Reductio ad absurdum

From New World Encyclopedia
Revision as of 21:10, 30 January 2007 by Keisuke Noda (talk | contribs) (import from wiki)
(diff) ← Older revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Reductio ad absurdum, Latin for "reduction to the absurd", traceable back to the Greek ἡ εις άτοπον απαγωγη (hê eis átopon apagogê), "reduction to the impossible", often used by Aristotle, also known as an apagogical argument, reductio ad impossibile, or proof by contradiction, is a type of logical argument where one assumes a claim for the sake of argument, derives an absurd or ridiculous outcome, and then concludes that the original assumption must have been wrong, as it led to an absurd result. It makes use of the law of non-contradiction - a statement cannot be both true and false. In some cases it may also make use of the law of excluded middle - a statement must be either true or false.

In formal logic, reductio ad absurdum is used when a formal contradiction can be derived from a premise, allowing one to conclude that the premise is false. If a contradiction is derived from a set of premises, this shows that at least one of the premises is false, but other means must be used to determine which one.

Reductio ad absurdum is also often used to describe an argument where a conclusion is derived in the belief that everyone (or at least those being argued against) will accept that it is false or absurd. However, this is a weak form of reductio, as the decision to reject the premise requires that the conclusion is accepted as being absurd. Although a formal contradiction is by definition absurd (unacceptable), a weak reductio ad absurdum argument can be rejected simply by accepting the purportedly absurd conclusion.

There is a fairly common misconception that reductio ad absurdum simply denotes "a silly argument" and is itself a logical fallacy. However, this is not correct; a properly constructed reductio constitutes a correct argument.

Examples

The following dialogue is an example of reductio ad absurdum:

Mother - I don't want you getting a tattoo.
Son - Why not?
Mother - Because tattoos were used in the holocaust.
Son - Okay, I'll never ride a train again, or take a shower, be naked, or speak German.



Another example:

A - All beliefs are of equal validity and cannot be denied.
B - If that's the case, then C is correct in his belief, even though C believes something that is considered to be wrong by most people, such as that the Earth is flat.
A - True.
B - Then some beliefs can be denied.

The following is a trickier reduction, but one which is stronger from the philosophical point of view because it does not rely on A's accepting that C's opinion is wrong:

A - You should respect C's belief, for all beliefs are of equal validity and cannot be denied.
B -
  1. I deny that all beliefs are of equal validity.
  2. According to your statement, this belief of mine (1) is valid, like all other beliefs.
  3. However, your statement also contradicts and invalidates mine, being the exact opposite of it.
  4. 2 and 3 are incompatible, so your statement is logically absurd.

In each case, B has used a reduction to the absurd to argue his or her point. The second example is also a version of the liar paradox.

Another very familiar example:

Mother - Why did you start smoking?
Son - All my friends were doing it.
Mother - You're saying that if all your friends jumped off a cliff, you would do that too?

Here, the mother refutes the son's justification by showing the absurdity of its consequences.

A recent, fairly well-known example of reductio ad absurdum is Bobby Henderson's notion of the Flying Spaghetti Monster, used to parody efforts by creationists and believers in intelligent design to teach such theories in science classes, instead of or in addition to evolution. His argument is that, given the arguments used by creationists and supporters of intelligent design, his lighthearted theory that a flying spaghetti monster created the world has an equally legitimate claim to a place in the science curriculum. This is a good example of the weaker form of reductio noted above, since it does not involve a formal contradiction. Someone could respond by saying that creationism and pastafarianism should indeed both be taught in schools; this position would strike most people as absurd (and this is Henderson's point), but it is, at least, internally consistent.

Attempts to construct a valid reductio ad absurdum are sometimes vulnerable to degenerating into fallacious straw man and/or slippery slope arguments. For example:

A - I don't think the police should arrest teenagers for soft drug possession.
B - So, you are basically arguing the police should not enforce the law and we should live in a society of violent chaos.

In mathematics

Say we wish to disprove proposition p. The procedure is to show that assuming p leads to a logical contradiction. Thus, according to the law of non-contradiction, p must be false.

Say instead we wish to prove proposition p. We can proceed by assuming "not p" (i.e. that p is false), and show that it leads to a logical contradiction. Thus, according to the law of non-contradiction, "not p" must be false, and so, according to the law of the excluded middle, p is true.

In symbols:

To disprove p: one uses the tautology [p ^ (R ^ ~R)] → ~p where R is any proposition and the "^" symbol is taken to mean and. Assuming p, one proves R and ~R, together they imply ~p.

To prove p: one uses the tautology [~p ^ (R ^ ~R)] →p where R is any proposition. Assuming ~p, one proves R and ~R, together they imply p.

For a simple example of the first kind, consider the proposition "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0". In a reductio ad absurdum argument, we would start by assuming the opposite: that there is a smallest rational number, say, r0.

Now let x = r0/2. Then x is a rational number, and it's greater than 0; and x is smaller than r0. (In the above symbolic argument, "x is the smallest rational number" would be R and "r (which is different from x) is the smallest rational number" would be R~".) But that contradicts our initial assumption that r0 was the smallest rational number. So we can conclude that the original proposition must be true - "there is no smallest rational number greater than 0".

It is not uncommon to use this first type of argument with propositions such as the one above, concerning the non-existence of some mathematical object. One assumes that such an object exists, and then proves that this would lead to a contradiction; thus, such an object does not exist. For other examples, see proof that the square root of 2 is not rational and Cantor's diagonal argument.

On the other hand, it is also common to use arguments of the second type concerning the existence of some mathematical object. One assumes that the object doesn't exist, and then proves that this would lead to a contradiction; thus, such an object must exist. Although it is quite freely used in mathematical proofs, not every school of mathematical thought accepts this kind of argument as universally valid. In schools such as intuitionism, the law of the excluded middle is not taken as true. From this way of thinking, there is a very significant difference between proving that something exists by showing that it would be absurd if it did not; and proving that something exists by constructing an actual example of such an object. These schools will still, however, accept arguments of the first kind concerning non-existence. A famous example of the second kind is Brouwer's own proof of his fixed point theorem, which shows that it is impossible for certain fixed points not to exist, without being able to show how to obtain one in the general case.

It is important to note that to form a valid proof, it must be demonstrated that the assumption being made for the sake of argument implies a property that is actually false in the mathematical system being used. The danger here is the logical fallacy of argument from lack of imagination, where it is proven that the assumption implies a property which looks false, but is not really proven to be false. Traditional (but incorrect!) examples of this fallacy include false proofs of Euclid's fifth postulate (a.k.a. the parallel postulate) from the other postulates.

The reason these examples are not really examples of this fallacy is that the notion of proof was different in the 19th century; (Euclidean) geometry was seen as being a 'true' reflection of physical reality, and so deducing a contradiction by concluding something physically implausible (like the angles of a triangle not being 180 degrees) was acceptable. Doubts about the nature of the geometry of the universe led mathematicians such as Bolyai, Gauss, Lobachevsky, Riemann, among others, to question and clarify what actually constituted 'geometry'. Out of these men's work, resulted Non-Euclidean geometry. For a further exposition of these misunderstandings see Morris Kline, Mathematical Thought: from Ancient to Modern Times.

In mathematical logic, the reductio ad absurdum is represented as:

if
then

or

if
then

In the above, p is the proposition we wish to prove or disprove; and S is a set of statements which are given as true - these could be, for example, the axioms of the theory we are working in, or earlier theorems we can build upon. We consider p, or the negation of p, in addition to S; if this leads to a logical contradiction F, then we can conclude that the statements in S lead to the negation of p, or p itself, respectively.

Note that the set-theoretic union, in some contexts closely related to logical disjunction (or), is used here for sets of statements in such a way that it is more related to logical conjunction (and).

In the words of G. H. Hardy (A Mathematician's Apology), "Reductio ad absurdum, which Euclid loved so much, is one of a mathematician's finest weapons. It is a far finer gambit than any chess gambit: a chess player may offer the sacrifice of a pawn or even a piece, but a mathematician offers the game."

See also

  • Reductio ad Hitlerum

bs:Reductio ad absurdum zh-min-nan:Hoán-chèng-hoat cs:Důkaz sporem de:Reductio ad absurdum et:Vastuväiteline tõestus es:Demostración por reducción al absurdo fr:Raisonnement par l'absurde he:הוכחה בדרך השלילה nl:Reductio ad absurdum ja:背理法 no:Reductio ad absurdum pl:Dowód nie wprost pt:Prova por contradição ru:Доказательство от противного sl:Dokaz s protislovjem sr:Свођење на контрадикцију sv:Indirekt bevis tr:Reductio ad absurdum zh:反證法


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.