time, namely, the whole past duration of the human species”. Ordinary morality may then be used as rules of thumb, guidelines that will help us in navigating through our daily lives.  
Consequentialism can also be contrasted with [[Aretaic turn|aretaic]] moral theories such as [[virtue ethics]]. In fact, Anscombe's paper which coined the term "consequentialism" also began the discussion of character-based ethical theories in modern philosophy{{smref|Ans}}.  
 
  
Whereas consequentialist theories, by definition, posit that consequences of action should be the primary focus of moral theories, virtue ethics insists that it is the character rather than the consequences of actions that should be the focal point. Some virtue ethicists hold that consequentialist theories totally disregard the development of moral character. For example, [[Phillipa Foot]], in an influential paper, argues that consequences in themselves have no ethical content, unless it has been provided by a virtue such as benevolence{{smref|Sch1}}.
+
This is important because it opens up a gap between how we ought to think in contexts of moral deliberation, and those properties of individual acts, which confer rightness or wrongness on the action. If the principle of Utility is a criterion of rightness, and not a decision procedure, then Utilitarianism does not entail that one ought (always) to try to calculate the greatest utility of one’s action. It will often be better to act in accordance with moral rules rather than trying to calculate the expected outcome of one’s action.
  
However, consequentialism and virtue ethics need not be understood to be entirely antagonistic. Consequentialist theories can consider character in several ways. For example, the effects on the character of the agent or any other people involved in an action may be regarded as a relevant consequences. Similarly, a consequentialist theory may aim at the maximization of a particular virtue or set of virtues. Finally, following Foot's lead, one might adopt a sort of consequentialism which argues that virtuous activity ultimately produces the best consequences.
+
This move may easily be transferred into the more general Consequentialist theories. If consequentialism is meant to be a theory of justification, rather than an account of deliberation, then it is quite coherent for a consequentialist to maintain that the best way of doing the right thing is not to calculate consequences but follow other policies. This provides a clear response to the problem of special obligations in that the best way of achieving the consequentialist objective might very well be to act in terms of our special obligations and continue to deliberate in accordance with ordinary moral thinking. This point is nicely illustrated by Austin, when he writes of the Utilitarian: “Though he approves with love because it accords with his principle, he is far from maintaining the general good ought to be the motive of the lover. It was never contended or conceived by a sound, orthodox utilitarian, that the lover should kiss his mistress with an eye to the common weal’ [cited in Petit 1997, p. 235].
 
 
==Criticisms of Consequentialism==
 
===General Criticisms===
 
Consequentialism has been criticized on several counts. According to [[G.E. Moore]] in ''Principia Ethica'', consequentialism (or at least classical utilitariansim) commits "the [[naturalistic fallacy]]" by assuming that "the good" can be adequately defined by some "natural" property or set of natural properties. This, he claims, is demonstrably false because for any X a consequentialist might propose as being innately good we can always ask "But is X good?" Thus we must have a tacit understanding of moral goodness that is different from any possible natural property or set of such properties. If this is the case, then, Moore argued, most forms of consequentialism are incoherent, since this innate sense of moral goodness is all that can be appealed to{{smref|Mor}}.
 
 
 
In a more extreme tenor, [[William Gass]] argues that moral theories such as consequentialism are unable to adequately explain what is wrong with a wrong action. Gass uses the example of an "obliging stranger" who is so obliging as to allow himself to be baked in an oven. Gass claims that the rationale that any moral theory might attempt to give for this wrongness, e.g. it does not bring about good results, is simply absurd. It is wrong to bake a stranger, however obliging, and nothing more can or need be said about it{{smref|Gass}}.
 
 
 
===Character-based Criticisms===
 
As already mentioned, G.E.M. Anscombe coined "consequentialism" in the process of criticizing the theory. She held that consequentialist theories hold moral agents responsible for consequences of their actions that they did not intend, and thus ignores the moral character of the agent involved{{smref|Ans}}. Not all consequentialists would see this as a valid criticism. After all, consequentialism places the strongest value on consequences.
 
[[Image:BernardWilliams.jpg|thumb|left|Bernard Williams]]
 
Along the same lines, [[Bernard Williams]] has argued that consequentialism is ''alienating'' because it requires moral agents to put too much distance between themselves and their own projects and commitments. Williams argues that consequentialism requires moral agents to take a strictly ''impersonal'' view of all actions, since it is only the consequences, and not who produces them, that is said to matter. Williams argues that this demands too much of moral agents &#8212; since (he claims) consequentialism demands that they be willing to sacrifice any and all personal projects and commitments in any given circumstance in order to pursue the most beneficent course of action possible. He argues further that consequentialism fails to make sense of intuitions that it ''can'' matter whether or not someone is ''personally'' the author of a particular consequence. For example, that having "dirty hands" by participating in a crime can matter, even if the crime would have been committed anyway, or would even have been worse, without the agent's participation. <!-- This really needs a quick discussion of William's firing-squad example. Maybe I'll add this later; but I wouldn't mind if someone beat me to it, either. —>
 
 
 
Some consequentialists &#8212; most notably [[Peter Railton]] &#8212; have attempted to develop a form of consequentialism that acknowledges and avoids the objections raised by Williams. Railton argues that Williams's criticisms can be avoided by adopting a form of consequentialism in which moral decisions are to be determined by the ''sort of life'' that they express. On his account, the agent should choose the sort of life that will, on the whole, produce the best overall effects{{smref|Sch1}}.
 
 
 
However, more recently, there have been attacks upon consequentialism in a similar vein. For example, [[Thomas Nagel]] holds that consequentialism fails to appropriately take into account the people affected by a particular action. He argues that a consequentialist cannot really critize human rights abuses in a war, for example, if they ultimately result in a better state of affairs{{smref|Sch1}}.
 
 
 
==Bibliography==
 
*{{note|Ans}}{{cite journal | author = Anscombe, G. E. M. | authorlink = G.E.M. Anscombe | publishyear = 1958 | title = Modern Moral Philosophy | journal = Philosophy | volume = 33 | pages = 1-19}}
 
*{{note|Ben}}{{cite book | title = An Introduction to the Principles of Moral Legislation | year = 1996 | last = Bentham | first = Jeremy | authorlink = Jeremy Bentham |publisher = Oxford University Press | location = Oxford | id = ISBN 0198205163 | url = http://www.la.utexas.edu/research/poltheory/bentham/ipml/ipml.toc.html}}
 
*{{note|Gass}}{{cite journal | author = Gass, William H. | authorlink = William Gass | publish year = 1957 | title = The Case of the Obliging Stranger | journal = The Philosophical Review | volume = 66 | pages = 193-204}}
 
*{{note|Hon}}{{Citepaper | Author = Honderich, Ted | Title = Consequentialism, Moralities of Concern and Selfishness | PublishYear = 2003 | URL = http://www.ucl.ac.uk/~uctytho/ted9.htm}}
 
*{{note|Mill}}{{cite book | title = Utilitarianism | year = 1998 | last = Mill | first = John Stuart | authorlink = John Stuart Mill | publisher = Oxford University Press | location = Oxford | id = ISBN 019875163X | url = http://www.utilitarianism.com/mill1.htm}}
 
*{{note|Mor}}{{cite book | title = Principia Ethica | year = 1903 | last = Moore | first = G. E. | authorlink = G.E. Moore | publisher = Cambridge University Press | location = Cambridge | id = ISBN 052144848 | url = http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica}}
 
*{{note|Sch1}}{{cite book | title = Consequentialism and Its Critics | year = 1988 | last = Scheffler | first = Samuel (Ed.) | publisher = Oxford University Press | location = Oxford | id = ISBN 0198750730}}
 
*{{note|Sing}}{{cite book | title = Unsanctifying Human Life | last = Singer | first = Peter | authorlink = Peter Singer | editor = Helga Kuhse, ed. | year = 2002 | publisher = Blackwell | location = Oxford | id = ISBN 0631225072}}
 
 
 
==See also==
 
*[[Ethics]]
 
*[[Utilitarianism]]
 
*[[Egoism]]
 
*[[Deontological ethics|Deontology]]
 
*[[Virtue ethics]]
 
*[[Altruism (ethical doctrine)|Altruism]]
 
 
 
===Notable Consequentialists===
 
*[[Jeremy Bentham]]
 
*[[R.M. Hare]]
 
*[[Amartya Sen]]
 
*[[Henry Sidgwick]]
 
*[[Peter Singer]]
 
*[[John Stuart Mill]]
 
 
 
==Further Reading==
 
*{{cite book | title = Consequentialism | year = 2002 | last = Darwall | first = Stephen (Ed.) | publisher = Blackwell | location = Oxford | id = ISBN 0631231080}}
 
*{{cite book | last = Scheffler | first = Samuel | title = The Rejection of Consequentialism: A Philosophical Investigation of the Considerations Underlying Rival Moral Conceptions | year = 1994 | publisher = Oxford University Press | location = Oxford | id = ISBN 0198235119}}
 
 
 
==External links==
 
*Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
 
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/ Consequentialism]
 
** [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism-rule/ Rule Consequentialism]
 
*[http://www.utilitarianism.com/ Utiliarianism Resources]
 
 
 
[[Category:Meta-ethics]]
 
[[Category:Ethics]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
 
 
 
{{Credit|47008809}}
 

Revision as of 11:31, 19 June 2006

Consequentialism

OVERVIEW:

One central aim of normative ethics is to provide general principles of right conduct that specify the conditions under which an action is right or wrong. A consequentialist moral theory defines normative properties such as rightness, praiseworthiness, and virtuousness in terms of the promotion of valuable states of affairs. Classical Utilitarianism as advanced by Bentham and Mill provides a clear example of consequentialism, defining right actions as those maximising the happiness of sentient beings. Consequentialism epitomises the intuition that morality should be concerned with improving the quality of people’s lives, and, as such, can seem to be little more than common sense. However, consequentialism has problems accounting for intuitions concerning justice and rights, the existence of special obligations, and a distinction between what is morally required and morally supererogatory.

MORAL THEORIES: TELEOLOGICAL AND NON-TELEOLOGICAL

Moral theories include two components: a theory of value (a theory of the good) and a theory of the right. A theory of value provides an account of what things are intrinsically good, or what states of affairs we would like to have realised. For example, hedonism is a theory of value according to which the happiness (qualitative states) of sentient beings is the only intrinsic good. The second component of a moral theory is the specification of how moral agents ought to responds to the valuable properties specified by the theory of value. This is most often understood in terms of a theory of right action, for modern ethical thinking has tended to focus centrally concerned with what is done, as over above, (e.g.) what sort of persons we should become. (See entry on Virtue Ethics)

On a standard taxonomy, moral theories may be classified according to how they specify the relation between the theory of value and the theory of right action. The Greek word telos means goal, end, or purpose; teleology is the study of goals, ends and purposes; teleological ethical theories, therefore, emphasise that morality is oriented toward bringing about a certain goal. Consequentialism is one important sort of teleological moral theory. Consequentialism in its most general form is the claim that a normative property (such as ‘rightness’, ‘wrongness’ ‘virtuousness’ etc) depends on the value of consequences. More particularly, according to act consequentialism the rightness of an action derives from the value of the consequences, that is, what is brought about by the action. Act consequentialism holds that the right act for a particular agent is the one that produces the greatest balance of good over bad. Rule consequentialism justifies moral rules according to the value that the rules tend to promote. Motive consequentialism is the thesis that the moral qualities of an action depend on the overall consequences of actions done from a particular motive. This article will focus most centrally on act consequentialism.

Interpretations of what is to be included under the rubric of consequentialism are not entirely standard in the philosophical literature. One significant area of disagreement is whether consequentialism must be regarded as an agent neutral theory. Agent neutrality is the thesis that when comparisons are made as to the overall goodness or badness of actions, this judgment must be made from an objective perspective, without taking the agent’s particular circumstances into account. This is important insofar a most consequentialists would want to differentiate their theory from ethical egoism, which has a superficially similar structure to consequentialism as outline above. Ethical egoism may be understood as the moral theory according to which right actions are those that bring about the greatest overall good for the agent him or herself. The ethical egoist does not consider the best state of the world overall, but the best state of the world from his perspective. In this article, I shall assume that a moral theory that does not include the thesis of agent neutrality is nonetheless legitimately classified as consequentialist moral theory.

CLASSICAL UTLITARIANISM AND CONSEQUENTIALISM:

The most well known example of a consequentialist ethical theory is Classical Utilitarianism, as articulated in the seminal writings of Bentham and Mill. Consequentialism may be helpfully understood in terms of its relation to Classical Utilitarianism. Classical Utilitarianism is hedonistic act consequentialism. This means that Classical Utilitarianism is a consequentialist ethical theory that endorses hedonism as a theory of value, and focuses on actions (as opposed to rules, motives, character traits). This is clearly evident in Principle of Utility, which Mill articulates as follows:

The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness; wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.

The Hedonism of Classical Utilitarianism has always been controversial, and many philosophers have rejected Hedonism as a theory of value without rejecting the insight the morality ought to be concerned with promoting valuable states of affairs. Philosophers have then tended to articulate alternative accounts of value, without abandoning the consequentialism in Classical Utilitarianism. More generally, the varieties of consequentialism are helpfully understood as revisions of Classical Utilitarianism in an attempt to accommodate its basic insight whilst avoiding the objections to which Classical Utilitarianism seems susceptible.

All Utilitarian theories are versions of consequentialism, since consequentialism is one element of Utilitarianism. However, Utilitarianism is sometimes understood as a brand of consequentialism which endorses theory of value that is specifically concerned with the welfare of individual human beings. On this definition, Utilitarianism is welfarist consequentialism. Some welfarist theories are subjectivist, including Hedonism and desire and preference satisfaction theories. Other welfarist theories are objective, including G.E. Moore’s Ideal Utilitarianism. Perfectionist Consequentialist theories would not, on this definition count as forms of Utilitarianism. But this usage is not standard across the philosophical literature.


OBJECTIONS TO CONSEQUENTIALISM

Consequentialism is in conflict with ordinary moral thinking in a number of ways.

Firstly, consequentialism seems unable to accommodate justice and rights. In J.J.C Smart’s (1978) formulates the problem for consequentialism with respect to justice as follows: “The most poignant sort of case, of course, is that of the punishment of an innocent man. Suppose that in order to prevent a riot in which thousands would certainly be killed a sheriff were to frame and execute an innocent man. On utilitarian principles would not the sacrifice of one life in order to save thousands be justified?” (Smart’s discussion is with particular reference to Utilitarianism, but Utilitarianism is a form of consequentialism.) If the sheriff frames the stranger he will bring about more good consequences than bad consequences. We may simply stipulate that this is so. According to consequentialism, therefore, this is the right action to perform. However, an innocent man does not deserve to be punished. So, it seems, consequentialism does not accommodate justice.

A structurally very similar problem arises with respect to consequentialism and rights. The concept of a ‘right’ has to do with protecting a person’s important interests. Rights place limits on how an individual may be treated, regardless of the good purposes that might be accomplished” (Rachels 2003, p. 108). Once again, a consequentialist moral theory is apparently committed to the claim that nothing that is ultimately prohibited, so long as the good consequences of this action outweigh the bad. Rape, torture, and all manner of horrific acts may in principle be required whenever the overall consequences are good enough.

Another problem for consequentialism is accounting for the existence of special ties of obligation. Special obligations include those acquired by entering into contracts, obligations acquired in virtue of occupying a certain occupational role, and family ties. For example, a teacher is obligated to certain sorts of actions related to satisfying occupational duties, and these actions are required of him or her only because of the special duties incumbent on a teacher. Similarly, a mother or father is usually thought to be obligated to her or his children in a way she or he is not obligated to other people’s children. These are sometime called agent-relative duties. Consequentialism, however, is usually understood to be an agent neural moral theory, and so, one is obligated to bring about good for those who would benefit from it most, irrespective of their relationship to oneself. This consequence is at odds with ordinary thinking in that it seems that a person reasonably displays concern for her family that she does not display for others. But consequentialism requires one to promote the good in general, and does therefore not accommodate the common sense intuition that special obligations generate special duties, and that (e.g.) a father is required to do things for his own family that he is not required to do for people in general.

On a closely related point, W.D. Ross has argued that if breaking a promise brings about slightly more happiness, then the Classical Utilitarian must prescribe that the promise is to be broken. Imagine that you’ve made a promise to give me a ride to the airport. However, at the last moment someone asks you to come away for the weekend, making it impossible to give me the ride. Imagine that there would be a slightly greater balance of gain for everyone concerned – you really are a bundle of fun – if you broke your promise. Ross’s point is that consequentialism says you should break your promise even if the gain is only slightly more. But this seems to imply that consequentialism cannot accommodate the point that one is obligated by the promise, and a slight gain in overall pleasure does not seem to trump this obligation.

Another important objection to consequentialism is that it is too demanding as a moral theory. To understand this objection, it is necessary to spend a moment considering some key features of our common moral beliefs. In ordinary morality, there is a distinction between what we are morally required to do (or not do) and what is good or morally significant to do, but what is not strictly required. For example, ‘Thou shall not murder’ entails that we are required to refrain from intentionally killing innocent people. By contrast, acts of charity are morally praiseworthy, but we are not, it is usually thought, strictly required to be charitable. Rather, charity is something that goes beyond the bounds of duty. One would not normally be blamed for failing to give to charity, although one would be morally praised for acts of charity. Actions that are morally admirable to do but not strictly required of us are called supererogatory actions.

The problem for consequentialism is that it eliminates the distinction between actions that are morally required of us and morally supererogatory actions. The Consequentialist criterion (in its barest formulation) for right action is maximisation of a specified value: one is doing the right thing only insofar as one is maximising the good. However, we often take ourselves to be acting in a way that is morally permissible even when it clearly is not one which brings about the most good. Spending money on a holiday, for example, seems to be a candidate for a morally permissible action although there are other courses of action that would serve a much greater good overall. For instance, giving the money to an agency like the United Nations Children’s Fund (UNICEF) may help to save lives, a much greater good than a few days spent lazing about on a beach. If we are doing the right thing only if we are maximising the good, it seems that almost all of our actions are wrong. Critics contend that entails that consequentialism is too demanding as a moral theory. It does not seem right to say that one is doing wrong by going out for dinner on Friday night, or sitting around chatting with friends.

Consequentialist replies to objections

The conflict between the prescriptions of a moral theory and our ordinary way of thinking raises a question about how moral theories are to be evaluated. If a moral theory conflicts with our commonsense, pre-reflective morality, it could be that the theory is wrong or our moral convictions are wrong (or both). Do we revise our practices, our morality, to accord with the theory? Or do we reject the theory, and try to find another one that fits better with our moral convictions? The responses consequentialists are inclined to give to the above objections may be interpreted within this framework.

Revisionism

Some hard line consequentialists argue that moral common sense is mistaken and ought to be revised. Smart expresses this view as follows:

“Admittedly utilitarianism does have consequences which are incompatible with the common moral consciousness, but I tended to take the view “so much the worse for the common moral consciousness”. That is, I was inclined to reject the common methodology of testing general ethical principles by seeing how they square with our feelings in particular instances.” (J.J.C Smart)

With respect to the case in which an innocent man was framed in order to avert a riot in which many more people would be killed, a consequentialist might point out that all options are terrible in this sort of scenario and insofar as our common sense moral judgments dictate that framing an innocent man ought not to be done, there is no reason to suppose that these common sense judgments are to be preferred over the result given by consequentialism. Similarly, with respect to the problem that consequentialist is committed to saying that since almost all our actions (including watching TV) fail to maximize utility, almost all our actions are wrong, some philosophers are inclined to accept this consequence. Peter Singer is probably the most influential defender of this sort of position.

This sort of hard line commitment to the revision of our moral practices is probably not the most popular response taken by consequentialists. Most philosophers are uncomfortable with a large-scale revisionism of our moral practices as a result of a moral theory. As a result, they attempt to modify the theory to bring closer to ordinary moral thinking on certain key matters. The philosophical literature on consequentialism is enormous, proliferating with attempts to avoid the problems outlined above, and others, and bring consequentialism more into line with moral common sense. Only two of the most influential strategies of reply will be articulated below.


1. RULE CONSEQUENTIALISM

One common move in bringing consquentialism more in line with ordinary moral thinking is to specify the relation between consequences and right action indirectly. Classical Utilitarianism defines rightness directly. An act is right if and only if it increases aggregate happiness. Direct act consequentialism says that the moral rightness of an action depends on the consequences of that very action. By contrast, indirect act consequentialism says that the moral rightness of an act depends on the consequences of something else, such as motives or rules. (The direct / indirect distinction may be applied to any normative property.)

One influential form of indirect consequentialism is rule utilitarianism. According to rule utilitarianism, the moral rightness of an act depends on its conformity with a rule, which itself is justified because it produces the best consequences overall. So rule consequentialism defines right action indirectly in terms of rules that tend to promote the non-moral good. In order to ascertain whether an action is right, one has to take into account the consequences of following the rule against which the action is assessed. In this respect, Rule Utilitarianism is indirect act consequentialism because it makes the rightness of an action dependent on the results of following a rule, rather than the action itself. A right action is one which conforms to a rule, which is justified because the consequences of following this rule are better than the consequences of following alternative rules.

Rule Consequentialism seems to be able to answer the objections from rights and justice outlined above. With respect to the framing of an innocent man in order to prevent a riot, a rule Utilitarian will reason that a society in which people adhere to the rule ‘don’t punish the innocent’ is bound to be better that a society in which this rule is not followed. The rule ‘don’t punish the innocent’ produces greater overall good. Punishing the innocent man is wrong because it does not accord with the rule which would bring about the best consequences overall. Secondly, the rule consequentialist may accommodate intuitions about special obligations by arguing that the consequences of following these sorts of rules will tend to be better than those generated by not adhering to agent relative duties. It seems reasonable to think that rule consequentialism will generate moral prescriptions quite closely in accordance with those of common sense.

Justification and Deliberation

A second popular consequentialist response to the above objections is to distinguish between a criterion of rightness and a decision procedure. This line of response goes back to Mill’s Utilitarianism, and his response to the objection that “There is not enough time, previous to action, for calculating and weighing any line of conduct on the general happiness.” Mill’s reply is to say that the “… there is ample time, namely, the whole past duration of the human species”. Ordinary morality may then be used as rules of thumb, guidelines that will help us in navigating through our daily lives.

This is important because it opens up a gap between how we ought to think in contexts of moral deliberation, and those properties of individual acts, which confer rightness or wrongness on the action. If the principle of Utility is a criterion of rightness, and not a decision procedure, then Utilitarianism does not entail that one ought (always) to try to calculate the greatest utility of one’s action. It will often be better to act in accordance with moral rules rather than trying to calculate the expected outcome of one’s action.

This move may easily be transferred into the more general Consequentialist theories. If consequentialism is meant to be a theory of justification, rather than an account of deliberation, then it is quite coherent for a consequentialist to maintain that the best way of doing the right thing is not to calculate consequences but follow other policies. This provides a clear response to the problem of special obligations in that the best way of achieving the consequentialist objective might very well be to act in terms of our special obligations and continue to deliberate in accordance with ordinary moral thinking. This point is nicely illustrated by Austin, when he writes of the Utilitarian: “Though he approves with love because it accords with his principle, he is far from maintaining the general good ought to be the motive of the lover. It was never contended or conceived by a sound, orthodox utilitarian, that the lover should kiss his mistress with an eye to the common weal’ [cited in Petit 1997, p. 235].