Encyclopedia, Difference between revisions of "Antoine Arnauld" - New World

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 7: Line 7:
 
Antoine Arnauld was born in Paris on February 8, 1612.  His family was a particularly important one in France, with various connections to the convent at Port-Royal (Arnauld's older sistent, Mère Angélique, had become the abbess in 1602).  Arnauld's original aspiration was to become a lawyer, as his father had.  Yet by 1633, Arnauld had decided to pursue theology instead.  In 1640, he joined an informal group of intellectuals associated with the Port-Royal convent, whose ranks included [[Blaise Pascal]] and Pierre Nicole.  That same year, he was asked to write a series of objections to a forthcoming work by René [[Descartes]].  These objections were published the following year as the Fourth Objections to Descartes' landmark ''Meditations''.  Arnauld's objections were particularly incisive, and he began to establish his reputation as one of the most powerful analytic minds of his day.
 
Antoine Arnauld was born in Paris on February 8, 1612.  His family was a particularly important one in France, with various connections to the convent at Port-Royal (Arnauld's older sistent, Mère Angélique, had become the abbess in 1602).  Arnauld's original aspiration was to become a lawyer, as his father had.  Yet by 1633, Arnauld had decided to pursue theology instead.  In 1640, he joined an informal group of intellectuals associated with the Port-Royal convent, whose ranks included [[Blaise Pascal]] and Pierre Nicole.  That same year, he was asked to write a series of objections to a forthcoming work by René [[Descartes]].  These objections were published the following year as the Fourth Objections to Descartes' landmark ''Meditations''.  Arnauld's objections were particularly incisive, and he began to establish his reputation as one of the most powerful analytic minds of his day.
  
In 1641, Arnauld was ordained a priest.  Two years later, he was admitted to the faculty of the Sorbonne.  That same year, he published ''De la fréquente communion'', a critique of the Jesuits.  This work remained influential in Catholic circles well into the 1800's.
+
In 1641, Arnauld was ordained a priest.  Two years later, he was admitted to the faculty of the Sorbonne.  That same year, he published ''De la fréquente communion'', a critique of the Jesuits.  This work remained influential in Catholic circles well into the 1800's.
  
The twentieth and youngest child of the original Antoine Arnauld, he was originally intended for the bar, but decided instead to study theology at the [[Collège de Sorbonne|Sorbonne]].  Here he was brilliantly successful, and his career was flourishing when he came under the influence of [[Jean du Vergier de Hauranne|Vergier]], and was drawn in the direction of [[Jansenism]]. His book, ''De la fréquente Communion'' (1643), was an important step in making the aims and ideals of this movement intelligible to the general public. Its appearance attracted controversy, and Arnauld was forced to go into hiding; for more than twenty years he dared not appear publicly in [[Paris]].
+
==Philosophy==
  
During this time he produced innumerable Jansenist [[pamphlet]]s. In [[1655]] two very outspoken ''Lettres à un duc et pair'' on [[Society of Jesus|Jesuit]] methods in the confessional brought a motion to expel him from the Sorbonne. This motion was the immediate cause of [[Blaise Pascal]]'s ''[[Lettres provinciales]]''. Pascal, however, failed to save his friend; in February 1656 Arnauld was ceremonially degraded. Twelve years later the so-called "peace" of [[Pope Clement IX]] put an end to his troubles; he was graciously received by [[Louis XIV of France|Louis XIV]], and treated almost as a popular hero.
+
Arnauld's mark on the history of philosophy was primarily made via his interactions with three of the greatest rationalists of his time: [[Descartes|Rene Descartes]], Nicolas [[Malebranche]] and Gottfried [[Leibniz]]. Though his first notable work was his criticism of Descartes, he eventually became one of Descartes' most staunch defenders. Though more than capable of seeing to the heart of purely philosophical issues, Arnauld was first and foremost a theologian. His advocation of Cartesian philosophy stemmed from his belief that it best supported the tenets of the Catholic faith.
  
He now set to work with [[Pierre Nicole]] on a great work against the [[Calvinist]]s: ''La perpétuité de la foi de l'Eglise catholique: touchant l'eucharistie''. Ten years later, however, persecution resumed. Arnauld was compelled to leave France for [[the Netherlands]], finally settling down at [[Brussels]]. Here the last sixteen years of his life were spent in incessant controversy with Jesuits, Calvinists and heretics of all kinds.
+
===Objections to Descartes===
  
His inexhaustible energy is best expressed by his famous reply to Nicole, who complained of feeling tired. "Tired!" echoed Arnauld, "when you have all eternity to rest in?" His energy was not exhausted by purely theological questions. He was one of the first to adopt the philosophy of [[René Descartes]], though with certain orthodox reservations; and between 1683 and 1685 he had a long battle with [[Nicolas Malebranche]] on the relation of theology to [[metaphysics]]. On the whole, public opinion leant to Arnauld's side. When Malebranche complained that his adversary had misunderstood him, [[Nicolas Boileau-Despréaux|Boileau]] silenced him with the question: "My dear sir, whom do you expect to understand you, if M. Arnauld does not?" And popular record for Arnauld's penetration was much increased in his ''L'Art de penser'', commonly known as the ''[[Port-Royal Logic]]'', which kept its place as an elementary text-book until the [[20th century]].
+
Descartes' ''Meditations'' was published in 1641 along with six sets of objections andd replies.  Arnauld composed the fourth set of objections.  His most famous objection to the ''Meditations'' is his description of what has come to be known as 'The Cartesian Circle.Arnauld noticed that Descartes relied on what he termed 'clear and distinct perceptions' in reaching the premises in his arguments for the existence of God, then used the existence of God as a premise in his argument for the claim that all he clearly and distinctly perceived to be the case had to be true. Such a form of argument, however, was circular - each argument relied on a premise that could only be accepted if one already accepted the conclusion of that argument.
  
Arnauld came to be regarded as important among the mathematicians of his time; one critic described him as the [[Euclid]] of the [[17th century]]. After his death, his reputation began to wane. Contemporaries admired him as a master of intricate reasoning; on this, [[Jacques-Bénigne Bossuet]], the greatest theologian of the age, agreed with [[Henry François d'Aguesseau]], the greatest [[lawyer]].  However, his eagerness to win every argument endeared him to no one"In spite of myself," Arnauld once said regretfully, "my books are seldom very short." If not for his connection with Pascal, Arnauld's name would be almost forgotten—or, at most, live only in the famous epitaph Boileau consecrated to his memory—as
+
Descartes' response was quite brief.  He pointed Arnauld back to passages where he had noted the use of the proof of God with respect to the memory of things formerly clearly and distinctly perceivedMost, but not all, contemporary readers of Descartes have found this response thoroughly unsatisfactory.
<blockquote>
 
"Au pied de cet autel de structure grossière<br />
 
Gît sans pompe, enfermé dans une vile bière,<br />
 
Le plus savant mortel qui jamais ait écrit ;<br />
 
...
 
</blockquote>
 
Antoine Arnauld's complete works (thirty-seven volumes in forty-two parts) were published in Paris, 1775-1781. There is a study of his philosophy in [[Francisque Bouillier]], ''Histoire de la philosophie cartésienne'' (Paris, 1868); and his mathematical achievements are discussed by [[Franz Bopp]] in the 14th volume of the ''Abhandilgen zur Geschichte der mathematischen Wissenschaften'' (Leipzig, 1902).
 
  
Arnauld conducted an extensive correspondence with [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]], regarding the latter's "Discourse on Metaphysics".
+
Arnauld also took issue with Descartes' certainty that there is nothing in the mind of which we are not aware.  To shed doubt on this view, Arnauld cited the example of an infant in its mother's womb, who surely is so far unaware that she has the power to think. 
 +
 
 +
Relatedly, Arnauld found reason to question Descartes' proof of the distinctness of the mind and body, which was based on his having a clear and distinct perception of each without the other.  If such a line of reasoning were sound, Arnauld argued, then it would likewise be reasonable for someone to argue that a triangle could be right-angled without having the square of its hypotenuse equal to the sum of the squares of its two sides (the Pythagorean Theorem).  For someone without knowledge of the Theorem might well clearly understand the nature of a right triangle, and yet have that understanding without seeing that the Theorem applied to any such triangle.
 +
 
 +
Arnauld also included a theological objection.  In the ''Meditations'', Descartes subtly provided the elements of a non-Aristotelian physics.  On Descartes' view, the physical world could be explained entirely in terms of extension and motion.  Such a view, Arnauld objected, undermined the then-established solution to the metaphysical puzzles of transubstantiation.  [[Aristotle|Aristotelian]] metaphysics described the world in terms of matter and form, and Catholic theologians had made use of these notions in saying that, in the Eucharist, the bread retained the form of bread while becoming the matter of Christ's body.  No such solution was available to Descartes, who shared Arnauld's desire for the new philosophy to remain consistent with Catholic doctrine.
 +
 
 +
===Debate with Malebranche===
 +
 
 +
Arnauld was initially supportive of [[Malebranche]]'s philosophy as presented in the latter's ''The Search After Truth'' (first published in 1674-75).  Like Arnauld, Malebranche was a priest whose interest in philosophy was largely theologically motivated.  Also like Arnauld, Malebranche drew heavily from the thought of Descartes and [[Augustine|St. Augustine]] - indeed, both Malebranche and Arnauld came to be regarded as experts in the new Cartesian philosophy.
 +
 
 +
===Correspondence with Leibniz===
  
 
==References==
 
==References==

Revision as of 01:55, 13 July 2006

Antoine Arnauld.

Antoine Arnauld, (1612 - August 8, 1694) — le grand as contemporaries called him, to distinguish him from his father — was a French Roman Catholic theologian, philosopher, and mathematician.

Biography

Antoine Arnauld was born in Paris on February 8, 1612. His family was a particularly important one in France, with various connections to the convent at Port-Royal (Arnauld's older sistent, Mère Angélique, had become the abbess in 1602). Arnauld's original aspiration was to become a lawyer, as his father had. Yet by 1633, Arnauld had decided to pursue theology instead. In 1640, he joined an informal group of intellectuals associated with the Port-Royal convent, whose ranks included Blaise Pascal and Pierre Nicole. That same year, he was asked to write a series of objections to a forthcoming work by René Descartes. These objections were published the following year as the Fourth Objections to Descartes' landmark Meditations. Arnauld's objections were particularly incisive, and he began to establish his reputation as one of the most powerful analytic minds of his day.

In 1641, Arnauld was ordained a priest. Two years later, he was admitted to the faculty of the Sorbonne. That same year, he published De la fréquente communion, a critique of the Jesuits. This work remained influential in Catholic circles well into the 1800's.

Philosophy

Arnauld's mark on the history of philosophy was primarily made via his interactions with three of the greatest rationalists of his time: Rene Descartes, Nicolas Malebranche and Gottfried Leibniz. Though his first notable work was his criticism of Descartes, he eventually became one of Descartes' most staunch defenders. Though more than capable of seeing to the heart of purely philosophical issues, Arnauld was first and foremost a theologian. His advocation of Cartesian philosophy stemmed from his belief that it best supported the tenets of the Catholic faith.

Objections to Descartes

Descartes' Meditations was published in 1641 along with six sets of objections andd replies. Arnauld composed the fourth set of objections. His most famous objection to the Meditations is his description of what has come to be known as 'The Cartesian Circle.' Arnauld noticed that Descartes relied on what he termed 'clear and distinct perceptions' in reaching the premises in his arguments for the existence of God, then used the existence of God as a premise in his argument for the claim that all he clearly and distinctly perceived to be the case had to be true. Such a form of argument, however, was circular - each argument relied on a premise that could only be accepted if one already accepted the conclusion of that argument.

Descartes' response was quite brief. He pointed Arnauld back to passages where he had noted the use of the proof of God with respect to the memory of things formerly clearly and distinctly perceived. Most, but not all, contemporary readers of Descartes have found this response thoroughly unsatisfactory.

Arnauld also took issue with Descartes' certainty that there is nothing in the mind of which we are not aware. To shed doubt on this view, Arnauld cited the example of an infant in its mother's womb, who surely is so far unaware that she has the power to think.

Relatedly, Arnauld found reason to question Descartes' proof of the distinctness of the mind and body, which was based on his having a clear and distinct perception of each without the other. If such a line of reasoning were sound, Arnauld argued, then it would likewise be reasonable for someone to argue that a triangle could be right-angled without having the square of its hypotenuse equal to the sum of the squares of its two sides (the Pythagorean Theorem). For someone without knowledge of the Theorem might well clearly understand the nature of a right triangle, and yet have that understanding without seeing that the Theorem applied to any such triangle.

Arnauld also included a theological objection. In the Meditations, Descartes subtly provided the elements of a non-Aristotelian physics. On Descartes' view, the physical world could be explained entirely in terms of extension and motion. Such a view, Arnauld objected, undermined the then-established solution to the metaphysical puzzles of transubstantiation. Aristotelian metaphysics described the world in terms of matter and form, and Catholic theologians had made use of these notions in saying that, in the Eucharist, the bread retained the form of bread while becoming the matter of Christ's body. No such solution was available to Descartes, who shared Arnauld's desire for the new philosophy to remain consistent with Catholic doctrine.

Debate with Malebranche

Arnauld was initially supportive of Malebranche's philosophy as presented in the latter's The Search After Truth (first published in 1674-75). Like Arnauld, Malebranche was a priest whose interest in philosophy was largely theologically motivated. Also like Arnauld, Malebranche drew heavily from the thought of Descartes and St. Augustine - indeed, both Malebranche and Arnauld came to be regarded as experts in the new Cartesian philosophy.

Correspondence with Leibniz

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.

External links

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.