Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich

From New World Encyclopedia
(import from wiki)
 
 
(26 intermediate revisions by 6 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi''' ([[25 January]], [[1743]] - [[10 March]], [[1819]]), was a [[Germany|German]] [[philosopher]] who made his mark on philosophy by coining the term [[nihilism]] and promoting it as the prime fault of [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] thought and [[Kant]]ianism. Instead of [[speculative reason]], he advocated [[faith]] (or "belief" aka ''Glaube'') and [[revelation]] (though he differed from the religious meaning in that he took this to be rational).  
+
{{Copyedited}}{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}
 
+
{{epname|Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich}}
On this basis he might be seen as the great-grandfather to present-day writers who criticize philosophy as relativistic and dangerous for religious faith.  
+
'''Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi''' (January 25, 1743 – March 10, 1819) was a [[Germany|German]] philosopher who made his mark on [[philosophy]] by coining the term [[nihilism]] and promoting it as the prime fault of [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] thought and [[Kant]]ianism. His correspondence with [[Moses Mendelssohn]] regarding the philosophy of [[Baruch Spinoza]] were published and widely known as the "pantheism dispute," and it expressed sharply and clearly Jacobi's strenuous objection to rationalist orientaion in philosophy. Instead of speculative [[reason]] and a systematic philosophy like that of Spinoza, he advocated [[faith]] (or "belief"; German: ''Glaube''), [[Feeling|feelings]], and [[revelation]] as the keystones of reason. Spinoza received the attention of [[Johann Gottlieb Fichte|Fichte]], [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]], [[Friedrich_Wilhelm_Joseph_von_Schelling|Schelling]], and others as a result of Jacobi's criticism. Jacobi was critical to the intellectualism of the Enlightenment, stressed the importance of belief and emotion of individuals, and influenced German [[Romanticism]].
 
+
{{toc}}
 
==Biography==
 
==Biography==
He was born at [[Düsseldorf]], the second son of a wealthy sugar merchant, and was educated for a commercial career. Of a retiring, meditative disposition, Jacobi associated himself at [[Geneva]] mainly with the literary and scientific circle of which the most prominent member was Le Sage. He studied closely the works of [[Charles Bonnet]], and the political ideas of [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]] and [[Voltaire]]. In 1763 he was recalled to Düsseldorf, and in the following year he married and took over the management of his father's business.
+
Jacobi was born at Düsseldorf, the second son of a wealthy sugar merchant, and was educated for a commercial career. Of a retiring, meditative disposition, Jacobi associated himself at [[Geneva]] mainly with the literary and scientific circle of which the most prominent member was Le Sage. He studied closely the works of Charles Bonnet, and the political ideas of [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]] and [[Voltaire]]. In 1763 he was recalled to Düsseldorf, and in the following year he married and took over the management of his father's business.
  
After a short time, he gave up his commercial career, and in [[1770]] became a member of the council for the duchies of Jülich and Berg, in which capacity he distinguished himself by his ability in financial affairs, and his zeal in social reform. Jacobi kept up his interest in literary and philosophic matters by an extensive correspondence, and his mansion at Pempelfort, near Düsseldorf, was the centre of a distinguished literary circle. With [[Christoph Martin Wieland]] he helped to found a new literary journal, ''Der Teutsche Mercur'', in which some of his earliest writings, mainly on practical or economic subjects, were published.
+
After a short time, he gave up his commercial career, and in 1770 became a member of the council for the duchies of Jülich and Berg, in which capacity he distinguished himself by his ability in financial affairs and his zeal for social reform. Jacobi kept up his interest in literary and philosophic matters by an extensive correspondence, and his mansion at Pempelfort, near Düsseldorf, was the center of a distinguished literary circle. With Christoph Martin Wieland, he helped to found a new literary journal, ''Der Teutsche Mercur'', in which some of his earliest writings, mainly on practical or economic subjects, were published.
  
Here too appeared in part the first of his philosophic works, ''Edward Allwill's Briefsammlung'' (1776), a combination of romance and speculation. This was followed in 1779 by ''Woldemar'', a philosophic novel, of very imperfect structure, but full of genial ideas, and giving the most complete picture of Jacobi's method of philosophizing.  
+
It was in the journal that the first of his philosophic works appeared in part, ''Edward Allwill's Briefsammlung'' (1776), a combination of romance and speculation. This was followed in 1779 by ''Woldemar'', a philosophic novel of very imperfect structure, but full of genial ideas, and gives the most complete picture of Jacobi's method of philosophizing.  
  
In 1779, he visited [[Munich]] as member of the privy council; but, after a short stay there, differences with his colleagues and with the authorities of [[Bavaria]] drove him back to Pempelfort. A few unimportant tracts on questions of theoretical politics were followed in 1785 by the work which first brought Jacobi into prominence as a philosopher.
+
In 1779, he visited [[Munich]] as member of the Privy Council; but, after a short stay there, differences with his colleagues and with the authorities of Bavaria drove him back to Pempelfort. A few unimportant tracts on questions of theoretical politics were followed in 1785 by the work which first brought Jacobi into prominence as a philosopher.
  
===Pantheism Controversy===
+
===Later life===
A conversation which he had held with [[Gotthold Lessing]] in 1780, in which Lessing avowed that he knew no philosophy, in the true sense of that word, save Spinozism, led him to a protracted study of [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]]'s works. The ''Briefe uber die Lehre Spinozas'' (1785; 2nd ed., much enlarged and with important Appendices, 1789) expressed sharply and clearly Jacobi's strenuous objection to a dogmatic system in philosophy, and drew upon him the vigorous enmity of the Berlin clique, led by [[Moses Mendelssohn]].
+
The outbreak of the war with the French Republic induced Jacobi in 1793 to leave Düsseldorf, and for nearly ten years he lived in Holstein. There he became intimately acquainted with Karl Leonhard Reinhold (in whose Beitrage his important work, ''Uber das Unternehmen des Kriticismus, die Vernunft zu Verstande zu bringen'', was first published), and with Matthias Claudius, the editor of the ''Wandsbecker Bote''.  
  
Jacobi was ridiculed for trying to reintroduce into philosophy the antiquated notion of unreasoning belief, was denounced as an enemy of reason, as a pietist, and as a [[Society of Jesus|Jesuit]] in disguise, and was especially attacked for his use of the ambiguous term "belief". His next important work, ''David Hume Über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus'' (1787), was an attempt to show not only that the term ''Glaube'' had been used by the most eminent writers to denote what he had employed it for in the ''Letters on Spinoza'', but that the nature of the cognition of facts as opposed to the construction of inferences could not be otherwise expressed. In this writing, and especially in the Appendix, Jacobi came into contact with the critical philosophy, and subjected the Kantian view of knowledge to searching examination.
+
During the same period the excitement caused by the accusation of [[atheism]] brought against [[Johann Gottlieb Fichte|Gottlieb Fichte]] at Jena led to the publication of Jacobi's ''Letter to Fichte'' (1799), in which he made more precise the relation of his own philosophic principles to [[theology]].
  
===Later life===
+
Soon after his return to Germany, Jacobi received a call to Munich in connection with the new academy of sciences recently founded there. The loss of a considerable portion of his fortune induced him to accept this offer; he settled in Munich in 1804, and in 1807 became president of the academy.  
The outbreak of the war with the French republic induced Jacobi in 1793 to leave [[Düsseldorf]], and for nearly ten years he lived in Holstein. There he became intimately acquainted with [[Karl Leonhard Reinhold]] (in whose Beitrage his important work, ''Uber das Unternehmen des Kriticismus, die Vernunft zu Verstande zu bringen'', was first published), and with [[Matthias Claudius]], the editor of the ''Wandsbecker Bote''.  
 
  
During the same period the excitement caused by the accusation of [[atheism]] brought against [[Gottlieb Fichte]] at [[university of Jena|Jena]] led to the publication of Jacobi's ''Letter to Fichte'' (1799), in which he made more precise the relation of his own philosophic principles to [[theology]].
+
In 1811 his last philosophic work appeared, directed against [[Friedrich_Wilhelm_Joseph_von_Schelling|Schelling]] especially ''(Von den göttlichen Dingen und ihrer Offenbarung)''; the first part of which, a review of the ''Wandsbecker Bote,'' had been written in 1798. A bitter reply from Schelling was left without answer by Jacobi, but gave rise to an animated controversy in which Jakob Friedrich Fries and Franz Xaver von Baader took prominent part.  
  
Soon after his return to Germany, Jacobi received a call to Munich in connection with the new academy of sciences just founded there. The loss of a considerable portion of his fortune induced him to accept this offer; he settled in Munich in 1804, and in 1807 became president of the academy.  
+
In 1812 Jacobi retired from the office of president, and began to prepare a collected edition of his works. He died before this was completed. The edition of his writings was continued by his friend F. Koppen, and was completed in 1825. The works fill six volumes, of which the fourth is in three parts. To the second is prefixed an introduction by Jacobi, which is at the same time an introduction to his philosophy. The fourth volume has also an important preface.
  
In 1811 appeared his last philosophic work, directed against [[Friedrich Schelling]] specially (''Von den göttlichen Dingen und ihrer Offenbarung''), the first part of which, a review of the ''Wandsbecker Bote,'' had been written in 1798. A bitter reply from Schelling was left without answer by Jacobi, but gave rise to an animated controversy in which [[Jakob Friedrich Fries|Fries]] and [[Franz Xaver von Baader|Baader]] took prominent part.  
+
==Philosophy==
 +
A conversation which Jacobi held with [[Gotthold Ephraim Lessing|Gotthold Lessing]] in 1780 led him to a protracted study of [[Baruch Spinoza|Spinoza]]'s works. What followed was a correspondence with [[Moses Mendelssohn]], published as the ''Briefe uber die Lehre Spinozas'' (1785; 2nd ed., much enlarged and with important appendices, 1789) expressed sharply and clearly Jacobi's strenuous objection to a rationalist orientation and systematic construction of philosophy, and drew upon him the vigorous enmity of the Berlin clique, led by Mendelssohn. Jacobi and Mendelssohn disputed over the interpretation of Spinoza, and this dispute was known as "[[Pantheism]] Dispute." Through this dispute, Spinoza's philosophy was recognized not simply as [[atheism]] but as pantheism, and Spinoza's vitalist view of nature came to be known to others, which influenced the formation of German [[Romanticism]].  
  
In 1812 Jacobi retired from the office of president, and began to prepare a collected edition of his works. He died before this was completed. The edition of his writings was continued by his friend F Koppen, and was completed in 1825. The works fill six volumes, of which the fourth is in three parts. To the second is prefixed an introduction by Jacobi, which is at the same time an introduction to his philosophy. The fourth volume has also an important preface.
+
Jacobi addressed a number of criticisms to major thinkers including Fichte, Schelling, and Kant for their neglect of "belief" and "emotion" as the basis of philosophy. Jacobi, however, was also ridiculed for trying to reintroduce the irrational elements such as belief and emotion into philosophy and was denounced as an enemy of reason, as a pietist, and as a [[Jesuit]] in disguise. He was also attacked for his use of the ambiguous term "belief."
  
==Teachings==
+
Jacobi’s next important work, ''David Hume Über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus'' (1787), was an attempt to show not only that the term ''Glaube'' (faith) had been used by the most eminent writers to denote what he had employed it for in the ''Letters on Spinoza'', but that the nature of the cognition. In this writing, and especially in the appendix, Jacobi came into contact with the critical philosophy, and criticized [[Immanuel Kant|Kantian]] view of knowledge.
Jacobi's philosophy is essentially unsystematic. A fundamental view which underlies all his thinking is brought to bear in succession upon those systematic doctrines which appear to stand most sharply in contradiction to it, and any positive philosophic results are given only occasionally. The leading idea of the whole is that of the complete separation between understanding and apprehension of real fact. For Jacobi understanding, or the logical faculty, is purely formal or elaborative, and its results never transcend the given material supplied to it. From the basis of immediate experience or perception thought proceeds by comparison and abstraction, establishing connexions among facts, but remaining in its nature mediate and finite.  
 
  
The principle of reason and consequent, the necessity of thinking each given fact of perception as conditioned, impels understanding towards an endless series of identical propositions, the records of successive comparisons and abstractions. The province of the understanding is therefore strictly the region of the conditioned; to it the world must present itself as a [[Mechanism (philosophy)|mechanism]]. If, then, there is objective truth at all, the existence of real facts must be made known to us otherwise than through the logical faculty of thought; and, as the regress from conclusion to premises must depend upon something not itself capable of logical grounding, mediate thought implies the consciousness of immediate truth.  
+
As Jacobi starts with the doctrine that thought is partial and limited, applicable only to connect facts but incapable of explaining the aspect of their existence, it is evident that for him, any demonstrative system of metaphysic which should attempt to subject all existence to the principle of logical ground must be repulsive. Jacobi argued that [[human being|human]] cognitive capacity was limited and incapable of grasping God; it was belief that allowed humans to recognize God.  
  
Philosophy therefore must resign the hopeless ideal of a systematic (i.e. intelligible) explanation of things, and must content itself with the examination of the facts of consciousness. It is a mere prejudice of philosophic thinkers, a prejudice which has descended from [[Aristotle]], that mediate or demonstrated cognition is superior in cogency and value to the immediate perception of truths or facts.
+
Now, in modern philosophy, the first and greatest demonstrative system of metaphysic is that of Spinoza, and it lies in the nature of things that upon Spinoza's system Jacobi should first direct his criticism. Some major points of his examination are as follows (''Werke'', i. 216-223):
 +
*[[Baruch Spinoza|Spinozism]] is [[atheism]]
 +
*the philosophy of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]] and [[Christian Wolff|Wolff]] is not less [[fatalism|fatalistic]] than that of Spinoza
 +
*every demonstrative method ends in [[fatalism]] ([[nihilism]])
 +
*we can demonstrate only similarities (agreements, truths conditionally necessary), proceeding always in identical propositions; every proof presupposes something already proved, the principle of which is immediately given (''Offenbarung'', [[revelation]], is the term here employed by Jacobi to denote the peculiar character of an immediate, unproved truth)
 +
*the keystone ''(Element)'' of all human knowledge and activity is "belief" (''Glaube,'' or "[[faith]]")
 +
*Motive of moral action is not the rational understanding of the moral laws as Kant claimed, but the emotional feeling which precedes reason.  
  
As Jacobi starts with the doctrine that thought is partial and limited, applicable only to connect facts, but incapable of explaining their existence, it is evident that for him any demonstrative system of metaphysic which should attempt to subject all existence to the principle of logical ground must be repulsive. Now in modern philosophy the first and greatest demonstrative system of metaphysic is that of Spinoza, and it lay in the nature of things that upon Spinoza's system Jacobi should first direct his criticism. A summary of the results of his examination is thus presented (''Werke'', i. 216-223):
+
Jacobi attacked the humanistic values of the Enlightenment and their emphasis on [[rationalism]]. He did not completely deny the function of [[reason]]; rather, he criticized the creation of a systematic philosophy in which the principles of reason and consequent have obligated philosophers to shape their concept according to their path of logic. Thus, he characterized "Glaube" as the key element of human knowledge and took this to be the keystone of reason.
#[[Spinozism]] is [[atheism]];
 
#the Kabbalistic philosophy, in so far as it is philosophy, is nothing but undeveloped or confused Spinozism;
 
#the philosophy of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]] and [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Wolff]] is not less [[fatalism|fatalistic]] than that of Spinoza, and carries a resolute thinker to the very principles of Spinoza;
 
#every demonstrative method ends in [[fatalism]] ([[nihilism]]);
 
#we can demonstrate only similarities (agreements, truths conditionally necessary), proceeding always in identical propositions; every proof presupposes something already proved, the principle of which is immediately given (''Offenbarung'', [[revelation]], is the term here employed by Jacobi, as by many later writers, e.g. [[Rudolf Hermann Lotze|Lotze]], to denote the peculiar character of an immediate, unproved truth);
 
#the keystone (''Element'') of all human knowledge and activity is belief (''Glaube,'' or "[[faith]]"). Of these propositions only the first and fourth require further notice.
 
  
Jacobi, accepting the law of reason and consequent as the fundamental rule of demonstrative reasoning, and as the rule explicitly followed by Spinoza, points out that, if we proceed by applying this principle so as to recede from particular and qualified facts to the more general and abstract conditions, we land ourselves, not in the notion of an active, intelligent creator of the system of things, but in the notion of an all-comprehensive, indeterminate Nature, devoid of will or intelligence. Our unconditioned is either a pure abstraction, or else the impossible notion of a completed system of conditions. In either case the result is [[atheism]], and this result is necessary if the demonstrative method, the method of understanding, is regarded as the only possible means of knowledge.  
+
==References==
 +
* Jacobi, F. H. ''David Hume Ueber Den Glauben, Oder Idealismus Und Realismus (“The Philosophy of David Hume”)''. Taylor & Francis, 1982. ISBN 0824054091
 +
* di Giovanni, G. (ed. and trans.). 1994. ''The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel 'Allwill'''. Kingston, O.N. and Montreal, PQ: McGill-Queen University Press.
 +
*Wilde, N. 1894. ''Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi: A Study of the Origin of German Realism''. Columbia College. ASIN B00085BU4W
 +
*Rehder, H. 1965. ''Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi and German Thought During the Eighteenth Century''. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. ASIN B0007HY43K
  
Moreover, the same method inevitably lands in [[fatalism]]/[[nihilism]]. For, if the action of the human will is to be made intelligible to understanding, it must be thought as a conditioned phenomenon, having its sufficient ground in preceding circumstances, and, in ultimate abstraction, as the outflow from nature which is the sum of conditions. But this is the fatalist conception, and any philosophy which accepts the law of reason and consequent as the essence of understanding is fatalistic/nihilistic. Thus for the scientific understanding there can be no [[God]] and no [[liberty]].
+
{{1911}}
  
It is impossible that there should be a God, for if so he would of necessity be finite. But a finite God, a God that is known, is no God. It is impossible that there should be liberty, for if so the mechanical order of phenomena, by means of which they are comprehensible, would be disturbed, and we should have an unintelligible world, coupled with the requirement that it shall be understood. Cognition, then, in the strict sense, occupies the middle place between sense perception, which is belief in matters of sense, and reason, which is belief in supersensuous fact
+
==External links==
 +
All links retrieved April 11, 2024.
  
==References==
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/friedrich-jacobi/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi]
*{{1911}}
 
  
[[Category:1743 births|Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich]]
+
===General Philosophy Sources===
[[Category:1819 deaths|Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich]]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
[[Category:German philosophers|Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich]]
+
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
[[Category:German-language philosophers|Jacobi, Friedrich Heinrich]]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
  
==External link==
+
[[Category:Philosophers]]
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/friedrich-jacobi/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi]
 
  
[[de:Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi]]
 
[[fr:Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi]]
 
[[ka:იაკობი, ფრიდრიხ ჰაინრიხ]]
 
[[ja:フリードリヒ・ハインリヒ・ヤコービ]]
 
[[no:Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi]]
 
[[pt:Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi]]
 
[[ru:Якоби, Фридрих Генрих]]
 
  
 
{{credit|66543700}}
 
{{credit|66543700}}

Latest revision as of 11:04, 11 April 2024

Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi (January 25, 1743 – March 10, 1819) was a German philosopher who made his mark on philosophy by coining the term nihilism and promoting it as the prime fault of Enlightenment thought and Kantianism. His correspondence with Moses Mendelssohn regarding the philosophy of Baruch Spinoza were published and widely known as the "pantheism dispute," and it expressed sharply and clearly Jacobi's strenuous objection to rationalist orientaion in philosophy. Instead of speculative reason and a systematic philosophy like that of Spinoza, he advocated faith (or "belief"; German: Glaube), feelings, and revelation as the keystones of reason. Spinoza received the attention of Fichte, Hegel, Schelling, and others as a result of Jacobi's criticism. Jacobi was critical to the intellectualism of the Enlightenment, stressed the importance of belief and emotion of individuals, and influenced German Romanticism.

Biography

Jacobi was born at Düsseldorf, the second son of a wealthy sugar merchant, and was educated for a commercial career. Of a retiring, meditative disposition, Jacobi associated himself at Geneva mainly with the literary and scientific circle of which the most prominent member was Le Sage. He studied closely the works of Charles Bonnet, and the political ideas of Jean-Jacques Rousseau and Voltaire. In 1763 he was recalled to Düsseldorf, and in the following year he married and took over the management of his father's business.

After a short time, he gave up his commercial career, and in 1770 became a member of the council for the duchies of Jülich and Berg, in which capacity he distinguished himself by his ability in financial affairs and his zeal for social reform. Jacobi kept up his interest in literary and philosophic matters by an extensive correspondence, and his mansion at Pempelfort, near Düsseldorf, was the center of a distinguished literary circle. With Christoph Martin Wieland, he helped to found a new literary journal, Der Teutsche Mercur, in which some of his earliest writings, mainly on practical or economic subjects, were published.

It was in the journal that the first of his philosophic works appeared in part, Edward Allwill's Briefsammlung (1776), a combination of romance and speculation. This was followed in 1779 by Woldemar, a philosophic novel of very imperfect structure, but full of genial ideas, and gives the most complete picture of Jacobi's method of philosophizing.

In 1779, he visited Munich as member of the Privy Council; but, after a short stay there, differences with his colleagues and with the authorities of Bavaria drove him back to Pempelfort. A few unimportant tracts on questions of theoretical politics were followed in 1785 by the work which first brought Jacobi into prominence as a philosopher.

Later life

The outbreak of the war with the French Republic induced Jacobi in 1793 to leave Düsseldorf, and for nearly ten years he lived in Holstein. There he became intimately acquainted with Karl Leonhard Reinhold (in whose Beitrage his important work, Uber das Unternehmen des Kriticismus, die Vernunft zu Verstande zu bringen, was first published), and with Matthias Claudius, the editor of the Wandsbecker Bote.

During the same period the excitement caused by the accusation of atheism brought against Gottlieb Fichte at Jena led to the publication of Jacobi's Letter to Fichte (1799), in which he made more precise the relation of his own philosophic principles to theology.

Soon after his return to Germany, Jacobi received a call to Munich in connection with the new academy of sciences recently founded there. The loss of a considerable portion of his fortune induced him to accept this offer; he settled in Munich in 1804, and in 1807 became president of the academy.

In 1811 his last philosophic work appeared, directed against Schelling especially (Von den göttlichen Dingen und ihrer Offenbarung); the first part of which, a review of the Wandsbecker Bote, had been written in 1798. A bitter reply from Schelling was left without answer by Jacobi, but gave rise to an animated controversy in which Jakob Friedrich Fries and Franz Xaver von Baader took prominent part.

In 1812 Jacobi retired from the office of president, and began to prepare a collected edition of his works. He died before this was completed. The edition of his writings was continued by his friend F. Koppen, and was completed in 1825. The works fill six volumes, of which the fourth is in three parts. To the second is prefixed an introduction by Jacobi, which is at the same time an introduction to his philosophy. The fourth volume has also an important preface.

Philosophy

A conversation which Jacobi held with Gotthold Lessing in 1780 led him to a protracted study of Spinoza's works. What followed was a correspondence with Moses Mendelssohn, published as the Briefe uber die Lehre Spinozas (1785; 2nd ed., much enlarged and with important appendices, 1789) expressed sharply and clearly Jacobi's strenuous objection to a rationalist orientation and systematic construction of philosophy, and drew upon him the vigorous enmity of the Berlin clique, led by Mendelssohn. Jacobi and Mendelssohn disputed over the interpretation of Spinoza, and this dispute was known as "Pantheism Dispute." Through this dispute, Spinoza's philosophy was recognized not simply as atheism but as pantheism, and Spinoza's vitalist view of nature came to be known to others, which influenced the formation of German Romanticism.

Jacobi addressed a number of criticisms to major thinkers including Fichte, Schelling, and Kant for their neglect of "belief" and "emotion" as the basis of philosophy. Jacobi, however, was also ridiculed for trying to reintroduce the irrational elements such as belief and emotion into philosophy and was denounced as an enemy of reason, as a pietist, and as a Jesuit in disguise. He was also attacked for his use of the ambiguous term "belief."

Jacobi’s next important work, David Hume Über den Glauben, oder Idealismus und Realismus (1787), was an attempt to show not only that the term Glaube (faith) had been used by the most eminent writers to denote what he had employed it for in the Letters on Spinoza, but that the nature of the cognition. In this writing, and especially in the appendix, Jacobi came into contact with the critical philosophy, and criticized Kantian view of knowledge.

As Jacobi starts with the doctrine that thought is partial and limited, applicable only to connect facts but incapable of explaining the aspect of their existence, it is evident that for him, any demonstrative system of metaphysic which should attempt to subject all existence to the principle of logical ground must be repulsive. Jacobi argued that human cognitive capacity was limited and incapable of grasping God; it was belief that allowed humans to recognize God.

Now, in modern philosophy, the first and greatest demonstrative system of metaphysic is that of Spinoza, and it lies in the nature of things that upon Spinoza's system Jacobi should first direct his criticism. Some major points of his examination are as follows (Werke, i. 216-223):

  • Spinozism is atheism
  • the philosophy of Leibniz and Wolff is not less fatalistic than that of Spinoza
  • every demonstrative method ends in fatalism (nihilism)
  • we can demonstrate only similarities (agreements, truths conditionally necessary), proceeding always in identical propositions; every proof presupposes something already proved, the principle of which is immediately given (Offenbarung, revelation, is the term here employed by Jacobi to denote the peculiar character of an immediate, unproved truth)
  • the keystone (Element) of all human knowledge and activity is "belief" (Glaube, or "faith")
  • Motive of moral action is not the rational understanding of the moral laws as Kant claimed, but the emotional feeling which precedes reason.

Jacobi attacked the humanistic values of the Enlightenment and their emphasis on rationalism. He did not completely deny the function of reason; rather, he criticized the creation of a systematic philosophy in which the principles of reason and consequent have obligated philosophers to shape their concept according to their path of logic. Thus, he characterized "Glaube" as the key element of human knowledge and took this to be the keystone of reason.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Jacobi, F. H. David Hume Ueber Den Glauben, Oder Idealismus Und Realismus (“The Philosophy of David Hume”). Taylor & Francis, 1982. ISBN 0824054091
  • di Giovanni, G. (ed. and trans.). 1994. The Main Philosophical Writings and the Novel 'Allwill'. Kingston, O.N. and Montreal, PQ: McGill-Queen University Press.
  • Wilde, N. 1894. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi: A Study of the Origin of German Realism. Columbia College. ASIN B00085BU4W
  • Rehder, H. 1965. Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi and German Thought During the Eighteenth Century. Austin, TX: University of Texas Press. ASIN B0007HY43K

This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.

External links

All links retrieved April 11, 2024.

General Philosophy Sources


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.