Carl Gustav Hempel

From New World Encyclopedia

Carl Gustav Hempel (born January 8, 1905, in Oranienburg, Germany; died November 9, 1997, in Princeton, New Jersey) was a philosopher of science and a major figure in 20th-century logical positivism. He is especially well-known for his defense of the Deductive-nomological model of scientific explanation and for his work on the Raven paradox.

Biography

Hempel studied first at the Realgymnasium in Berlin. In 1923 he was admitted to the University of Göttingen, where he studied mathematics with David Hilbert and symbolic logic with Henirich Behmann. He was especially impressed with Hilbert's effort to base mathematics on a solid logical foundation by deriving it from a limited number of axioms; this attempt is known as(Hilbert's Program).

Also in 1923 Hempel moved to the University of Heidelberg, where he studied mathematics, physics, and philosophy. From 1924 he studied at the University of Berlin where he met Hans Reichenbach, who introduced him to the Berlin Circle of philosophers. Hempel attended Reichenbach's courses. He also studied physics with Max Planck and logic with John von Neumann. In 1929 Hempel participated in the first conference on scientific philosophy organized by the logical positivists. He met Rudolf Carnap there and became enthusiastic about Carnap's work; Hempel therefore moved to Vienna and became part of the Vienna Circle, attending courses with Carnap, Schlick, and Waismann. In 1934 he received his doctoral degree from the University of Berlin with a dissertation on probability theory.

The same year he fled the increasingly repressive Germany and emigrated to Belgium with the help of a friend of Reichenbach, Paul Oppenheim. With Oppenheim, Hempel co-authored the book "Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen Logik" on typology and logics in 1936.

In 1937 Hempel emigrated to the US where he accepted a position as Carnap's assistant at the University of Chicago. Subsequently he held positions at New York's City College (1939-1940), Queens College of New York (1940-48) Yale University (1948-1955), and Princeton University where he taught alongside Thomas Kuhn, and stayed until he was given emeritus status in 1964. As an emeritus he spent the years from 1964-1966 at the Hebrew University in Jerusalem and taught at the University of Pittsburgh until 1985.

He never embraced the term "logical positivism" as an accurate description of the Vienna Circle and Berlin Group in which he had participated during the years between the World Wars, preferring to describe those philosophers, and himself, as "logical empiricists."

In 2005 the City of Oranienburg renamed a street to "Carl-Gustav-Hempel-Straße".

Scientific Explanation

Until later in his life, Hempel was best known for producing, with Oppenheim, what is known as the deductive-nomological account of science, an account that made scientific explanation and prediction equivalent. According to this view, a scientific explanation of a fact is a deduction of a statement (called the explanandum) of the fact we wish to explain; the premises of the deduction (the explanans) are scientific laws (whence the term "nomological") plus initial conditions. The explanans must be true for the explanation to be acceptable.

This view — a typical and central view of logical positivism, or logical empiricism as Hempel preferred to call it — reduces a scientific explanation to a logical relationship between statements. The explanandum is a logical consequence of the explanans. The view requires scientific laws, and facts are explained when they are subsumed under laws. This led to questions about the nature and status of scientific laws.

Hempel and Oppenheim held that a fundamental theory is a true statement with quantifiers ("all," "some," "none") and without individual constants ("John," "that bird that has the cut on its beak"). A derived theory is a generalized statement that is a consequence of a fundamental theory. Hempel, and the logical positivists as a group, held the view that a scientific theory deals with general properties, and these properties are expressed by universal statements (e.g., the example that was often used was "All ravens are black"). Statements referring to specific space-time regions or individual entities wer enot allowed. The example often given was Newton's laws: They were supposed to be true for all bodies in any space at any time.

There are, however, scientific laws that are true under limited conditions and that refer to specific entities, such as the Sun or one of its planets. To deal with this, Hempel and Oppenheim distinguished between a fundamental theory, which is universal and has no temporal or other restrictions, and a derived theory that can make reference to individual things with their individual characteristics.

The Hempel-Oppenheim model required that scientific theories be true and not just tools for making predictions. This means that their theory assumed or entailed scientific realism.

Bibliography

Main Works:

  • 1936 Über den Gehalt von Wahrscheinlichkeitsaussagen
  • 1936 Der Typusbegriff im Licht der neuen Logik, with Paul Oppenheim
  • 1942 The Function of General Laws in History
  • 1943 Studies in the Logic of Confirmation
  • 1950 "Problems and Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning," 11 Review International de Philosophy 41, pp. 41 - 63.
  • 1959 The Logic of Functional Analysis
  • 1965 Aspects of Scientific Explanation
  • 1966 Philosophy of Natural Science,
  • 1967 Scientific Explanation
  • 2000 Selected Philosophical Essays
  • 2001 The Philosophy of Carl G. Hempel: Studies in Science, Explanation, and Rationality

See also

  • Raven paradox
  • Hempel's Dilemma

External links


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.