Difference between revisions of "Xenocrates" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m ({{Contracted}})
Line 2: Line 2:
 
{{otheruses}}
 
{{otheruses}}
  
'''Xenocrates''' (''{{polytonic|Ξενοκράτης}}'') of [[Chalcedon]] ([[396 BC|396]][[314 BC]]) was a [[Ancient Greece|Greek]] [[philosopher]] and scholarch or rector of the [[Academy]] from [[339 B.C.E.|339]] to [[314 B.C.E.]].
+
'''Xenocrates''' (''{{polytonic|Ξενοκράτης}}'') of Chalcedon (396 – 314 b.c.e.) was a [[Ancient Greece|Greek]] [[philosophy|philosopher]] and third scholarch or rector of the [[Academy]] from 339 to 314 b.c.e..  His thought is known to us only through the commentaries of [[Aristotle]], [[Proclus]], [[Themistius]] and other Greek philosophers.  He was loyal to the ideas of [[Plato]], and responsible for formulating them in way that influenced later Platonists.  He is credited with organizing the topics of philosophy into [[logic]], [[physics]] and [[ethics]], and with elaborating a more logical and complete [[cosmology]] than other [[Platonism|Platonists]], postulating the generation of number, then soul (as a self-moving number), then all the succeeding intangible and material levels of the universe.
  
==Overview==
+
In his biography of Xenocrates, [[Diogenes Laertius]] recounts several anecdotes to illustrate his humble, consistent and incorruptible character.  He was teacher to a number of important Greek thinkers, including Polemon, the statesman Phocion,  the academic [[Crantor]], [[Crates]], the [[Zeno of Citium|Stoic Zeno]] and [[Epicurus]].   
  
Moving to [[Athens]] in early youth, he became the pupil of [[Aeschines Socraticus]], but presently joined himself to [[Plato]], whom he attended to [[Sicily]] in [[361 B.C.E.|361]]. Upon his master's death, he paid a visit with [[Aristotle]] to [[Hermias]] at [[Atarneus]]. In 339, Xenocrates succeeded [[Speusippus]] in the presidency of the school, defeating his competitors [[Menedemus]] and [[Heraclides Ponticus]] by a few votes. On three occasions he was member of an Athenian legation, once to [[Philip II of Macedon|Philip]], twice to [[Antipater]].
+
== Life ==
  
Xenocrates resented the [[Macedon|Macedonian]] influence then dominant at Athens. Soon after the death of [[Demosthenes]] (fl 322), Xenocrates declined the citizenship offered to him at the instance of [[Phocion]], and, being unable to pay the tax levied upon resident aliens, he was sold, or on the point of being sold, into slavery. He died in [[314 B.C.E.|314]], and was succeeded as scholarch by [[Polemon]], whom he had reclaimed from a life of profligacy. Besides Polemon, the statesman [[Phocion]], [[Chaeron]] (tyrant of [[Pellene]]), the academic [[Crantor]], the [[Zeno of Citium|Stoic Zeno]] and [[Epicurus]] are said to have frequented his lectures.
+
Xenocrates was born in Chalcedon around 396 B.C.E.. Moving to [[Athens]] in early youth, he became the pupil of [[Aeschines Socraticus]], and then a disciple of  [[Plato]], whom he accompanied  to [[Sicily]] in 361 b.c.e..  According to [[Diogenes Laertes]], Xenocrates was lazy by nature, and when comparing him with [[Aristotle]], Plato used to say, "The one requires the spur, and the other the bridle."  Diogenes also relates that  Xenocrates was always solemn and grave, and that Plato often told him, "Xenocrates, sacrifice to the Graces."
  
Xenocrates's earnestness and strength of character won for him universal respect. Stories were remembered in proof of his purity, integrity and benevolence. Wanting in quickness of apprehension and in native grace, he made up for these deficiencies by a conscientious love of truth and an untiring industry. Less original than Speusippus, he adhered more closely to the letter of Platonic doctrine, and is accounted the typical representative of the Old Academy. In his writings, which were numerous, he seems to have covered nearly the whole of the Academic programme; but [[metaphysics]] and ethics were the subjects which principally engaged his thoughts. He is said to have invented, or at least to have emphasized, the division of philosophy into the three parts of physic, dialectic and ethic.
+
After Plato’s death, Xenocrates went with [[Aristotle]] to visit Hermias at Atarneus. In 339, Xenocrates succeeded [[Speusippus]] as president of Plato’s Academy, defeating his rivals Menedemus and Heraclides Ponticus by only a few votes. Xenocrates's earnestness and strength of character won him the respect of the people of Athens. Three times he was sent as a member of an Athenian legation, once to [[Philip II of Macedon|Philip]], and twice to [[Antipater]].  On these occasions he refused to be corrupted by gifts and lavish banquets.  Diogenes Laertes reports several stories about Xenocrates' refusal to keep more wealth then he needed for his living expenses. He also had the habit of meditating in silence for an hour every day.
  
==Ontology==
+
Xenocrates resented the [[Macedon|Macedonian]] influence then dominant in Athens. Soon after the death of [[Demosthenes]] (fl 322 B.C.E.), Xenocrates declined the citizenship offered to him at the instance of Phocion, and, being unable to pay the tax levied upon resident aliens, he was sold as a slave by the city of Athens.  A man named Demetrius Phalereus purchased him and gave him his freedom.
  
In his ontology Xenocrates built upon Plato's foundations; with Plato he postulated ideas or numbers to be the causes of nature's organic products, and derived these ideas or numbers from unity (which is active) and plurality (which is passive). But he put upon this fundamental idea a new interpretation. According to Plato, existence is mind pluralized: mind as a unity, i.e. universal mind, apprehends its own plurality as eternal, immutable, intelligible ideas; and mind as a plurality, i.e. particular mind, perceives its own plurality as transitory, mutable, sensible things. The idea, inasmuch as it is a law of universal mind, which in particular minds produces aggregates of sensations called things, is a "determinant", and as such is styled "quantity" and perhaps "number"; but the ideal numbers are distinct from arithmetical numbers.
+
After twenty-five years as president of the Academy, Xenocrates died in  314 b.c.e. and was succeeded as scholarch by Polemon, whom he had reclaimed from a life of profligacy. Besides Polemon, [[Crates]] the Cynic, the statesman Phocion, Chaeron (tyrant of Pellene), the academic Crantor, the [[Zeno of Citium|Stoic Zeno]] and [[Epicurus]] are said to have frequented his lectures.
  
Xenocrates, however, failing, as it would seem, to grasp the idealism which was the metaphysical foundation of Plato's theory of natural kinds, took for his principles arithmetical unity and plurality, and accordingly identified ideal numbers with arithmetical numbers. In thus reverting to the crudities of certain [[Pythagorean]]s, he laid himself open to the criticisms of Aristotle, who, in his ''Metaphysics'', recognizing amongst contemporary Platonists three principal groups:
+
== Thought and Works ==
  
#those who, like Plato, distinguished mathematical and ideal numbers;
+
[[Diogenes Laertes]] lists seventy works by Xenocrates on a wide variety of topics; none of them have survived even as fragments embedded in other works.  References and responses to his ideas in the writings of other Greek philosophers such as [[Aristotle]], [[Theophrastus]], [[Proclus]] and Asclepius, however, are numerous, and indicate that his thought played an important role in the development of Greek philosophy.  Aristotle wrote several criticisms of Xenocrates without mentioning him by name, but commentators on Aristotle, such as [[Alexander of Aphrodisias]], verify that these passages were directed towards him.  His role seems to have been to clarify and formalize the teachings of [[Plato]] rather than to promote original ideas of his own. 
#those who, like Xenocrates, identified them; and
 
#those who, like Speusippus, postulated mathematical numbers only
 
  
Aristotle has much to say against the Xenocratean interpretation of the theory, and in particular points out that, if the ideas are numbers made up of arithmetical units, they not only cease to be principles, but also become subject to arithmetical operations. Xenocrates's theory of inorganic nature was substantially identical with the theory of the elements which is propounded in the ''[[Timaeus (dialogue)|Timaeus]]'', 53 C seq. Nevertheless, holding that every dimension has a principle of its own, he rejected the derivation of the elemental solids—[[pyramid]], [[octahedron]], [[icosahedron]] and [[cube (geometry)|cube]]—from triangular surfaces, and in so far approximated to [[atomism]]. Moreover, to the tetrad of the [[classical elements]] (fire, air, water, and earth) he added the ether.
+
Xenocrates is said to have invented, or at least to have emphasized, the division of philosophy into [[physics]], [[logic]] and [[ethics]].
  
==Cosmology==
+
=== Ontology ===
  
His [[cosmology]], which is drawn almost entirely from the ''Timaeus'', and, as he intimated, is not to be regarded as a [[cosmogony]], should be studied in connection with his [[psychology]]. [[Soul]] is a self-moving number, derived from the two fundamental principles, unity and plurality, whence it obtains its powers of rest and motion. It is incorporeal, and may exist apart from body. The irrational soul, as well as the rational soul, is immortal. The universe, the heavenly bodies, man, animals, and presumably plants, are each of them endowed with a soul, which is more or less perfect according to the position which it occupies in the descending scale of creation. With this Platonic philosopheme Xenocrates combines the current theology, identifying the universe and the heavenly bodies with the greater gods, and reserving a place between them and mortals for the lesser divinities.
+
Xenocrates held that being originated with the two ultimate principles, the One and the Indefinite Dyad (plurality, the everflowing, or the many) which generated the form-numbers from which arose lines, planes, solids, solids in motion (astronomical bodiesand ultimately perceptible things.  He interpreted the concept of generation as simply a pedagogical device.  Plato had distinguished between ideal (formal) numbers, which were essential concepts or ideals, and the mathematical numbers which are used for arithmetic calculations and measurements in the material world. Xenocrates thought that the formal numbers and mathematical numbers had the same nature, and that therefore it was unnecessary to distinguish between them.  [[Aristotle]] attacked this concept, pointing out that, if forms (ideals) are numbers made up of arithmetical units, they not only cease to be principles, but also become subject to arithmetical operations.  In his ''Metaphysics'', Aristotle distinguishes between three groups of Platonists; those who, like [[Plato]], distinguished between mathematical and ideal numbers; those who, like Xenocrates, identified them; and those who, like [[Speusippus]], postulated mathematical numbers only.
  
==Cognition and ethics==
+
Xenocrates's theory of inorganic nature was substantially identical with the theory of the elements which is propounded in Plato's ''Timaeus'', 53 C seq. Nevertheless, holding that every dimension has a principle of its own, he rejected the derivation of the elemental solids—[[pyramid]], [[octahedron]], [[icosahedron]] and [[cube (geometry)|cube]]—from triangular surfaces, thus suggesting something closer to [[atomism]]. He also added the ether to the tetrad of the classical elements (fire, air, water, and earth). 
  
If the extant authorities are to be trusted, Xenocrates recognized three grades of cognition, each appropriated to a region of its own: knowledge, opinion, and sensation. Their objects, respectively, are supra-celestials or ideas, celestials or stars, and infra-celestials or things. Of Xenocrates's logic we know only that he sided with Plato, rejecting the Aristotelian list of ten categories as a superfluity.
+
According to Proclus, Xenocrates rejected the existence of forms (ideals) for objects manufactured by man (artifacts) and for individual beings.
  
Valuing philosophy chiefly for its influence upon conduct, Xenocrates bestowed especial attention upon ethics. The catalogue of his works shows that he had written largely upon this subject; but the indications of doctrine which have survived are scanty, and may be summed up in a few sentences. Things are goods, ills or neutrals. Goods are of three sorts—mental, bodily, external; but of all goods virtue is incomparably the greatest. Happiness consists in the possession of virtue, and consequently is independent of personal and extraneous advantages. The virtuous man is pure, not in act only, but also in heart. To the attainment of virtue the best help is philosophy; for the philosopher does of his own accord what others do under the compulsion of law. Speculative wisdom and practical wisdom are to be distinguished. Meagre as these statements are, they suffice to show that in ethics, as elsewhere, Xenocrates worked upon Platonic lines.
+
Xenocrates proposed that there were certain lines that were indivisible and therefore primary, and certain primary planes and solids composed of them. Aristotle attributed this concept to Plato, but passages in the works of [[Alexander of Aphrodisias|Alexander]] and several other commentators indicate that Xenocrates was a much stronger proponent of this idea. Several commentators suggested that Xenocrates was speaking of the form (ideal) of such a line rather than its physical or geometric magnitude.  
  
Xenocrates was not in any sense a great thinker. His metaphysic was a travesty rather than a reproduction of that of his master. His ethic had little which was distinctive. But his austere life and commanding personality made him an effective teacher, and his influence, kept alive by his pupils Polemon and Crates, ceased only when [[Arcesilaus]], the founder of the so-called [[Second Academy]], gave a new direction to the studies of the school.
+
In his  ''Metaphysics'', Theophrastus complains that the Platonists and [[Pythagoras|Pythagoreans]] fail to give a complete description of the structure of the universe, but that Xenocrates presents a coherent world order which encompasses perceptibles, mathematicals and the divine. [[Aristotle]] also credited Xenocrates’ explanation of the universe with showing continuity.   
 +
 
 +
=== Cosmology ===
 +
 
 +
His [[cosmology]], which is drawn almost entirely from [[Plato]]’s ''Timaeus'', and, as he intimated, is not to be regarded as a [[cosmogony]], should be studied in connection with his [[psychology]]. [[Soul]] is a self-moving number, derived from the two fundamental principles, the one and the Indefinite Dyad (plurality, the everflowing, or the many), from where it obtains its powers of rest and motion. It is incorporeal, and may exist apart from body. The irrational soul, as well as the rational soul, is immortal. The universe, the heavenly bodies, man, animals, and presumably plants, are each of them endowed with a soul, which is more or less perfect according to the position which it occupies in the descending scale of creation.
 +
 
 +
In a passage from his commentary on Aristotle’s ''De anima'', [[Themistius]] refers to an account from a work by Xenocrates called ''On Nature'', which describes how the soul is composed from the formal numbers 1, 2, 3 and 4. Both Themistius and [[Aristotle]] explain that, since the universe is derivative from those numbers, the soul derived from those same numbers can know about the universe on the principle that like recognizes like.  The soul, a self-moving number, was capable of understanding the universe which was derived from the same number.
 +
 
 +
Xenocrates saw the One  and the Dyad as gods, the One as male and the Dyad as female. He also thought of the heavenly bodies as gods, and identified intermediary beings between man and god, called ''daimones'', who existed in the sublunary world. Plutarch says that Xenocrates associated each type of being with a different type of triangle; gods with equilateral  triangles, daimones with isosceles triangles (intermediate between equilateral and scalene), and men with scalene triangles.  Plutarch also said that according to Xenocrates, there were good and bad types of ''daimones''.
 +
 
 +
=== Cognition and Ethics ===
 +
 
 +
Xenocrates recognized three grades of [[cognition]], each appropriated to a region of its own: knowledge, opinion, and sensation. Their objects, respectively, are supra-celestials or ideas, celestials or stars, and infra-celestials or things.
 +
 
 +
Xenocrates valued philosophy chiefly for its influence upon conduct.  [[Diogenes Laertes]]’ catalogue of his works shows that he had written largely on ethics; but few traces of his doctrine have survived.  Things are goods, ills or neutrals. Goods are of three types—mental, bodily, or external; of all goods, virtue is incomparably the greatest. Happiness consists in the possession of virtue, and consequently is independent of personal and extraneous advantages. The virtuous man is pure, not only in his actions, but also in heart. Philosophy offers the greatest assistance to the attainment of virtue; for the philosopher does of his own accord what others do under the compulsion of law. There is a distinction between speculative wisdom and practical wisdom.
 +
 
 +
Of Xenocrates' logic we know only that he rejected the Aristotelian list of ten categories as too long, and sided with Plato’s distinction between things that are “by virtue of themselves” and things that exist “relative to something.”  He associated things which exist in themselves with the One and things that exist relative to something with the many (plurality).
  
 
== References ==
 
== References ==
 +
=== Commentaries on Xenocrates ===
  
* [[D. Van de Wynpersse]], ''De Xenocrate Chalcedonio'' (Leiden, 1822)
+
*Babbitt, F.C., ''Plutarch's Moralia'', vol. v: 351C-438E. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd., 1936, rpr. 1969.
* [[C. A. Brandis]], ''Geschichte die griechisch-romischen Philosophie'' (Berlin, 1853), ii. 2, I
+
*Bury, R.G., ''Sextus Empiricus'', 4 vols., vol ii: Against the Logicians. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd.,1935.
* [[Eduard Zeller]], ''Philosophie die Griechen'' (Leipzig, 1875), ii. I
+
*Dooley, W.E., ''Alexander of Aphrodisias on Aristotle's Metaphysics'' 1. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1989.
* [[F. W. A. Mullach]], ''Fragmenta Philosophorum Graecorum'' (Paris, 1881), iii.
+
*Morrow, Glenn R., & John Dillon, ''Proclus' Commentary on Plato's Parmenides''. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987.
* [[R. Heinze]], ''Xenocrates'' (1892)
+
*Pines, S., “''A New Fragment of Xenocrates and Its Implications''”, Transactions of the American Philological Association 51 (1961), 3-34.  
 +
*Ross, W.D., & F.H. Fobes, ''Theophrastus: Metaphysics''. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1929; rpr. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1967. Greek with facing English translation.
 +
*Todd, Robert B., ''Themistius on Aristotle's On the Soul''. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1996.
 +
=== Works About Xenocrates ===
 +
*Cherniss, Harold, ''The Riddle of the Early Academy.'' Berkeley & Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1945; rpr. New York: Russell & Russell, 1962.
 +
*Dillon, John, ''The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy (347-274 B.C.E.''). Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.  
 +
*Furley, David, ''Two Studies in the Greek Atomists''. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1967.  
 +
*Heinze, Richard, ''Xenocrates.'' Stuttgart: Teubner, 1892; rpr. Hildesheim: G. Olms, 1965.
 +
*Hicks, R.D., ''Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers'', 2 vols. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd., 1925. 
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/xenocrates/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry]
+
*[http://classicpersuasion.org/pw/diogenes/dlxenocrates.htm  Lives of Eminent Philsophers- Diogenes Laertius]
 
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/xenocrates/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry]
 
 
 
{{1911}}
 
{{1911}}
  
[[Category:396 B.C.E. births]]
 
[[Category:314 B.C.E. deaths]]
 
 
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers]]
 
[[Category:Ancient Greek philosophers]]
 
[[Category:Ancient Athenians]]
 
[[Category:Ancient Athenians]]

Revision as of 02:48, 20 October 2006

For other uses, see Xenocrates (disambiguation).

Xenocrates (Ξενοκράτης) of Chalcedon (396 – 314 B.C.E.) was a Greek philosopher and third scholarch or rector of the Academy from 339 to 314 b.c.e.. His thought is known to us only through the commentaries of Aristotle, Proclus, Themistius and other Greek philosophers. He was loyal to the ideas of Plato, and responsible for formulating them in way that influenced later Platonists. He is credited with organizing the topics of philosophy into logic, physics and ethics, and with elaborating a more logical and complete cosmology than other Platonists, postulating the generation of number, then soul (as a self-moving number), then all the succeeding intangible and material levels of the universe.

In his biography of Xenocrates, Diogenes Laertius recounts several anecdotes to illustrate his humble, consistent and incorruptible character. He was teacher to a number of important Greek thinkers, including Polemon, the statesman Phocion, the academic Crantor, Crates, the Stoic Zeno and Epicurus.

Life

Xenocrates was born in Chalcedon around 396 b.c.e.. Moving to Athens in early youth, he became the pupil of Aeschines Socraticus, and then a disciple of Plato, whom he accompanied to Sicily in 361 b.c.e.. According to Diogenes Laertes, Xenocrates was lazy by nature, and when comparing him with Aristotle, Plato used to say, "The one requires the spur, and the other the bridle." Diogenes also relates that Xenocrates was always solemn and grave, and that Plato often told him, "Xenocrates, sacrifice to the Graces."

After Plato’s death, Xenocrates went with Aristotle to visit Hermias at Atarneus. In 339, Xenocrates succeeded Speusippus as president of Plato’s Academy, defeating his rivals Menedemus and Heraclides Ponticus by only a few votes. Xenocrates's earnestness and strength of character won him the respect of the people of Athens. Three times he was sent as a member of an Athenian legation, once to Philip, and twice to Antipater. On these occasions he refused to be corrupted by gifts and lavish banquets. Diogenes Laertes reports several stories about Xenocrates' refusal to keep more wealth then he needed for his living expenses. He also had the habit of meditating in silence for an hour every day.

Xenocrates resented the Macedonian influence then dominant in Athens. Soon after the death of Demosthenes (fl 322 B.C.E.), Xenocrates declined the citizenship offered to him at the instance of Phocion, and, being unable to pay the tax levied upon resident aliens, he was sold as a slave by the city of Athens. A man named Demetrius Phalereus purchased him and gave him his freedom.

After twenty-five years as president of the Academy, Xenocrates died in 314 B.C.E. and was succeeded as scholarch by Polemon, whom he had reclaimed from a life of profligacy. Besides Polemon, Crates the Cynic, the statesman Phocion, Chaeron (tyrant of Pellene), the academic Crantor, the Stoic Zeno and Epicurus are said to have frequented his lectures.

Thought and Works

Diogenes Laertes lists seventy works by Xenocrates on a wide variety of topics; none of them have survived even as fragments embedded in other works. References and responses to his ideas in the writings of other Greek philosophers such as Aristotle, Theophrastus, Proclus and Asclepius, however, are numerous, and indicate that his thought played an important role in the development of Greek philosophy. Aristotle wrote several criticisms of Xenocrates without mentioning him by name, but commentators on Aristotle, such as Alexander of Aphrodisias, verify that these passages were directed towards him. His role seems to have been to clarify and formalize the teachings of Plato rather than to promote original ideas of his own.

Xenocrates is said to have invented, or at least to have emphasized, the division of philosophy into physics, logic and ethics.

Ontology

Xenocrates held that being originated with the two ultimate principles, the One and the Indefinite Dyad (plurality, the everflowing, or the many) which generated the form-numbers from which arose lines, planes, solids, solids in motion (astronomical bodies) and ultimately perceptible things. He interpreted the concept of generation as simply a pedagogical device. Plato had distinguished between ideal (formal) numbers, which were essential concepts or ideals, and the mathematical numbers which are used for arithmetic calculations and measurements in the material world. Xenocrates thought that the formal numbers and mathematical numbers had the same nature, and that therefore it was unnecessary to distinguish between them. Aristotle attacked this concept, pointing out that, if forms (ideals) are numbers made up of arithmetical units, they not only cease to be principles, but also become subject to arithmetical operations. In his Metaphysics, Aristotle distinguishes between three groups of Platonists; those who, like Plato, distinguished between mathematical and ideal numbers; those who, like Xenocrates, identified them; and those who, like Speusippus, postulated mathematical numbers only.

Xenocrates's theory of inorganic nature was substantially identical with the theory of the elements which is propounded in Plato's Timaeus, 53 C seq. Nevertheless, holding that every dimension has a principle of its own, he rejected the derivation of the elemental solids—pyramid, octahedron, icosahedron and cube—from triangular surfaces, thus suggesting something closer to atomism. He also added the ether to the tetrad of the classical elements (fire, air, water, and earth).

According to Proclus, Xenocrates rejected the existence of forms (ideals) for objects manufactured by man (artifacts) and for individual beings.

Xenocrates proposed that there were certain lines that were indivisible and therefore primary, and certain primary planes and solids composed of them. Aristotle attributed this concept to Plato, but passages in the works of Alexander and several other commentators indicate that Xenocrates was a much stronger proponent of this idea. Several commentators suggested that Xenocrates was speaking of the form (ideal) of such a line rather than its physical or geometric magnitude.

In his Metaphysics, Theophrastus complains that the Platonists and Pythagoreans fail to give a complete description of the structure of the universe, but that Xenocrates presents a coherent world order which encompasses perceptibles, mathematicals and the divine. Aristotle also credited Xenocrates’ explanation of the universe with showing continuity.

Cosmology

His cosmology, which is drawn almost entirely from Plato’s Timaeus, and, as he intimated, is not to be regarded as a cosmogony, should be studied in connection with his psychology. Soul is a self-moving number, derived from the two fundamental principles, the one and the Indefinite Dyad (plurality, the everflowing, or the many), from where it obtains its powers of rest and motion. It is incorporeal, and may exist apart from body. The irrational soul, as well as the rational soul, is immortal. The universe, the heavenly bodies, man, animals, and presumably plants, are each of them endowed with a soul, which is more or less perfect according to the position which it occupies in the descending scale of creation.

In a passage from his commentary on Aristotle’s De anima, Themistius refers to an account from a work by Xenocrates called On Nature, which describes how the soul is composed from the formal numbers 1, 2, 3 and 4. Both Themistius and Aristotle explain that, since the universe is derivative from those numbers, the soul derived from those same numbers can know about the universe on the principle that like recognizes like. The soul, a self-moving number, was capable of understanding the universe which was derived from the same number.

Xenocrates saw the One and the Dyad as gods, the One as male and the Dyad as female. He also thought of the heavenly bodies as gods, and identified intermediary beings between man and god, called daimones, who existed in the sublunary world. Plutarch says that Xenocrates associated each type of being with a different type of triangle; gods with equilateral triangles, daimones with isosceles triangles (intermediate between equilateral and scalene), and men with scalene triangles. Plutarch also said that according to Xenocrates, there were good and bad types of daimones.

Cognition and Ethics

Xenocrates recognized three grades of cognition, each appropriated to a region of its own: knowledge, opinion, and sensation. Their objects, respectively, are supra-celestials or ideas, celestials or stars, and infra-celestials or things.

Xenocrates valued philosophy chiefly for its influence upon conduct. Diogenes Laertes’ catalogue of his works shows that he had written largely on ethics; but few traces of his doctrine have survived. Things are goods, ills or neutrals. Goods are of three types—mental, bodily, or external; of all goods, virtue is incomparably the greatest. Happiness consists in the possession of virtue, and consequently is independent of personal and extraneous advantages. The virtuous man is pure, not only in his actions, but also in heart. Philosophy offers the greatest assistance to the attainment of virtue; for the philosopher does of his own accord what others do under the compulsion of law. There is a distinction between speculative wisdom and practical wisdom.

Of Xenocrates' logic we know only that he rejected the Aristotelian list of ten categories as too long, and sided with Plato’s distinction between things that are “by virtue of themselves” and things that exist “relative to something.” He associated things which exist in themselves with the One and things that exist relative to something with the many (plurality).

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

Commentaries on Xenocrates

  • Babbitt, F.C., Plutarch's Moralia, vol. v: 351C-438E. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd., 1936, rpr. 1969.
  • Bury, R.G., Sextus Empiricus, 4 vols., vol ii: Against the Logicians. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd.,1935.
  • Dooley, W.E., Alexander of Aphrodisias on Aristotle's Metaphysics 1. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1989.
  • Morrow, Glenn R., & John Dillon, Proclus' Commentary on Plato's Parmenides. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987.
  • Pines, S., “A New Fragment of Xenocrates and Its Implications”, Transactions of the American Philological Association 51 (1961), 3-34.
  • Ross, W.D., & F.H. Fobes, Theophrastus: Metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1929; rpr. Hildesheim: Georg Olms, 1967. Greek with facing English translation.
  • Todd, Robert B., Themistius on Aristotle's On the Soul. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1996.

Works About Xenocrates

  • Cherniss, Harold, The Riddle of the Early Academy. Berkeley & Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1945; rpr. New York: Russell & Russell, 1962.
  • Dillon, John, The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy (347-274 B.C.E.). Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.
  • Furley, David, Two Studies in the Greek Atomists. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1967.
  • Heinze, Richard, Xenocrates. Stuttgart: Teubner, 1892; rpr. Hildesheim: G. Olms, 1965.
  • Hicks, R.D., Diogenes Laertius: Lives of Eminent Philosophers, 2 vols. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press; London: William Heinemann Ltd., 1925.

External links

This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain. da:Xenokrates de:Xenokrates es:Jenócrates et:Xenokrates fr:Xénocrate ja:クセノクラテス sk:Xenokrates sr:Ксенократ fi:Ksenokrates


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.