Difference between revisions of "Pierre Bayle" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 15: Line 15:
  
 
Bayle died peacefully on December 28, 1706.
 
Bayle died peacefully on December 28, 1706.
 +
 +
==Philosophy==
 +
 +
Bayle appeared near the end of a long tradition of attempts to reconcile fundamental points of Christian doctrine with fundamental principles of reason.  In its strongest form this tradition extended from the early Christians, through the medievals, and into the beginning of the 18th century.  Among the classic problems were the doctrine of transubstantiation in the Eucharist, the doctrine of the trinity, and problem of the existence of evil in a world created by a benevolent God.
 +
 +
In contrast to his contemporaries (such as [[Malebranche]] and [[Leibniz]]), Bayle insisted that no reconciliation was possible.  Advocating a form of [[fideism]], Bayle held that the tenets of faith could neither be reached nor understood through reason.  This general view appears amid a wide range of criticisms of other thinkers, primarily in the ''Dictionnaire'', and so is best illustrated with examples.
 +
 +
===Criticism of Malebranche===
 +
 +
A particularly clear instance of this line of thought appears in Bayle's critique of Malebranche's theodicy (his purported solution to the problem of evil).  In sum, Malebranche held that evil was the result of God's reconciliation of two aims: producing the best possible world, and using the best possible means to do so.  Malebranche conceded that our world is not the best possible one, but held that the combination of the goodness of the world and the simplicity of the means was the best possible such combination.  Given this, the evil in the world was merely a foreseen but intended consequence of God's creation.
 +
 +
Bayle's response to this solution centered around an analogy.  Consider a mother who sends her daughters into a situation where she knows they will succumb to temptation, while nevertheless encouraging them to be virtuous.  In such a case, Bayle argued, it is clear that the inevitable failing of the daughters was not something the mother intended, even though she foresaw it.  Yet clearly the mother is at fault in this case, since it was within her power to prevent the failing.  Likewise, in Malebranche's view, God has it within his power to prevent evil, yet does not do so out of considerations of simplicity in means.  Such considerations hardly appear to exonerate God, so, according to Bayle, Malebranche offers no true solution to the difficulty.
 +
 +
===Skepticism about Reason===
 +
 +
Unsurprisingly, Bayle offered no alternative to Malebranche's theodicy.  Yet this was not merely because the issue was a theological problem.  Bayle held that reason was better equipped to criticize and undermine than to build, so that skeptical arguments were unavoidable.
 +
 +
One instance of this view appears in an argument (found in the footnote to the article on Zeno of Elea in the ''Dictionnare'') which later greatly influenced the Irish Bishop [[Berkeley|George Berkeley]].  Bayle focuses on [[John Locke]]'s distinction between primary and secondary qualities.  According to Locke, primary qualities (such as extension) produce ideas in our minds which resemble the objects themselves, whereas secondary qualities (such as color) produce ideas which do not resemble the objects.  Locke argues this by noting that the ideas we have of (e.g.) colors often vary without any changes in the objects themselves.  For instance, the color of an apple appears more yellow than normal if one is affected by jaundice, yet this variation does not require any variation in the apple itself.  Given this, it would appear that either the apple is simultaneously two different colors, or that it is itself neither color.  Since the former option is absurd, the latter option must be the case.
 +
 +
Bayle noted that arguments of the exact same form can be used for ''any'' quality, not merely those designated by Locke as 'primary.'  For, depending on one's distance and perspective, the ideas one has of any aspect of an object's extension (shape, dimension, etc.) will vary without the object itself varying.  For instance, a plate sitting on a table appears round if viewed from overhead, yet appears to be an extended line if viewed from the side.  Likewise, though an acorn appears small to us, it must appear very large to a flea.  It would appear, then, that none of our ideas are capable of resembling anything in the objects themselves.
 +
 +
The overall suggestion on Bayle's part seems to be that the self-defeat of reason makes the acceptance of religious doctrine easier, despite the fact that that doctrine cannot be understood through reason.
 +
 +
===Political Thought===
 +
 +
Bayle's skepticism and fideism was largely confined to the theoretical realm.  As suggested by his ''Lettre sur la Comète'', his view of morality was quite different.
  
 
==Editions==
 
==Editions==

Revision as of 22:36, 6 August 2006

Pierre Bayle.

Template:French literature (small)

Pierre Bayle (November 18, 1647 – December 28, 1706) was a French philosopher, skeptic, and writer.

Biography

Pierre Bayle was born at La Carla (near Brive-la-Gaillarde) in southwestern France on November 19, 1647. His family was of modest means, and strictly Calvinist - in fact, Bayle's father was a Calvinist minister. After studying at the local school and spending some time educating himself, Bayle took up studies at the Protestant academy in Puylaurens in 1668. Shortly thereafter, Bayle (secretly) transfered to a Jesuit college in Toulouse. While there, Bayle briefly converted to Catholicism, only to convert back to Calvinism after receiving his Master's degree. French law, however, forbade conversions from Catholicism, and Bayle had fled to Geneva by 1670. Bayle continued his studies in Geneva, until accepting a position as Professor of Philosophy at the Protestant Academy in Sedan (near the present-day border of France and Belgium). Bayle taught at the academy for five years, leaving only when it was officially closed in 1681. He moved to Rotterdam, where he taught at the École Illustre for the remainder of his life.

Bayle's first publications date from soon after his arrival in Rotterdam. These began with his anonymous Lettre sur la Comète (Letter concerning the comet) in 1682. Though the work superficially concerned the nature of comets, Bayle's real purpose was to argue that humans could behavor morally even without any religious beliefs - so that even atheists could maintain a moral society. The implication was that mere considerations of the stability of morality and society were not sufficient to justify persecution based on religious beliefs. This basic theme appeared consistently elswhere in Bayle's work, and has clear roots in his experience of Huguenot persecution by French authorities under Louis XIV.

Through the mid-1680s, Bayle edited a journal entitled Nouvelles de la République des lettres, which published reviews of recent work in nearly all areas of learning. The creation of such journals was a significant factor in the development of the Enlightenment, and the success of the Nouvelles journal did much to advance the trend.

Bayle published a number of other philosophical, political and theological works in the years that followed, yet his most significant publication is the Dictionnaire historique et critique, first published in 1696. While the majority of its material is devoted to non-evaluative information concerning nearly every known philosopher and theologian, the most striking feature of the work is found in footnotes to the main articles. These footnotes were to be tremendously influential with respect to the philosophies of such figures as Berkeley, Leibniz, Hume, and Voltaire.

Bayle died peacefully on December 28, 1706.

Philosophy

Bayle appeared near the end of a long tradition of attempts to reconcile fundamental points of Christian doctrine with fundamental principles of reason. In its strongest form this tradition extended from the early Christians, through the medievals, and into the beginning of the 18th century. Among the classic problems were the doctrine of transubstantiation in the Eucharist, the doctrine of the trinity, and problem of the existence of evil in a world created by a benevolent God.

In contrast to his contemporaries (such as Malebranche and Leibniz), Bayle insisted that no reconciliation was possible. Advocating a form of fideism, Bayle held that the tenets of faith could neither be reached nor understood through reason. This general view appears amid a wide range of criticisms of other thinkers, primarily in the Dictionnaire, and so is best illustrated with examples.

Criticism of Malebranche

A particularly clear instance of this line of thought appears in Bayle's critique of Malebranche's theodicy (his purported solution to the problem of evil). In sum, Malebranche held that evil was the result of God's reconciliation of two aims: producing the best possible world, and using the best possible means to do so. Malebranche conceded that our world is not the best possible one, but held that the combination of the goodness of the world and the simplicity of the means was the best possible such combination. Given this, the evil in the world was merely a foreseen but intended consequence of God's creation.

Bayle's response to this solution centered around an analogy. Consider a mother who sends her daughters into a situation where she knows they will succumb to temptation, while nevertheless encouraging them to be virtuous. In such a case, Bayle argued, it is clear that the inevitable failing of the daughters was not something the mother intended, even though she foresaw it. Yet clearly the mother is at fault in this case, since it was within her power to prevent the failing. Likewise, in Malebranche's view, God has it within his power to prevent evil, yet does not do so out of considerations of simplicity in means. Such considerations hardly appear to exonerate God, so, according to Bayle, Malebranche offers no true solution to the difficulty.

Skepticism about Reason

Unsurprisingly, Bayle offered no alternative to Malebranche's theodicy. Yet this was not merely because the issue was a theological problem. Bayle held that reason was better equipped to criticize and undermine than to build, so that skeptical arguments were unavoidable.

One instance of this view appears in an argument (found in the footnote to the article on Zeno of Elea in the Dictionnare) which later greatly influenced the Irish Bishop George Berkeley. Bayle focuses on John Locke's distinction between primary and secondary qualities. According to Locke, primary qualities (such as extension) produce ideas in our minds which resemble the objects themselves, whereas secondary qualities (such as color) produce ideas which do not resemble the objects. Locke argues this by noting that the ideas we have of (e.g.) colors often vary without any changes in the objects themselves. For instance, the color of an apple appears more yellow than normal if one is affected by jaundice, yet this variation does not require any variation in the apple itself. Given this, it would appear that either the apple is simultaneously two different colors, or that it is itself neither color. Since the former option is absurd, the latter option must be the case.

Bayle noted that arguments of the exact same form can be used for any quality, not merely those designated by Locke as 'primary.' For, depending on one's distance and perspective, the ideas one has of any aspect of an object's extension (shape, dimension, etc.) will vary without the object itself varying. For instance, a plate sitting on a table appears round if viewed from overhead, yet appears to be an extended line if viewed from the side. Likewise, though an acorn appears small to us, it must appear very large to a flea. It would appear, then, that none of our ideas are capable of resembling anything in the objects themselves.

The overall suggestion on Bayle's part seems to be that the self-defeat of reason makes the acceptance of religious doctrine easier, despite the fact that that doctrine cannot be understood through reason.

Political Thought

Bayle's skepticism and fideism was largely confined to the theoretical realm. As suggested by his Lettre sur la Comète, his view of morality was quite different.

Editions

  • Historical and Critical Dictionary (1695-1697; 1702, enlarged; best that of P. des Maizeaux, 4 vols., 1740)
  • Les Œuvres de Bayle (3 vols., The Hague)
  • des Maizeaux, Vie de Bayle
  • LA Feuerbach, Pierre Bayle (1838)
  • Damiron, La Philosophie en France au XVIII' siècle (1858-1864)
  • Sainte-Beuve, “Du genie critique et de Bayle" (Revue des deux mondes, December 1, 1855)
  • A. Deschamps, La Génèse du scepticisme erudit chez Bayle (Liege, 1878)
  • J. Denis, Bayle et furleu (Paris, 1886)
  • Ferdinand Brunetière, La Critique littéraire au XVIII' siècle (vol. 1, 1890), and La Critique de Bayle (1893)
  • Émile Gigas, Choix de to correspondance inédite de Pierre Bayle (Paris, 1890, reviewed in Revue critique, December 22 1890)
  • de Budé, Lettres inédites adressées a J. A. Turretini (Paris, 1887)
  • J. F. Stephen, Horae Sabbaticae (London, 1892, 3rd ser. pp. 174192)
  • A. Cazes, P. Bayle, sa vie, ses œuvres, etc. (1905).

Reference

  • This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.

External links


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.