Difference between revisions of "Authenticity (philosophy)" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
 
(25 intermediate revisions by 8 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{claimed}}
+
{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{Paid}}{{copyedited}}
'''Authenticity''' is a technical term in [[existentialism|existentialist philosophy]]. In this philosophy, the [[conscious]] [[self]] is seen as coming to terms with being in a material world and with encountering external forces, pressures and influences which are [[Other|very different]] from, and other than, itself. Authenticity is the degree to which one is true to one's own personality, spirit, or character, despite these pressures.  [[Existentialist]]s see this process in different ways.
+
{{toc|right}}
 +
'''Authenticity''' is a philosophical concept that denotes the genuine, original, true state of human existence. The concept arises from the insights that human beings generally live or exist in an inauthentic way and that the genuine sense of self and its relationship with others (including [[God]] and/or other people), have been lost. The authentic life is often described as a life of [[freedom]], joy, meaning, value, and happiness.  
  
==Views of authenticity==
+
[[Religion|Religious]] traditions generally incorporate such insights into their teachings, which often emphasize the restoration of an authentic self and society. In philosophy, the concept has also been discussed by many thinkers. According to [[Existentialism|Existentialists]], who formally thematized the concept of authenticity, social relationships, cultural values, and norms construct an inauthentic self; the recovery of the authentic self requires a radical reexamination of cultural contexts, habitual lifestyles, and ways of thinking. 
  
It is difficult to determine the origin of the contemporary notion of authenticity. Writers on the subject of authenticity have often attempted to ground their views in work from a wide variety of historical periods. Secular and religious notions of authenticity have coexisted for centuries under different guises; perhaps the earliest account of authenticity that remains popular is [[Socrates]]' admonition that the "unexamined" life is not worth living.
+
== General characteristics ==
  
In the twentieth century, Anglo-American discussions of authenticity often center around the writers of a few key figures associated with [[existentialism|existentialist philosophy]], where the term originated; because most of these writers wrote in languages other than English, the process of translating and anthologizing has had a strong impact on the debate. [[Walter Kaufmann (philosopher)|Walter Kaufmann]] might be credited with creating a "canon" of existentialist writers which include:
+
If authenticity can only be described in very abstract terms, or as the negative of inauthenticity, what can be said about it directly? All writers generally agree that authenticity is:
  
* [[Søren Kierkegaard]]
+
* Something to be pursued as a goal intrinsic to "the good life."
* [[Martin Heidegger]]
+
* Intrinsically difficult, due in part to social pressures to live inauthentically, and in part due to a person's own character.
* [[Jean-Paul Sartre]]
+
* A revelatory state, where one perceives oneself, other people, and sometimes even things, in a radically new way.
* [[Therese Kennelly]]
+
 
For these writers, the [[conscious]] [[self]] is seen as coming to terms with being in a material world and with encountering external forces and influences which are very different from itself; authenticity is one way in which the self acts and changes in response to these pressures.
+
One might add that many, though not all, writers have agreed that authenticity also:
 +
 
 +
* Requires self-knowledge.
 +
* Alters radically one's relationships with others (God and/or people).
 +
* Carries with it its own set of moral obligations.
 +
 
 +
The notion of authenticity also fits in to [[utopia]]n ideas, in as much as many believe that a utopia:
  
Authenticity is often "at the limits" of language; it is described as the negative space around inauthenticity, with reference to examples of inauthentic living. Sartre's novels are perhaps the easiest access to this mode of describing authenticity: they often contain characters and anti-heroes who base their actions on external pressures—the pressure to appear to be a certain kind of person, the pressure to adopt a particular mode of living, the pressure to ignore one's own moral and aesthetic objections in order to have a more comfortable existence. His work also includes characters who do not understand their own reasons for acting, or who ignore crucial facts about their own lives in order to avoid uncomfortable truths; this connects his work with the philosophical tradition.
+
* Requires authenticity among its citizens to exist, ''or''
 +
* Would remove physical and economic barriers to pursuing authenticity.
 +
 
 +
==Religious perspective ==
 +
 
 +
Religious traditions generally contain the concept of authenticity. Based upon the insight that human beings are vulnerable to various temptations, religions offer teachings, practical methodologies, rituals, trainings, institutionalized mechanism, and other ways to allow human beings to recover an authentic self and life. The concept of [[salvation]], for example, is built upon the idea that there is some authentic state of being.
  
Sartre is concerned also with the "vertiginous" experience of absolute freedom. Under Sartre's view, this experience, necessary for the state of authenticity, can be sufficiently unpleasant that it leads people to inauthentic ways of living.
+
The concept of authenticity can be applied to almost all key concepts in religious teachings. It functions to distinguish religious ideals from secular notions. For example, religious teachings often distinguish genuine happiness, which is built upon spiritual awakening or oneness with the divine or some other spiritual element, from secular happiness built upon material wealth and secular values alone. Genuine joy is also distinguished from [[hedonism|hedonistic]] pleasure in a pejorative sense. Even genuine love is distinguished from a secular notion of love. Authenticity separates and establishes the religious realm or the sacred realm in sharp contrast with the mundane or secular realm. Thus, religious teachings are, in a sense, attempts to present an authentic way of life to the world. Religious teachings challenge people, who would otherwise continue to live as they are, to question the way they live.
  
In all writers, authenticity is seen as a very general concept, not attached to any particular political or aesthetic ideology. This is a necessary aspect of authenticity: because it concerns a person's ''relation'' with the world, it can not be arrived at by simply repeating a set of actions or taking up a set of positions. In this manner, authenticity is connected with creativity: the impetus to action must arise from the person in question, and not be externally imposed. Heidegger takes this notion to the extreme, by speaking in very abstract terms about modes of living; his terminology was adopted and simplified by Sartre in his philosophical works. Kierkegaard's work (such as the "Panegyric Upon Abraham" from his ''[[Fear and Trembling]]'') often focuses on biblical stories which are (naturally) not directly imitatable. Sartre, as has been noted above, focused on inauthentic existence as a way to avoid the paradoxical problem of appearing to provide prescriptions for a mode of living that rejects external dictates.
+
== Philosophical perspectives ==
  
These considerations aside, it is the case that authenticity has been associated with various human activities. For Sartre, [[Jazz]] music was a representation of freedom; this may have been in part because Jazz was associated with [[African-American]] culture, and was thus in opposition to Western culture generally, which Sartre considered hopelessly inauthentic. [[Theodor Adorno]], however, another writer and philosopher concerned with the notion of authenticity, despised Jazz music because he saw it as a false representation that could give the appearance of authenticity but that was as much bound up in concerns with appearance and audience as many other forms of art. Heidegger in his later life associated authenticity with non-technological modes of existence, seeing technology as distorting a more "authentic" relationship with the natural world.
+
The concept of authenticity has been discussed in diverse ways throughout philosophical history. For example, [[Socrates]]'s dictums, such as, "Unexamined life is not worth living," or "Know yourself," can be seen as his attempts to lead others to the discovery of the authentic self and way of life. [[Kierkegaard]] examined the loss of the genuine self in the mass, in society, and tried to present the process of recovering the authentic self within a [[theism|theistic]] context. Other existential thinkers such as [[Nietzsche]], [[Pascal]], [[Heidegger]], [[Karl Jaspers]], and [[Sartre]] equally discussed the issue of authenticity and developed various ways to deal with the issue.
  
Most writers on inauthenticity in the [[twentieth century]] considered the predominant cultural norms to be inauthentic; not only because they were seen as forced on people, but also because, in themselves, they required people to behave inauthentically towards their own desires, obscuring true reasons for acting. [[Advertising]], in as much as it attempted to give people a reason for doing something that they did not already possess, was a "textbook" example of how Western culture distorted the individual for external reasons. Race relations are seen as another limit on authenticity, as they demand that the self engage with others on the basis of external attributes. An early example of the connection between inauthenticity and capitalism was made by [[Karl Marx]], whose notion of "[[Marx's theory of alienation|alienation]]" can be linked to the later discourse on the nature of inauthenticity.
+
The term ''eigentlich'' (authentic) in German contains the element of ''eigen'' ("one's own"). Authenticity, thus, includes the element of "one's own unique self." Accordingly, recovery of authenticity, at least in German, implies the recovery of one's own unique identity. When existential thinkers speak of authenticity, they often include this element and contrast the unique self against the concept of mass, in which the individual is no more than just a number.
  
Hence those concerned with living authentically have often led unusual lives that opposed cultural norms; the rise of the [[counter-culture]] in the 1960s in Europe and America was seen by many as a new opportunity to live an authentic existence. Many, however, have pointed out that just because one lives unusually, one is not necessarily in an authentic state of being. The connection of the violation of cultural norms to authenticity, however, is strong and real, and continues today: among artists who explicitly violate the conventions of their profession, for example. The connection of inauthenticity to [[capitalism]] is contained in the notion of "[[selling out]]," used to describe an artist whose work has become inauthentic after achieving commercial success and thus becoming to an extent integrated into an inauthentic system.
+
Existential philosophers build the element of authenticity into their own philosophical thought and configure it according to central themes of their works. Accordingly, the way each philosopher deals with authenticity is different and expositions of their views of authenticity are not straightforward. Only a few are introduced below as examples.  
  
If authenticity can only be described in very abstract terms, or as the negative of inauthenticity, what can be said about it directly? All writers agree that authenticity is:
+
== Kierkegaard==
  
* Something to be pursued as a goal intrinsic to "the good life."
+
[[Kierkegaard]] criticized the philosophical systems that were brought on by philosophers such as [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel]] before him and the Danish Hegelians, although Kierkegaard respected the philosophy of [[Immanuel Kant]].<ref>Ronald M. Green, ''Kierkegaard and Kant: The Hidden Debt'' (SUNY Press, 1992). ISBN 0791411079</ref>  He measured himself against the model of philosophy which he found in Socrates, which aims to draw one's attention not to explanatory systems, but rather to the issue of how one exists.
* Intrinsically difficult, due in part to social pressures to live inauthentically, and in part due to a person's own character.
 
* A revelatory state, where one perceives oneself, other people, and sometimes even things, in a radically new way.
 
  
One might add that many, though not all, writers have agreed that authenticity also:
+
One of Kierkegaard's recurrent themes is the importance of [[subjectivity]], which has to do with the way people relate themselves to (objective) truths.  In ''[[Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments]]'', he argues that "subjectivity is truth" and "truth is subjectivity."  What he means by this is that most essentially, truth is not just a matter of discovering objective facts. While objective facts are important, there is a second and more crucial element of truth, which involves how one relates oneself to those matters of fact.  Since how one acts is, from the ethical perspective, more important than any matter of fact, truth is to be found in subjectivity rather than objectivity.<ref>Howard V. and Edna H. Hong, "Subjectivity/Objectivity." ''Søren Kierkegaard's Journals and Papers''.(Indiana University Press, 1975). ISBN 0253182433 </ref>
  
* Requires self-knowledge.
+
===Individuality===
* Alters radically one's relationships with other people.
 
* Carries with it its own set of moral obligations.
 
* Can be obtained regardless of race, gender and class.
 
  
The notion of authenticity also fits in to [[utopia]]n ideology, in as much as many believe that a utopia:
+
For Kierkegaard, true [[individual]]ity is called selfhood. Becoming aware of true self is the true task and endeavor in life&mdash;it is an ethical imperative, as well as preparatory to a true religious understanding. Individuals can exist at a level that is less than true selfhood. One can live, for example, simply in terms of [[pleasure]]s&mdash;the immediate satisfaction of desires, propensities, or distractions. In this way, people glide through life without direction or purpose. To have a direction, one must have a purpose that defines for him the meaning of his lives.
  
* Requires authenticity among its citizens to exist, ''or''
+
In ''[[Sickness Unto Death]],'' specifically, Kierkegaard deals with the self as a product of relations. In this sense, a human results from a relation between the Infinite (Noumena, spirit, eternal) and Finite (Phenomena, body, temporal). This does not create a true self, as a human can live without a "self" as he defines it. Instead, the Self or ability for the self to be created from a relation to the Absolute or God (the Self can only be realized through a relation to God) arises as a relation between the relation of the Finite and Infinite relating back to the human. This would be a positive relation.
* Would remove physical and economic barriers to pursuing authenticity.
 
  
==Criticisms of authenticity==
+
An individual person, for Kierkegaard, is a particular that no abstract formula or definition can ever capture. Including the individual in "the public" (or "the crowd" or "the herd") or subsuming a human being as simply a member of a species is a reduction of the true meaning of life for individuals. What philosophy or politics try to do is to categorize and pigeonhole individuals by group characteristics instead of individual differences. For Kierkegaard, those differences are what make people who they are.
  
Authenticity has its paradoxical components. Sartre illustrated these in his extensive writings, pointing to the conflict between seeing the self as unique and different from the world, but the self is embedded in a world which clearly contains other such beings.  
+
Kierkegaard's critique of the modern age, therefore, is about the loss of what it means to be an individual. Modern society contributes to this dissolution of what it means to be an individual. Through its production of the [[false idol]] of "the public," it diverts attention away from individuals to a mass public that loses itself in abstractions, communal dreams, and fantasies. It is helped in this task by the media and the mass production of products to keep it distracted. Although Kierkegaard attacked "the public," he is supportive of communities.
  
Stated as a doctrine authenticity can be thought to be self-defeating. This is because it is thereby classified and becomes part of the non-self, an object of perhaps methodical study among others. This is opposed to the notion of the individual self which seeks its own solution independently of competing external ideologies.
+
==[[Sartre]] and others ==
  
Another criticism is that the solution to Sartre's difficulties involves some compromise to allow unique individuals to co-exist in a way which is acceptable to all of them. Therefore public [[ethics]] or [[morality]] may be a limit on authenticity.
+
Secular and religious notions of authenticity have coexisted for centuries under different guises. For these writers, the [[conscious]] [[self]] is seen as coming to terms with being in a material world and with encountering external forces and influences which are very different from itself; authenticity is one way in which the self acts and changes in response to these pressures.
  
Because authenticity is such a slippery concept, and because it can never be rigorously defined, it can be seen as a threat to [[rationality]] or to [[The Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] ideas about the transparency of laws.
+
Authenticity is often "at the limits" of language; it is described as the negative space around inauthenticity, with reference to examples of inauthentic living. Sartre's novels are perhaps the easiest access to this mode of describing authenticity: they often contain characters and anti-heroes who base their actions on external pressures—the pressure to appear to be a certain kind of person, the pressure to adopt a particular mode of living, the pressure to ignore one's own moral and aesthetic objections in order to have a more comfortable existence. His work also includes characters who do not understand their own reasons for acting, or who ignore crucial facts about their own lives in order to avoid uncomfortable truths; this connects his work with the philosophical tradition.
  
==Authenticity today==
+
Sartre is concerned also with the "vertiginous" experience of absolute freedom. Under Sartre's view, this experience, necessary for the state of authenticity, can be sufficiently unpleasant that it leads people to inauthentic ways of living.
  
British philosophy has seen authenticity as part of the continuation of the Continental [[dualist]] position stated by [[Descartes]]. He held that reality consists of two kinds of things, mental and physical substances, which are fundamentally different from each other. Authenticity is based on a clear distinction between self and the [[other]], non-self, or world.
+
These considerations aside, it is the case that authenticity has been associated with various cultural activities. For Sartre, [[Jazz]] music, for example, was a representation of freedom; this may have been in part because Jazz was associated with [[African-American]] culture, and was thus in opposition to Western culture generally, which Sartre considered hopelessly inauthentic. [[Theodor Adorno]], however, another writer and philosopher concerned with the notion of authenticity, despised Jazz music because he saw it as a false representation that could give the appearance of authenticity but that was as much bound up in concerns with appearance and audience as many other forms of art. Heidegger, in his later life, associated authenticity with non-technological modes of existence, seeing technology as distorting a more "authentic" relationship with the natural world.
  
American philosophy has eagerly pursued the authenticity ideal, seeing it as central to the values of individuality and independence prevalent in American society.  
+
Most writers on inauthenticity in the twentieth century considered the predominant cultural norms to be inauthentic; not only because they were seen as forced on people, but also because, in themselves, they required people to behave inauthentically towards their own desires, obscuring true reasons for acting. [[Advertising]], in as much as it attempted to give people a reason for doing something that they did not already possess, was a "textbook" example of how Western culture distorted the individual for external reasons. Race relations are seen as another limit on authenticity, as they demand that the self engage with others on the basis of external attributes. An early example of the connection between inauthenticity and capitalism was made by [[Karl Marx]], whose notion of "[[Marx's theory of alienation|alienation]]" can be linked to the later discourse on the nature of inauthenticity.
  
Those who advocate [[social reform]] value the study of authenticity since it can provide a radical  manifesto and an overview of the shortcomings of social structures.
+
==Notes==
 +
<references/>
  
 
==References==
 
==References==
* Lionel Trilling <cite>[[Sincerity and Authenticity]]</cite>; ISBN 0-192-81166-5; Harvard UP 1974
 
* Charles Taylor <cite>[[The Ethics of Authenticity]]</cite>; ISBN 0-674-26863-6; Harvard UP 1992
 
* [http://www.acsu.buffalo.edu/~adspear/kaufmann.htm Walter Kaufmann, whose life increasingly focused on a search for authenticity.]
 
* [http://www.authenticbusiness.co.uk/ Authentic Business] is a non-profit [[United Kingdom|British]] online community exploring doing business with purpose
 
* [http://www.stagisblog.com/stagis/authenticity/ Stagisblog] is a blog run by communication consultants discussing the paradoxial idea of the 'authentic organizational identity'
 
  
[[Category:Philosophical terminology]]
+
*Anton, Corey. ''Selfhood and Authenticity.'' Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2001. ISBN 0791448991
[[Category:Martin Heidegger]]
+
*Chen, Xunwu. ''Being and Authenticity.'' Value inquiry book series, v. 149. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2004. ISBN 9042008288
[[Category:Existentialism]]
+
*Ferrara, Alessandro, ''Reflective Authenticity: Rethinking the Project of Modernity,'' London and New York, Routledge, 1998. ISBN 041513062X
 +
*Golomb, Jacob. ''In Search of Authenticity From Kierkegaard to Camus. Problems of Modern European Thought.'' London: Routledge, 1995. ISBN 0415119464
 +
*Moore, Thomas. ''Original Self Living with Paradox and Authenticity.'' New York: HarperCollins, 2000. ISBN 0060195428
 +
*Nehamas, Alexander. ''Virtues of Authenticity Essays on Plato and Socrates.'' Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1999. ISBN 0691001774
 +
*Taylor, Charles. ''The Ethics of Authenticity.'' Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1992. ISBN 0674268636
 +
*Trilling, Lionel. ''Sincerity and Authenticity.'' Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1972. ISBN 0674808606
 +
*Zimmerman, Michael E. ''Eclipse of the Self The Development of Heidegger's Concept of Authenticity.'' Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1981. ISBN 0821405705
 +
 
 +
*For a contemporary reader covering also the social sciences, see: Philip Vannini and J.Patrick Williams (eds.), ''Authenticity in Culture, Self and Society,'' Farnham, Ashgate, 2009. ISBN 0754675165
 +
 
 +
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved August 22, 2023.
 +
 
 +
===General philosophy sources===
  
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
 +
 +
[[category:Philosophy and religion]]
 +
[[Category:philosophy]]
  
{{credit|Authenticity_(philosophy)|168418593}}
+
{{credit|Authenticity_(philosophy)|168418593|Philosophy_of_Søren_Kierkegaard|177100088}}

Latest revision as of 19:15, 22 August 2023

Authenticity is a philosophical concept that denotes the genuine, original, true state of human existence. The concept arises from the insights that human beings generally live or exist in an inauthentic way and that the genuine sense of self and its relationship with others (including God and/or other people), have been lost. The authentic life is often described as a life of freedom, joy, meaning, value, and happiness.

Religious traditions generally incorporate such insights into their teachings, which often emphasize the restoration of an authentic self and society. In philosophy, the concept has also been discussed by many thinkers. According to Existentialists, who formally thematized the concept of authenticity, social relationships, cultural values, and norms construct an inauthentic self; the recovery of the authentic self requires a radical reexamination of cultural contexts, habitual lifestyles, and ways of thinking.

General characteristics

If authenticity can only be described in very abstract terms, or as the negative of inauthenticity, what can be said about it directly? All writers generally agree that authenticity is:

  • Something to be pursued as a goal intrinsic to "the good life."
  • Intrinsically difficult, due in part to social pressures to live inauthentically, and in part due to a person's own character.
  • A revelatory state, where one perceives oneself, other people, and sometimes even things, in a radically new way.

One might add that many, though not all, writers have agreed that authenticity also:

  • Requires self-knowledge.
  • Alters radically one's relationships with others (God and/or people).
  • Carries with it its own set of moral obligations.

The notion of authenticity also fits in to utopian ideas, in as much as many believe that a utopia:

  • Requires authenticity among its citizens to exist, or
  • Would remove physical and economic barriers to pursuing authenticity.

Religious perspective

Religious traditions generally contain the concept of authenticity. Based upon the insight that human beings are vulnerable to various temptations, religions offer teachings, practical methodologies, rituals, trainings, institutionalized mechanism, and other ways to allow human beings to recover an authentic self and life. The concept of salvation, for example, is built upon the idea that there is some authentic state of being.

The concept of authenticity can be applied to almost all key concepts in religious teachings. It functions to distinguish religious ideals from secular notions. For example, religious teachings often distinguish genuine happiness, which is built upon spiritual awakening or oneness with the divine or some other spiritual element, from secular happiness built upon material wealth and secular values alone. Genuine joy is also distinguished from hedonistic pleasure in a pejorative sense. Even genuine love is distinguished from a secular notion of love. Authenticity separates and establishes the religious realm or the sacred realm in sharp contrast with the mundane or secular realm. Thus, religious teachings are, in a sense, attempts to present an authentic way of life to the world. Religious teachings challenge people, who would otherwise continue to live as they are, to question the way they live.

Philosophical perspectives

The concept of authenticity has been discussed in diverse ways throughout philosophical history. For example, Socrates's dictums, such as, "Unexamined life is not worth living," or "Know yourself," can be seen as his attempts to lead others to the discovery of the authentic self and way of life. Kierkegaard examined the loss of the genuine self in the mass, in society, and tried to present the process of recovering the authentic self within a theistic context. Other existential thinkers such as Nietzsche, Pascal, Heidegger, Karl Jaspers, and Sartre equally discussed the issue of authenticity and developed various ways to deal with the issue.

The term eigentlich (authentic) in German contains the element of eigen ("one's own"). Authenticity, thus, includes the element of "one's own unique self." Accordingly, recovery of authenticity, at least in German, implies the recovery of one's own unique identity. When existential thinkers speak of authenticity, they often include this element and contrast the unique self against the concept of mass, in which the individual is no more than just a number.

Existential philosophers build the element of authenticity into their own philosophical thought and configure it according to central themes of their works. Accordingly, the way each philosopher deals with authenticity is different and expositions of their views of authenticity are not straightforward. Only a few are introduced below as examples.

Kierkegaard

Kierkegaard criticized the philosophical systems that were brought on by philosophers such as Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel before him and the Danish Hegelians, although Kierkegaard respected the philosophy of Immanuel Kant.[1] He measured himself against the model of philosophy which he found in Socrates, which aims to draw one's attention not to explanatory systems, but rather to the issue of how one exists.

One of Kierkegaard's recurrent themes is the importance of subjectivity, which has to do with the way people relate themselves to (objective) truths. In Concluding Unscientific Postscript to Philosophical Fragments, he argues that "subjectivity is truth" and "truth is subjectivity." What he means by this is that most essentially, truth is not just a matter of discovering objective facts. While objective facts are important, there is a second and more crucial element of truth, which involves how one relates oneself to those matters of fact. Since how one acts is, from the ethical perspective, more important than any matter of fact, truth is to be found in subjectivity rather than objectivity.[2]

Individuality

For Kierkegaard, true individuality is called selfhood. Becoming aware of true self is the true task and endeavor in life—it is an ethical imperative, as well as preparatory to a true religious understanding. Individuals can exist at a level that is less than true selfhood. One can live, for example, simply in terms of pleasures—the immediate satisfaction of desires, propensities, or distractions. In this way, people glide through life without direction or purpose. To have a direction, one must have a purpose that defines for him the meaning of his lives.

In Sickness Unto Death, specifically, Kierkegaard deals with the self as a product of relations. In this sense, a human results from a relation between the Infinite (Noumena, spirit, eternal) and Finite (Phenomena, body, temporal). This does not create a true self, as a human can live without a "self" as he defines it. Instead, the Self or ability for the self to be created from a relation to the Absolute or God (the Self can only be realized through a relation to God) arises as a relation between the relation of the Finite and Infinite relating back to the human. This would be a positive relation.

An individual person, for Kierkegaard, is a particular that no abstract formula or definition can ever capture. Including the individual in "the public" (or "the crowd" or "the herd") or subsuming a human being as simply a member of a species is a reduction of the true meaning of life for individuals. What philosophy or politics try to do is to categorize and pigeonhole individuals by group characteristics instead of individual differences. For Kierkegaard, those differences are what make people who they are.

Kierkegaard's critique of the modern age, therefore, is about the loss of what it means to be an individual. Modern society contributes to this dissolution of what it means to be an individual. Through its production of the false idol of "the public," it diverts attention away from individuals to a mass public that loses itself in abstractions, communal dreams, and fantasies. It is helped in this task by the media and the mass production of products to keep it distracted. Although Kierkegaard attacked "the public," he is supportive of communities.

Sartre and others

Secular and religious notions of authenticity have coexisted for centuries under different guises. For these writers, the conscious self is seen as coming to terms with being in a material world and with encountering external forces and influences which are very different from itself; authenticity is one way in which the self acts and changes in response to these pressures.

Authenticity is often "at the limits" of language; it is described as the negative space around inauthenticity, with reference to examples of inauthentic living. Sartre's novels are perhaps the easiest access to this mode of describing authenticity: they often contain characters and anti-heroes who base their actions on external pressures—the pressure to appear to be a certain kind of person, the pressure to adopt a particular mode of living, the pressure to ignore one's own moral and aesthetic objections in order to have a more comfortable existence. His work also includes characters who do not understand their own reasons for acting, or who ignore crucial facts about their own lives in order to avoid uncomfortable truths; this connects his work with the philosophical tradition.

Sartre is concerned also with the "vertiginous" experience of absolute freedom. Under Sartre's view, this experience, necessary for the state of authenticity, can be sufficiently unpleasant that it leads people to inauthentic ways of living.

These considerations aside, it is the case that authenticity has been associated with various cultural activities. For Sartre, Jazz music, for example, was a representation of freedom; this may have been in part because Jazz was associated with African-American culture, and was thus in opposition to Western culture generally, which Sartre considered hopelessly inauthentic. Theodor Adorno, however, another writer and philosopher concerned with the notion of authenticity, despised Jazz music because he saw it as a false representation that could give the appearance of authenticity but that was as much bound up in concerns with appearance and audience as many other forms of art. Heidegger, in his later life, associated authenticity with non-technological modes of existence, seeing technology as distorting a more "authentic" relationship with the natural world.

Most writers on inauthenticity in the twentieth century considered the predominant cultural norms to be inauthentic; not only because they were seen as forced on people, but also because, in themselves, they required people to behave inauthentically towards their own desires, obscuring true reasons for acting. Advertising, in as much as it attempted to give people a reason for doing something that they did not already possess, was a "textbook" example of how Western culture distorted the individual for external reasons. Race relations are seen as another limit on authenticity, as they demand that the self engage with others on the basis of external attributes. An early example of the connection between inauthenticity and capitalism was made by Karl Marx, whose notion of "alienation" can be linked to the later discourse on the nature of inauthenticity.

Notes

  1. Ronald M. Green, Kierkegaard and Kant: The Hidden Debt (SUNY Press, 1992). ISBN 0791411079
  2. Howard V. and Edna H. Hong, "Subjectivity/Objectivity." Søren Kierkegaard's Journals and Papers.(Indiana University Press, 1975). ISBN 0253182433

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Anton, Corey. Selfhood and Authenticity. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2001. ISBN 0791448991
  • Chen, Xunwu. Being and Authenticity. Value inquiry book series, v. 149. Amsterdam: Rodopi, 2004. ISBN 9042008288
  • Ferrara, Alessandro, Reflective Authenticity: Rethinking the Project of Modernity, London and New York, Routledge, 1998. ISBN 041513062X
  • Golomb, Jacob. In Search of Authenticity From Kierkegaard to Camus. Problems of Modern European Thought. London: Routledge, 1995. ISBN 0415119464
  • Moore, Thomas. Original Self Living with Paradox and Authenticity. New York: HarperCollins, 2000. ISBN 0060195428
  • Nehamas, Alexander. Virtues of Authenticity Essays on Plato and Socrates. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1999. ISBN 0691001774
  • Taylor, Charles. The Ethics of Authenticity. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1992. ISBN 0674268636
  • Trilling, Lionel. Sincerity and Authenticity. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1972. ISBN 0674808606
  • Zimmerman, Michael E. Eclipse of the Self The Development of Heidegger's Concept of Authenticity. Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1981. ISBN 0821405705
  • For a contemporary reader covering also the social sciences, see: Philip Vannini and J.Patrick Williams (eds.), Authenticity in Culture, Self and Society, Farnham, Ashgate, 2009. ISBN 0754675165

External links

All links retrieved August 22, 2023.

General philosophy sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.