Lotze, Rudolf Hermann

From New World Encyclopedia
(import from wiki)
 
 
(18 intermediate revisions by 11 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
'''Rudolf Herman Lotze''' ([[May 21]], [[1817]] - [[July 1]], [[1881]]), was a [[Germany|German]] [[philosopher]] and [[logician]]. He also had a medical degree and was unusually well versed in biology. He argued that if the physical world is governed by mechanical laws, relations and developments in the universe could be explained as the functioning of a world mind. His medical studies were pioneering works in scientific [[psychology]].
+
{{Paid}}{{Approved}}{{Images OK}}{{Submitted}}{{copyedited}}
 +
{{epname|Lotze, Rudolf Hermann}}
 +
'''Rudolf Herman Lotze''' (May 21, 1817 - July 1, 1881), was a preeminent [[Germany|German]] [[philosophy|philosopher]] and [[logic|logician]] during the second half of the nineteenth century. He obtained a [[medicine|medical]] degree and was unusually well versed in [[biology]]. He tried to reconcile [[German idealism]] with scientific [[mechanism]] by asserting that scientific laws and principles were incomprehensible without an underlying higher purpose, the realization of a world of goodness. He also proposed that the role of philosophy was not to discover universal principles, but to clarify and organize existing concepts and ideas into an intelligible system. Convinced of the emptiness of philosophical terms and abstract notions, he declared that ultimate reality was larger and wider than philosophy, and its unity could only be understood in terms of the multitude of [[human being|human]] experiences and observations of everyday [[life]].
 +
{{toc}}
 +
Lotze combined the [[monad]]s of [[Gottfried Leibniz]]'s spheres of individual existence with the pantheism of [[Baruch Spinoza]]. He suggested that the "monads" existed within a universal substance. He taught that the human [[soul]] regards universal substance as an absolutely good being, a [[God]] of [[love]]. Lotze applied the general principles used in the investigation of inorganic phenomena to the study of the physical and mental phenomena of the human [[organism]], in its normal and diseased states. He wrote several treatises on [[Aesthetics|aesthetics]]. He included aesthetic values with [[morality|moral]] [[values]] as part of the underlying tendency towards goodness which give meaning to existence.
  
==From 1911 Ency. Britannica==
+
== Life ==
He was born in [[Bautzen]], [[Saxony]], [[Germany]], the son of a physician. He was educated at the gymnasium of [[Zittau]]; he had an enduring love of the classical authors, translating of the ''[[Antigone]]'' of [[Sophocles]] into [[Latin]] verse, published in his middle age.  
+
Rudolf Herman Lotze was born in Bautzen, Saxony, [[Germany]], on May 21, 1817, the son of an army [[surgeon]]. He was educated at the gymnasium of Zittau; he wrote [[poetry]] and had an enduring love of the classical authors, translating ''Antigone'' of [[Sophocles]] into [[Latin]] verse (published when he was middle-aged). At the age of seventeen, he entered the University of Leipzig as a student of medicine, perhaps to please his father, but he also studied philosophy, psychology, physics, and mathematics under [[E.H. Weber]], [[W. Volckmann]], [[Gustav Fechner]], and [[Christian Hermann Weisse]]. He was interested both in science and the idealism of [[Fichte|Gottlieb Fichte]], [[Schelling|Friedrich von Schelling]], and [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Georg Hegel]].  
  
He attended the [[University of Leipzig]] as a student of philosophy and natural sciences, but entered officially as a student of medicine. He was then only seventeen. It appears that thus early Lotze's studies were governed by two distinct interests. The first was scientific, based upon mathematical and physical studies under the guidance of [[E. H. Weber]], [[W. Volckmann]] and [[Gustav Fechner]]. The other was his aesthetic and artistic interest, which was developed under the care of [[Christian Hermann Weisse]]. He was interested both in science and the idealism of [[Gottlieb Fichte]], [[Friedrich von Schelling]] and [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Georg Hegel]].
+
Four months after receiving his doctorate in philosophy in 1838, Lotze was awarded a doctorate in medicine for his dissertation ''De futurae biologiae principibus philosophicis.''  In 1841, at the age of twenty-four, he became a junior lecturer at Leipzig. He published two short books on philosophy, ''Metaphysik'' (Leipzig, 1841) and ''Logik'' (1843). In 1844, he succeeded [[Johann Friedrich Herbart]] in the chair of philosophy at the University of Göttingen.  
  
Lotze's first essay was his dissertation ''De futurae biologiae principibus philosophicis'', with which he gained (1838) the degree of doctor of medicine, only four months after obtaining the degree of doctor of philosophy. He laid the foundation of his philosophical system in his ''Metaphysik'' (Leipzig, 1841) and his ''Logik'' (1843), short books published while still a junior lecturer at Leipzig, from where he moved to [[university of Göttingen|Göttingen]], succeeding [[Johann Friedrich Herbart]] in the chair of philosophy.
+
His two early books remained unnoticed by the reading public, and Lotze first became known to a larger circle through his ''Allgemeine Pathologie und Therapie als mechanische Naturwissenschaften'' (Leipzig, 1842, 2nd ed., 1848), the articles "''Lebenskraft''" (1843) and "''Seele und Seelenleben''" (1846) in Rud. Wagner's ''Handwörterbuck der Physiologie,'' his ''Allgemeine Physiologie des Korperlichen Lebens'' (Leipzig, 1851), and his ''Medizinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele'' (Leipzig, 1852). Lotze applied the general principles used in the investigation of inorganic phenomena to the study of the physical and mental phenomena of the human organism, in its normal and diseased states. When Lotze published these works, medical science was still under the influence of Schelling's [[natural philosophy|philosophy of nature]], and the mechanical laws were considered to be valid only in the inorganic world. Though Lotze reiterated that his ideas did not include a solution of the philosophical question regarding the nature of [[mechanism]], his works, published during the years when the modern school of German [[materialism]] was at its height, were counted among the literature of [[Empiricism|empirical philosophy]].  
  
It was only during the last decade of his life that he ventured, hesitantly, to present his ideas in a systematic and final form. His two early books remained unnoticed by the reading public, and Lotze first became known to a larger circle through a series of works which aimed at establishing in the study of the physical and mental phenomena of the human organism in its normal and diseased states the same general principles which had been adopted in. the investigation of inorganic phenomena. These works were his ''Allgemeine Pathologie und Therapie als mechanische Naturwissenschaften'' (Leipzig, 1842, 2nd ed., 1848), the articles "''Lebenskraft''" (1843) and "''Seele und Seelenleben''" (1846) in Rud. Wagner's ''Handwörterbuck der Physiologie'', his ''Allgemeine Physiologie des Korperlichen Lebens'' (Leipzig, 1851), and his ''Medizinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele'' (Leipzig, 1852).
+
This misinterpretation of his ideas induced Lotze to publish a small polemical pamphlet (''Streitschriften,'' Leipzig, 1857), in which he corrected two mistakes: Some associated him with the materialistic school because of his opposition to [[Hegel]]'s formalism, while others regarded him as a follower of Herbart. Lotze denied that he belonged to the school of Herbart, though he incorporated the monadology of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]] in his views. When Lotze wrote these explanations, he had already published the first volume of his ''Mikrokosmus'' (vol. i. 1856, vol. ii. 1858, vol. iii. 1864). In many passages of his works on [[pathology]], [[physiology]], and [[psychology]], Lotze had distinctly stated that the method of research which he advocated did not give an explanation of the phenomena of life and mind, but only the means of observing and connecting them together. He emphasized that by studying the macrocosm of the universe, it is possible to acquire data necessary for deciding what meaning attaches to the existence of the microcosmic world of human life.
  
When Lotze published these works, medical science was still under the influence of Schelling's [[philosophy of nature]]. The mechanical laws, to which external things were subject, were conceived as being valid only in the inorganic world. Mechanism was the unalterable connexion of every phenomenon ''a'' with other phenomena ''b'', ''c'', ''d'', either as following or preceding it; mechanism was the inexorable form into which the events of this world are cast, and by which they are connected. The object of those writings was to establish the all-pervading rule of mechanism. But the mechanical view of nature is not identical with the materialistic. In the last of the above-mentioned works the question is discussed at great length how we have to consider mind, and the relation between mind and body; the answer is we have to consider mind as an immaterial principle, its action, however, on the body and vice versa as purely mechanical, indicated by the fixed laws of a psycho-physical mechanism.  
+
As professor of philosophy at Göttingen, Lotze delivered  annual lectures on [[psychology]] and [[logic]] (the latter included a survey of all philosophical research, under the title ''Encyclopädie der Philosophie''), and at longer intervals, lectures on [[metaphysics]], [[philosophy of nature]], [[philosophy of art]], [[philosophy of religion]], and occasionally on the history of philosophy and [[ethics]]. During these lectures he developed his ideas in relation to each of these subjects, and during the last decade of his life he embodied the substance of those courses in his ''System der Philosophie.'' Only two volumes were published, Vol. i. ''Logik'' (1st ed., Leipzig, 1874, 2nd ed., 1880) and Vol ii. ''Metaphysik'' (1879). The third and concluding volume, which was to treat in a more condensed form the principal problems of practical philosophy, of philosophy of art and religion, never appeared. A small pamphlet on psychology, containing the last form in which he had begun to treat the subject in his lectures, was published by his son.  
  
These doctrines of Lotze, though pronounced with the distinct and reiterated reserve that they did not contain a solution of the philosophical question regarding the nature of mechanism, were nevertheless by many considered to be the last word of the philosopher, denouncing the reveries of Schelling or the idealistic theories of Hegel. Published as they were during the years when the modern school of German [[materialism]] was at its height, these works of Lotze were counted among the opposition literature of [[empirical philosophy]]. Even philosophers of the eminence of [[I. H. Fichte]] (the younger) did not escape this misinterpretation of Lotze's true meaning.  
+
In 1881, Lotze joined the faculty at Berlin but, after three months, died of a chest infection on July 1, 1881.
  
The misinterpretations which he had suffered induced Lotze to publish a small polemical pamphlet (''Streitschriften'', Leipzig, 1857), in which he corrected two mistakes. His opposition to Hegel's formalism had induced some to associate him with the materialistic school, others to count him among the followers of [[Herbart]]. Lotze denied that he belonged to the school of Herbart. though he admitted that historically the same doctrine which might be considered the forerunner of Herbart's teachings might lead to his own views, viz. the [[monad]]ology of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibniz]].
+
== Thought and works ==
 +
Lotze was a preeminent figure in German academic philosophy during the second half of the nineteenth century. He recognized the validity of the methods of mechanistic science but perceived the limitations of [[mechanism]] in explaining human consciousness and in providing an underlying justification for the existence of mankind and the universe. He made ethics the starting point of his philosophy, which he called '''teleogical idealism,''' asserting that the causes and effects observed in nature were incomprehensible without an underlying purpose, the realization of a world of goodness. Lotze believed that philosophy should be rooted in the natural sciences, since human beings and inanimate objects are subject to the same natural laws. However, he held that knowledge was acquired through observation and experimentation; reality could not be deduced from laws and principles, and the purpose of philosophy was to analyze and organize the concepts that came from scientific observation. Physiology and other natural sciences could contribute to the explanation of human behavior, but Lotze felt that certain metaphysical concepts like “vital force,” which were still popular in biology during the 1800s, were not scientific enough and should be done away with.
  
When Lotze wrote these explanations, he had already published the first volume of his ''Mikrokosmus'' (vol. i. 1856, vol. ii. 1858, vol. iii. 1864). In many passages of his works on [[pathology]], [[physiology]], and [[psychology]] Lotze had distinctly stated that the method of research which he advocated there did not give an explanation of the phenomena of life and mind, but only the means of observing and connecting them together; we gain the necessary data for deciding what meaning attaches to the existence of this microcosm, or small world of human life, in the macrocosm of the universe.
+
Mechanism was the unalterable connection of every phenomenon ''a'' with other phenomena ''b,'' ''c,'' ''d,'' either following or preceding it; mechanism was the inexorable form into which the events of this world are cast, and by which they are connected.
  
This review, which extends, in three volumes, over the wide field of anthropology, beginning with the human frame, the soul, and their union in life, advancing to man his mind, and the course of the world, and concluding with history, progress, and the connexion of things, ends with the same idea which was expressed in Lotze's earliest work, his ''Metaphysik''. The view peculiar to him is reached in the end as the crowning conception towards which all separate channels of thought have tended, and in the light of which the life of man in nature and mind, in the individual and in society, had been surveyed. This view can be briefly stated as follows: Every where in the wide realm of observation we find three distinct regions,—the region of facts, the region of laws and the region of standards of value. These three regions are separate only in our thoughts, not in reality. To comprehend the real position we are forced to the conviction that the world of facts is the field in which, and that laws are the means by which, those higher standards of moral and aesthetic value are being realized; and such a union can again only become intelligible through he idea of a personal Deity, who in the creation and preservation of a world has voluntarily chosen certain forms and laws, through the natural operation of which the ends of His work are gained. Whilst Lotze had thus in his published works closed the circle of his thought, beginning with a conception metaphysically gained, proceeding to an exhaustive contemplation of things in the light it afforded, and ending with the stronger conviction of its truth which observation, experience, and life could afford, he had all the time been lecturing on the various branches of philosophy according to the scheme of academical instruction transmitted from his predecessors. Nor can it be considered anything but a gain that he was thus induced to expound his views with regard to those topics, and in connexion with those problems, which were the traditional forms of philosophical utterance. His lectures ranged over a wide field: he delivered annually lectures on psychology and on logic (the latter including a survey of the entirety of philosophical research under the title ''Encyclopädie der Philosophie''), then at longer intervals lectures on metaphysics, philosophy of nature, philosophy of art, philosophy of religion, rarely on history of philosophy and ethics. In these lectures he expounded his peculiar views in a stricter form, and during the last decade of his life he embodied the substance of those courses in his ''System der Philosophie'', of which only two volumes have appeared (vol. i. ''Logik'', 1st ed., Leipzig, 1874, 2nd ed., 1880; vol. ii. ''Metaphysik'', 1879). The third and concluding volume, which was to treat in a more condensed form the principal problems of practical philosophy, of philosophy of art and religion, never appeared. A small pamphlet on psychology, containing the last form in which he had begun to treat the subject in his lectures (abruptly terminated through his death) during the summer session of 1881, has been published by his son. Appended to this volume is a complete list of Lotze's writings, compiled by Professor Rehnisch of Göttingen.
+
Lotze believed that humanity was distinguishable from animals by the uniqueness of his mind; the development and history of humankind cannot be regarded as a mechanical scientific process. Humanity, because of its mind, brings unity to existence through his ideas and his ethical values. “Wholes” in nature are the product of the mind of humans.
  
To understand this series of Lotze's writings, it is necessary to begin with his definition of philosophy. This is given after his exposition of logic has established two points, viz. the existence in our mind of certain laws and forms according to which we connect the material supplied to us by our senses, and, secondly, the fact that logical thought cannot be usefully employed without the assumption of a further set of connexions, not logically necessary, but assumed to exist between the data of experience and observation. These connexions of a real not formal character are handed to us by the separate sciences and by the usage and culture of everyday life. Language has crystallized them into certain definite notions and expressions, without which we cannot proceed a single step, but which we have accepted without knowing their exact meaning, much less their origin. In consequence the special sciences and the wisdom of common life entangle themselves easily and frequently in contradictions. A problem of a purely formal character thus presents itself, viz. this to try to bring unity and harmony into the scattered thoughts of our general culture, to trace them to their primary assumptions and follow them into their ultimate consequences, to connect them all together, to remodel, curtail or amplify them, so as to remove their apparent contradictions, and to combine them in the unity of an harmonious view of things, and especially to investigate those conceptions which form the initial assumptions of the several sciences, and to fix the limits of their applicability This is the formal definition of philosophy. Whether an harmonious conception thus gained will represent more than an agreement among our thoughts, whether it will represent the real connexion of things and thus possess objective not merely subjective value, cannot be decided at the outset. It is also unwarranted to start with the expectation that everything in the world should be explained by one principle, and it is a needless restriction of our means to expect unity of method. Nor are we able to start our philosophical investigations by an inquiry into the nature of human thought and its capacity to attain an objective knowledge, as in this case we would be actually using that instrument the usefulness of which we were trying to determine. The main proof of the objective value of the view we may gain will rather lie in the degree in which it succeeds in assigning to every element of culture its due position, or in which it is able to appreciate and combine different and apparently opposite tendencies and interests, in the sort of justice with which it weighs our manifold desires and aspirations, balancing them in due proportions, refusing to sacrifice to a one-sided principle any truth or conviction which experience has proven to be useful and necessary. The investigations will then naturally divide themselves into three parts, the first of which deals with those to our mind inevitable forms in which we are obliged to think about things, if we think at all (metaphysics), the second being devoted to the great region of facts, trying to apply the results of metaphysics to these, specially the two great regions of external and mental phenomena (cosmology and psychology), the third dealing with those standards of value from which we pronounce our aesthetic or ethical approval or disapproval. In each department we shall have to aim first of all at views clear and consistent within themselves, but, secondly, we shall in the end wish to form some general idea or to risk an opinion how laws, facts and standards of value may be combined in one comprehensive view. Considerations of this latter kind will naturally present themselves in the two great departments of cosmology and psychology, or they may be delegated to an independent research under the name of religious philosophy. We have already mentioned the final conception in which Lotze's speculation culminates, that of a personal Deity, Himself the essence of all that merits existence for its own sake, who in the creation and government of a world has voluntarily chosen certain laws and forms through which His ends are to be realized. We may add that according to this view nothing is real but the living spirit of God and the world of living spirits which He has created; the things of this world have only reality in so far as they are the appearance of spiritual substance, which underlies everything. It is natural that Lotze, having this great and final conception always before him, works under its influence from the very beginning of his speculations, permitting us, as we progress, to gain every now and then a glimpse of that interpretation of things which to him contains the solution of our difficulties.
+
Lotze’s theory of [[space perception]] was an important contribution to philosophy.
  
The key to Lotze's theoretical philosophy lies in his metaphysics, to the exposition of which important subject the first and last of his larger publications have been devoted. To understand Lotze's philosophy, a careful and repeated perusal of these works is absolutely necessary. The object of his metaphysics is so to remodel the current notions regarding the existence of things and their connexions with which the usage of language supplies us as to make them consistent and thinkable. The further assumption, that the modified notions thus gained have an objective meaning, and that they somehow correspond to the real order of the existing world which of course they can never actually describe, depends upon a general confidence which we must have in our reasoning powers, and in the significance of a world in which we ourselves with all the necessary courses of our thoughts have a due place assigned. The principle therefore of these investigations is opposed to two attempts frequently repeated in the history of philosophy, viz.: (1) the attempt to establish general laws or forms, which the development of things must have obeyed, or which a Creator must have followed in the creation of a world (Hegel); and (2) the attempt to trace the genesis of our notions and decide as to their meaning and value (modern theories of knowledge). Neither of these attempts is practicable. The world of many things surrounds us; our notions, by which we manage correctly or incorrectly to describe it, are also ready made. What remains to be done is, not to explain how such a world manages to be what it is, nor how we came to form these notions, but merely this—to expel from the circle and totality of our conceptions those abstract notions which are inconsistent and jarring, or to remodel and define them so that they may constitute a consistent and harmonious view.
+
[[Aesthetics]] was a favorite study of Lotze's, perhaps because of his own artistic temperament. He wrote several essays on aesthetics in light of the leading ideas of his philosophy.  
  
In this endeavour Lotze discards as useless and untenable many favourite conceptions of the school, many crude notions of everyday life. The course of things and their connexion is only thinkable by the assumption of a plurality of existences, the reality of which (as distinguished from our knowledge of them) can be conceived only as a multitude of relations. This quality of standing in relation to other things is that which gives to a thing its reality. And the nature of this reality again can neither be consistently represented as a fixed and hard substance nor as an unalterable something, but only as a fixed order of recurrence of continually changing events or impressions. But, further, every attempt to think clearly what those relations are, what we really mean, if we talk of a fixed order of events, forces upon us the necessity of thinking also that the different things which stand in relations to the different phases which follow each other cannot be merely externally strung together or moved about by some indefinable external power, in the form of some predestination or inexorable fate The things themselves which exist and their changing phases must stand in some internal connexion; they themselves must be active or passive, capable of doing or suffering. This would lead to the view of Leibniz, that the world consists of monads, self-sufficient beings leading an inner life. But this idea involves the further conception of Leibniz, that of a pre-established harmony, by which the Creator has taken care to arrange the life of each monad, so that it agree with that of all others. This conception, according to Lotze, is neither necessary nor thoroughly intelligible. Why not interpret at once and render intelligible the common conception originating in natural science, viz. that of a system of laws which governs the many things? But, in attempting to make this conception quite clear and thinkable, we are forced to represent the connexion of things as a universal substance, the essence of which we conceive as a system of laws which underlies everything and in its own self connects everything, but is imperceptible, and known to us merely through the impressions it produces on us, which we call things.
+
=== ''Mikrokosmus'' (1856-1864) ===
 +
The three volumes of ''Mikrokosmus'' were a review of [[anthropology]], beginning with the human frame, the soul, and their relationship in life; advancing to the human mind and the course of the world; and concluding with history, progress, and the connection among all things. It concluded with the same idea which Lotze had expressed in his earliest work, ''Metaphysik,'' presented as the culmination of the preceding chapters, and as a framework for understanding his view of the existence of man, physical and mental, as an individual and a society. In every realm of observation these three distinct regions can be found; the region of facts, the region of laws and the region of standards of value. These three regions are separate only in human thoughts, not in reality. In order to comprehend reality, one must understand that the higher standards of moral and aesthetic value are being realized, by means of laws, in the realm of facts. Such a reality can only become intelligible through the existence of a personal Deity who, in the creation and preservation of the universe, has voluntarily established certain forms and laws, through the natural operation of which His purpose is realized.  
  
A final reflection then teaches us that the nature of this universal and all-pervading substance can only be imagined by us as something analogous to our own mental life, where alone we experience the unity of a substance (which we call self) preserved in the multitude of its (mental) states. It also becomes clear that only where such mental life really appears need we assign an independent existence, but that the purposes of everyday life as well as those of science are equally served if we deprive the material things outside of us of an independence, and assign to them merely a connected existence through the universal substance by the action of which alone they can appear to us.
+
=== Definition of philosophy ===
 +
Lotze established two points in his exposition of [[Logic|logic]]: The existence in the human mind of certain laws and forms, according to which people connect the data supplied to them by their senses; and secondly, the fact that logical thought cannot be usefully employed without the assumption of a further set of connections, not logically necessary, but assumed to exist between the data of experience and observation. These connections, of a real, not a formal character, come from the various sciences and from the usage and culture of everyday life. Language has crystallized them into certain definite notions and expressions, without which one cannot proceed a single step, but which people have accepted without knowing their exact meaning, much less their origin. Consequently, the special sciences and the wisdom of common life entangle themselves easily and frequently in contradictions. A problem of a purely formal character thus presents itself: How to bring unity and harmony into the scattered thoughts of general culture, to trace them to their primary assumptions and follow them into their ultimate consequences, to connect them all together, to remodel, curtail or amplify them, so as to remove their apparent contradictions, and to combine them in a united, harmonious view of things. More especially, how do we investigate those concepts which form the initial assumptions of the several sciences, and fix the limits of their applicability? This is the formal definition of philosophy.  
  
The universal substance, which we may call the absolute, is at this stage of our investigations not endowed with the attributes of a personal Deity, and it will remain to be seen by further analysis in how far we are able—without contradiction—to identify it with the object of religious veneration, in how far that which to metaphysics is merely a postulate can be gradually brought nearer to us and become a living power. Much in this direction is said by Lotze in various passages of his writings; anything complete, however, on the subject is wanting. Nor would it seem as if it could be the intention of the author to do much more than point out the lines on which the further treatment of the subject should advance. The actual result of his personal inquiries, the great idea which lies at the foundation of his philosophy, we know. It may be safely stated that Lotze would allow much latitude to individual convictions, as indeed it is evident that the empty notion of an absolute can only become living and significant to us in the same degree as experience and thought have taught us to realize the seriousness of life, the significance of creation, the value of the beautiful and the good, and the supreme worth of personal holiness. To endow the universal substance with moral attributes, to maintain that it is more than the metaphysical ground of everything, to say it is the perfect realization of the holy, the beautiful and the good, can only have a meaning for him who feels within himself what real not imaginary values are clothed in those expressions.
+
Whether a harmonious conception gained in this manner will represent more than an agreement among our thoughts; whether it will represent the real connection among things and thus possess objective, and not merely subjective, value, cannot be decided at the outset. It is unwarranted to start with the expectation that everything in the world should be explained by one principle, and it is a needless restriction of the means to expect unity of method. Philosophical investigations cannot start with an inquiry into the nature of human thought and its capacity to attain objective knowledge, because in that case we would be actually using the instrument whose usefulness we were trying to determine. The objective value of any view we gain will be proved by the degree to which it succeeds in assigning to every element of culture its due position; or in which it is able to appreciate and combine different and apparently opposite tendencies and interests; or in the justice with which it weighs human manifold desires and aspirations and balances them in due proportions, refusing to sacrifice to a one-sided principle any truth or conviction which experience has proven to be useful and necessary.  
  
We have still to mention that aesthetics formed a principal and favourite study of Lotze's, and that he has treated this subject also in the light of the leading ideas of his philosophy. See his essays ''Ueber den Begriff der Schönheit'' (Göttingen, 1845) and ''Ueber Bedingungen der Kunstschönheit'', ibid. (1847); and especially his ''Geschichte der Aesthetik in Deutschland'' (Munich, 1868).
+
Philosophical investigations will then naturally divide themselves into three parts. The first deals with the inevitable forms in which people are obliged to think about things, if they think at all ([[metaphysics]]). The second is devoted to the application of the results of metaphysics to the region of facts, especially to the regions of external and mental phenomena ([[cosmology]] and [[psychology]]). The third deals with the standards of value from which people pronounce their aesthetic or ethical approval or disapproval. In each area one must aim for views which are clear and consistent within themselves; secondly, one shall wish to form some general idea of how laws, facts, and standards of value may be combined in one comprehensive view. Considerations of this latter kind will naturally present themselves in the two great departments of cosmology and psychology, or they may be delegated to an independent research under the name of [[philosophy of religion|religious philosophy]].
  
Lotze's historical position is of much interest. Though he disclaims being a follower of [[Herbart]], his formal definition of philosophy and his conception of the object of metaphysics are similar to those of Herbart, who defines philosophy as an attempt to remodel the notions given by experience. In this endeavour he forms with Herbart an opposition to the philosophies of [[Fichte]], [[Schelling]] and [[Hegel]], which aimed at objective and absolute knowledge, and also to the criticism of Kant, which aimed at determining the validity of all human knowledge. But this formal agreement includes material differences, and the spirit which breathes in Lotze's writings is more akin to the objects and aspirations of the idealistic school than to the cold formalism of Herbart. What, however, with the idealists was an object of thought alone, the absolute, is to Lotze only inadequately definable in rigorous philosophical language; the aspirations of the human heart, the contents of our feelings and desires, the aims of art and the tenets of religious faith must be grasped in order to fill the empty idea of the absolute with meaning. These manifestations of the divine spirit again cannot be traced and understood by reducing (as Hegel did) the growth of the human mind in the individual, in society and in history to the monotonous rhythm of a speculative schematism; the essence and worth which is in them reveals itself only to the student of detail, for reality is larger and wider than philosophy; the problem, "how the one can be many," is only solved for us in the numberless examples in life and experience which surround us, for which we must retain a lifelong interest and which constitute the true field of all useful human work. This conviction of the emptiness of terms and abstract notions, and of the fulness of individual life, has enabled Lotze to combine in his writings the two courses into which German philosophical thought had been moving since the death of its great founder, Leibniz. We may define these courses by the terms esoteric and exoteric—the former the philosophy of the school, cultivated principally at the universities, trying to systematize everything and reduce all our knowledge to an intelligible principle, losing in this attempt the deeper meaning of Leibniz's philosophy; the latter the unsystematized philosophy of general culture which we find in the work of the great writers of the classical period, [[Gotthold Ephraim Lessing|Lessing]], [[Johann Joachim Winckelmann|Winckelmann]], [[Johann Wolfgang von Goethe|Goethe]], [[Friedrich Schiller|Schiller]] and [[Johann Gottfried von Herder|Herder]], all of whom expressed in some degree their indebtedness to Leibniz. Lotze can be said to have brought philosophy out of the lecture-room into the market-place of life. By understanding and combining what was great and valuable in those divided and scattered endeavours, he became the true successor of Leibniz.
+
=== Metaphysics ===
 +
[[Metaphysics]] are the underlying direction of Lotze's theoretical philosophy, and he devoted two of his major works to the subject. His desire was to reexamine the concepts inherent in the usage of language, regarding the existence of things and the connections among them, in order to make them consistent and thinkable. The further assumption, that the modified notions arrived at in this way have an objective meaning, and that they somehow correspond to the real order of the existing world which, of course, they can never actually describe, depends upon a general confidence which one must have in human reasoning powers, and in the significance of a world in which humans themselves thoughts have a due place assigned.  
  
The age in which Lotze lived and wrote in Germany was not one peculiarly fitted to appreciate the position he took up. Frequently misunderstood, yet rarely criticized, he was nevertheless greatly admired, listened to by devoted hearers and read by an increasing circle. But this circle never attained to the unity of a philosophical school.
+
Lotze opposed two common philosophical tendencies as impracticable: The attempt to establish general laws or forms, which the development of things must have obeyed, or which a Creator must have followed in the creation of a world ([[Hegel]]); and the attempt to trace the genesis of human notions and decide as to their meaning and value (modern theories of knowledge). People are surrounded by a world of many things; their notions, by which they manage correctly or incorrectly to describe, are also ready made. What remains to be done is, not to explain how such a world manages to be what it is, nor how people came to form these notions, but merely thisto expel from the circle and totality of their conceptions those abstract notions which are inconsistent and jarring, or to remodel and define them so that they may constitute a consistent and harmonious view.
  
==Works==
+
Lotze discarded as useless and untenable many favorite conceptions of the school, and many crude notions of everyday life. The course of things and the connections between them is only thinkable if people assume a plurality of existences, the reality of which (distinguished from knowledge of them) can be conceived only as a multitude of relations. This quality of standing in relation to other things is what gives to a thing its reality. The nature of this reality can neither be consistently represented as a fixed and hard substance nor as an unalterable something, but only as a fixed order of recurrence of continually changing events or impressions. Further, every attempt to think clearly what those relations are, and what people really mean if tjeu talk of a fixed order of events, also forces upon us the necessity of thinking that they cannot be merely externally strung together or moved about by some indefinable external power, such as fate or predestination. The things themselves which exist and their changing phases must have some internal connection to each other; they themselves must be active or passive, capable of doing or suffering. This would lead to the view of [[Gottfried Leibniz|Leibnitz]], that the world consists of monads, self-sufficient beings leading an inner life. But this idea involves a further conception of Leibnitz, that of a pre-established harmony, by which the Creator has taken care to arrange the life of each monad so that it agree with that of all others. That conception, according to Lotze, is neither necessary nor thoroughly intelligible. Why not interpret at once, and render intelligible, the common conception originating in natural science, of a system of laws which governs the many things? In attempting to make this conception clear and thinkable, one is forced to represent the connection of things as a universal substance, the essence of which one conceives as a system of laws which underlies everything and, in its own self, connects everything, but is imperceptible and known merely through the impressions it produces, which people call things.
*Logic, in three books: of Thought, of Investigation, and of Knowledge (1874), ed. and trans. [[B. Bosanquet]], Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1884; 2nd edition, 1887
+
 
*Metaphysics, in three books: Ontology, Cosmology, and Psychology (1879), ed. and trans. B. Bosanquet, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1884; 2nd edition, 1887.
+
A final reflection then teaches that the nature of this universal and all-pervading substance can only be imagined as something analogous to human mental life, where alone people experience the unity of a substance (which people call "self") preserved in the multitude of its (mental) states. It also becomes clear that only where such mental life really appears do people need to assign an independent existence. The purposes of everyday life, as well as those of science, are equally served if people deprive the material things outside of them of an independence, and assign to them merely a connected existence through the universal substance, by the action of which alone they can appear.
*Microcosmus: An Essay Concerning Man and His Relation to the World (1856-58, 1858-64), trans. E. Hamilton and E. E. C. Jones, Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1885; 4th edition, 1899.
+
 
*Outlines of Logic and of Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. and trans. G. T. Ladd, Boston, MA: Ginn & Co., 1887.
+
=== Historical position ===
*Outlines of Metaphysic, ed. and trans. G. T. Ladd, Boston, MA: Ginn & Co., 1884  
+
Though Lotze disclaims being a follower of [[Herbart]], his formal definition of philosophy and his conception of the object of metaphysics are similar to those of Herbart, who defines philosophy as an attempt to remodel the notions given by experience. He shared Herbart’s opposition to the philosophies of [[Fichte]], [[Schelling]], and [[Hegel]], which aimed at objective and absolute knowledge, and also to the criticism of Kant, which aimed at determining the validity of all human knowledge. However, the ideas expressed  in Lotze's writings resemble the objects and aspirations of the idealistic school more than the cold formalism of Herbart. Unlike the idealists, Lotze held that the absolute can only be inadequately defined in rigorous philosophical language; the aspirations of the human heart, the contents of our feelings and desires, the aims of art and the tenets of religious faith must be grasped in order to fill the empty idea of the absolute with meaning. These manifestations of the divine spirit again cannot be traced and understood by reducing (as Hegel did) the growth of the human mind in the individual, in society and in history to the monotonous rhythm of a predefined pattern. Reality is larger and wider than philosophy; the problem, "how the one can be many," is only solved for us in the numberless examples in life and experience which surround us, for which we must retain a lifelong interest and which constitute the true field of all useful human work.
*Outlines of a Philosophy of Religion, ed. [[F. C. Conybeare]], London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1892.
+
 
 +
This conviction of the emptiness of terms and abstract notions, and of the fullness of individual life, enabled Lotze to combine in his writings the two courses in which German philosophical thought had been moving since the death of Leibniz: The esoteric philosophy of the universities which tried to reduce all knowledge to an intelligible principle, and unsystematized philosophy of writers of the classical period, such as [[Gotthold Ephraim Lessing|Lessing]], [[Johann Joachim Winckelmann|Winckelmann]], [[Johann Wolfgang von Goethe|Goethe]], [[Friedrich Schiller|Schiller]], and [[Johann Gottfried von Herder|Herder]], all of whom expressed in some degree their indebtedness to Leibniz.
 +
 
 +
==Bibliography==
 +
*''Logic, in three books: of Thought, of Investigation, and of Knowledge'' (1874), ed. and trans. B. Bosanquet, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1884; 2nd edition, 1887
 +
*''Metaphysics'', in three books: Ontology, Cosmology, and Psychology (1879), ed. and trans. B. Bosanquet, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1884; 2nd edition, 1887.
 +
*''Microcosmus: An Essay Concerning Man and His Relation to the World'' (1856-58, 1858-64), trans. E. Hamilton and E. E. C. Jones, Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1885; 4th edition, 1899. Kessinger Publishing, 2006. ISBN 1425301207
 +
*''Outlines of Logic and of Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', ed. and trans. G. T. Ladd, Boston, MA: Ginn & Co., 1887.
 +
*''Outlines of Metaphysic,'' ed. and trans. G. T. Ladd, Boston, MA: Ginn & Co., 1884  
 +
*''Outlines of a Philosophy of Religion,'' ed. F. C. Conybeare, London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1892.
 
*“Philosophy in the Last Forty Years. First Article.” (1880) In Kleine Schriften, v. 3, ed. D. Peipers, Leipzig: S. Hirzel, 1885-91.
 
*“Philosophy in the Last Forty Years. First Article.” (1880) In Kleine Schriften, v. 3, ed. D. Peipers, Leipzig: S. Hirzel, 1885-91.
  
== Selected secondary literature==
+
==References==
*Adamson, R., 1903. ''The Development of Modern Philosophy''. Blackwood.
+
*Adamson, R. ''The Development of Modern Philosophy''. Blackwood, 1903. ISBN 1428615423
*[[Ernst Cassirer|Cassirer, E.]], 1923. ''Substance and Function''. Open Court.
+
*Cassirer, E. ''Substance and Function''. Open Court, 1923.
*Gabriel, G., 2002. "Frege, Lotze, and the Continental Roots of Early Analytic Philosophy" in E. Reck, ed., ''From Frege to Wittgenstein''. Oxford UP.
+
*Craig, E., ed. "Rudolf Hermann Lotze." In ''Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy,'' vol. 5. 839–842. Routledge, 1998.
*Gregory, F., 1977. ''Scientific Materialism in Nineteenth Century Germany''. Reidel.
+
*Gabriel, G. "Frege, Lotze, and the Continental Roots of Early Analytic Philosophy." In E. Reck, ed., ''From Frege to Wittgenstein''. Oxford University Press, 2002. ISBN 0195133269
*Hatfield, G., 1990. ''The Natural and the Normative: Theories of Spatial Perception from Kant to Helmholtz''. MIT Press.
+
*Gregory, F. ''Scientific Materialism in Nineteenth Century Germany''. Reidel, 1977. ISBN 902770760X
*Hauser, K., 2003, "Lotze and Husserl," ''Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 85'': 152-178.
+
*Hatfield, G. ''The Natural and the Normative: Theories of Spatial Perception from Kant to Helmholtz''. MIT Press, 1991. ISBN 0262080869
*James, W., 1977. ''A Pluralistic Universe''. Harvard UP.
+
*Hauser, K. "Lotze and Husserl," ''Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 85'': 152-178, 2003.
*Kusch, M., 1995. ''Psychologism''. Routledge.
+
*James, W. ''A Pluralistic Universe''. Harvard University Press, 1977.
*Lenoir, T., 1982. ''The Strategy of Life''. Reidel.
+
*Kusch, M. ''Psychologism''. Routledge, 1995.
*Milkov, N., 2000, "Lotze and the Early Cambridge Analytic Philosophy," ''Prima Philosophia 13'': 133-153.
+
*Lenoir, T.''The Strategy of Life''. Reidel, 1982.
*Morgan, M. J., 1977. ''Molyneaux's Question: Vision, Touch, and the Philosophy of Perception''. Cambridge UP.
+
*Morgan, M. J. ''Molyneaux's Question: Vision, Touch, and the Philosophy of Perception''. Cambridge University Press, 1977.
*Pierson, G., 1988, "Lotze's Concept of Value," ''Journal of Value Inquiry 22'': 115-125.
+
*Reardon, B., ed. ''Liberal Protestantism''. Stanford University Press, 1968.
*Rampersad, A., 1990. ''The Art and Imagination of W. E. B. DuBois''. Shocken.
+
*Rhees, Rush, ed. ''Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections''. Rowman and Littlefield, 1981.
*Reardon, B. (ed.), 1968. ''Liberal Protestantism''. Stanford UP.
+
*Richards, R.''The Romantic Conception of Life''. University of Chicago Press, 2002.
*[[Rush Rhees|Rhees, Rush]], ed., 1981. ''Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections''. Rowman and Littlefield.
+
*Rollinger, R.D. "Lotze on the Sensory Representation of Space." In L. Albertazzi, ed., ''The Dawn of Cognitive Science: Early European Contributors''. 103-122. Kluwer, 2001.
*Richards, R., 2002. ''The Romantic Conception of Life''. Uni. of Chicago Press.
+
*Rollinger, R.D. "Hermann Lotze on Abstraction and Platonic Ideas," ''Idealization XI: Historical Studies on Abstraction and Idealization.'' Edited by Francesco Coniglione, Roberto Poli, and Robin Rollinger, in ''Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and Humanities'', Vol. 82, 147-161. Rodopi,2004
*Rollinger, R. D., 2001, "Lotze on the Sensory Representation of Space" in L. Albertazzi, ed., ''The Dawn of Cognitive Science: Early European Contributors''. Kluwer, 103-122.
+
*Santayana, George. ''Lotze's System of Philosophy''. Edited by Paul Grimley Kuntz. Indiana University Press, 1971.
*Rollinger, R.D., 2004. "Hermann Lotze on Abstraction and Platonic Ideas", ''Idealization XI: Historical Studies on Abstraction and Idealization'', edited by Francesco Coniglione, Roberto Poli, and Robin Rollinger, in ''Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and Humanities'', Vol. 82. Rodopi, 147-161.
+
*Schnädelbach, H. 1984. ''Philosophy in Germany, 1831-1933''. Cambridge University Press, 1984.
*[[Gillian Rose|Rose, G.]], 1981. ''Hegel Contra Sociology''. London: Athalone.
+
*Willard, D. ''Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge''. Ohio University Press, 1984.
*[[George Santayana|Santayana, George]], 1971 (1889). ''Lotze's System of Philosophy''. Edited, with an introduction and Lotze bibliography, by Paul Grimley Kuntz. Indiana UP. The text of Santayana's Ph.D. thesis.
+
*Woodward, W.R. "From Association to Gestalt: The Fate of Hermann Lotze's Theory of Spatial Perception, 1846-1920." ''Isis 69:'' 572–582.
*Schnädelbach, H., 1984. ''Philosophy in Germany, 1831-1933''. Cambridge UP.
+
 
*Sluga, H., 1980. ''Gottlob Frege''. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
+
*{{1911}}
*Sullivan, D., 1991, "Frege on the Cognition of Objects," ''Philosophical Topics 19'': 245–268.
 
*-----, 1998, "Rudolf Hermann Lotze" in ''Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', vol. 5. E. Craig, ed. Routledge: 839–842.
 
*Willard, D., 1984. ''Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge''. Ohio UP.
 
*Willey, T. E., 1978. ''Back to Kant''. Wayne State UP.
 
*Woodward, W.R, 1978, "From Association to Gestalt: The Fate of Hermann Lotze's Theory of Spatial Perception, 1846-1920," ''Isis 69'': 572–582.
 
*----- & Pester, R., 1994, "From Romantic Naturphilosophie to a Theory of Scientific Method for the Medical Disciplines" in S. Poggi and M. Bossi, eds., ''Romanticism in Science''. Kluwer: 161–173.
 
  
 
== External links ==
 
== External links ==
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hermann-lotze/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry]
+
All links retrieved December 22, 2022.
 
 
==See also==
 
*{{1911}}
 
  
[[Category:1817 births|Lotze, Rudolf]]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hermann-lotze/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry].
[[Category:1881 deaths|Lotze, Rudolf]]
+
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/l/lotze.htm The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry].
[[Category:19th century philosophers|Lotze, Rudolf]]
+
*[http://hpy.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/16/1/117?ck=nck Excerpt from Medicinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele] G. E. Berrios.
[[Category:German philosophers|Lotze, Rudolf]]
+
===General philosophy sources===
[[Category:German-language philosophers|Lotze, Rudolf]]
+
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy].
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online].
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg].
  
[[de:Rudolf Hermann Lotze]]
+
[[Category:Philosophers]]
[[hu:Rudolf Hermann Lotze]]
+
[[Category:writers and poets]]
[[pl:Rudolf Hermann Lotze]]
 
[[ru:Лотце, Рудольф Герман]]
 
[[sk:Rudolf Hermann Lotze]]
 
[[sr:Рудолф Херман Лоце]]
 
  
 
{{credit|74905982}}
 
{{credit|74905982}}

Latest revision as of 16:57, 22 December 2022

Rudolf Herman Lotze (May 21, 1817 - July 1, 1881), was a preeminent German philosopher and logician during the second half of the nineteenth century. He obtained a medical degree and was unusually well versed in biology. He tried to reconcile German idealism with scientific mechanism by asserting that scientific laws and principles were incomprehensible without an underlying higher purpose, the realization of a world of goodness. He also proposed that the role of philosophy was not to discover universal principles, but to clarify and organize existing concepts and ideas into an intelligible system. Convinced of the emptiness of philosophical terms and abstract notions, he declared that ultimate reality was larger and wider than philosophy, and its unity could only be understood in terms of the multitude of human experiences and observations of everyday life.

Lotze combined the monads of Gottfried Leibniz's spheres of individual existence with the pantheism of Baruch Spinoza. He suggested that the "monads" existed within a universal substance. He taught that the human soul regards universal substance as an absolutely good being, a God of love. Lotze applied the general principles used in the investigation of inorganic phenomena to the study of the physical and mental phenomena of the human organism, in its normal and diseased states. He wrote several treatises on aesthetics. He included aesthetic values with moral values as part of the underlying tendency towards goodness which give meaning to existence.

Life

Rudolf Herman Lotze was born in Bautzen, Saxony, Germany, on May 21, 1817, the son of an army surgeon. He was educated at the gymnasium of Zittau; he wrote poetry and had an enduring love of the classical authors, translating Antigone of Sophocles into Latin verse (published when he was middle-aged). At the age of seventeen, he entered the University of Leipzig as a student of medicine, perhaps to please his father, but he also studied philosophy, psychology, physics, and mathematics under E.H. Weber, W. Volckmann, Gustav Fechner, and Christian Hermann Weisse. He was interested both in science and the idealism of Gottlieb Fichte, Friedrich von Schelling, and Georg Hegel.

Four months after receiving his doctorate in philosophy in 1838, Lotze was awarded a doctorate in medicine for his dissertation De futurae biologiae principibus philosophicis. In 1841, at the age of twenty-four, he became a junior lecturer at Leipzig. He published two short books on philosophy, Metaphysik (Leipzig, 1841) and Logik (1843). In 1844, he succeeded Johann Friedrich Herbart in the chair of philosophy at the University of Göttingen.

His two early books remained unnoticed by the reading public, and Lotze first became known to a larger circle through his Allgemeine Pathologie und Therapie als mechanische Naturwissenschaften (Leipzig, 1842, 2nd ed., 1848), the articles "Lebenskraft" (1843) and "Seele und Seelenleben" (1846) in Rud. Wagner's Handwörterbuck der Physiologie, his Allgemeine Physiologie des Korperlichen Lebens (Leipzig, 1851), and his Medizinische Psychologie oder Physiologie der Seele (Leipzig, 1852). Lotze applied the general principles used in the investigation of inorganic phenomena to the study of the physical and mental phenomena of the human organism, in its normal and diseased states. When Lotze published these works, medical science was still under the influence of Schelling's philosophy of nature, and the mechanical laws were considered to be valid only in the inorganic world. Though Lotze reiterated that his ideas did not include a solution of the philosophical question regarding the nature of mechanism, his works, published during the years when the modern school of German materialism was at its height, were counted among the literature of empirical philosophy.

This misinterpretation of his ideas induced Lotze to publish a small polemical pamphlet (Streitschriften, Leipzig, 1857), in which he corrected two mistakes: Some associated him with the materialistic school because of his opposition to Hegel's formalism, while others regarded him as a follower of Herbart. Lotze denied that he belonged to the school of Herbart, though he incorporated the monadology of Leibniz in his views. When Lotze wrote these explanations, he had already published the first volume of his Mikrokosmus (vol. i. 1856, vol. ii. 1858, vol. iii. 1864). In many passages of his works on pathology, physiology, and psychology, Lotze had distinctly stated that the method of research which he advocated did not give an explanation of the phenomena of life and mind, but only the means of observing and connecting them together. He emphasized that by studying the macrocosm of the universe, it is possible to acquire data necessary for deciding what meaning attaches to the existence of the microcosmic world of human life.

As professor of philosophy at Göttingen, Lotze delivered annual lectures on psychology and logic (the latter included a survey of all philosophical research, under the title Encyclopädie der Philosophie), and at longer intervals, lectures on metaphysics, philosophy of nature, philosophy of art, philosophy of religion, and occasionally on the history of philosophy and ethics. During these lectures he developed his ideas in relation to each of these subjects, and during the last decade of his life he embodied the substance of those courses in his System der Philosophie. Only two volumes were published, Vol. i. Logik (1st ed., Leipzig, 1874, 2nd ed., 1880) and Vol ii. Metaphysik (1879). The third and concluding volume, which was to treat in a more condensed form the principal problems of practical philosophy, of philosophy of art and religion, never appeared. A small pamphlet on psychology, containing the last form in which he had begun to treat the subject in his lectures, was published by his son.

In 1881, Lotze joined the faculty at Berlin but, after three months, died of a chest infection on July 1, 1881.

Thought and works

Lotze was a preeminent figure in German academic philosophy during the second half of the nineteenth century. He recognized the validity of the methods of mechanistic science but perceived the limitations of mechanism in explaining human consciousness and in providing an underlying justification for the existence of mankind and the universe. He made ethics the starting point of his philosophy, which he called teleogical idealism, asserting that the causes and effects observed in nature were incomprehensible without an underlying purpose, the realization of a world of goodness. Lotze believed that philosophy should be rooted in the natural sciences, since human beings and inanimate objects are subject to the same natural laws. However, he held that knowledge was acquired through observation and experimentation; reality could not be deduced from laws and principles, and the purpose of philosophy was to analyze and organize the concepts that came from scientific observation. Physiology and other natural sciences could contribute to the explanation of human behavior, but Lotze felt that certain metaphysical concepts like “vital force,” which were still popular in biology during the 1800s, were not scientific enough and should be done away with.

Mechanism was the unalterable connection of every phenomenon a with other phenomena b, c, d, either following or preceding it; mechanism was the inexorable form into which the events of this world are cast, and by which they are connected.

Lotze believed that humanity was distinguishable from animals by the uniqueness of his mind; the development and history of humankind cannot be regarded as a mechanical scientific process. Humanity, because of its mind, brings unity to existence through his ideas and his ethical values. “Wholes” in nature are the product of the mind of humans.

Lotze’s theory of space perception was an important contribution to philosophy.

Aesthetics was a favorite study of Lotze's, perhaps because of his own artistic temperament. He wrote several essays on aesthetics in light of the leading ideas of his philosophy.

Mikrokosmus (1856-1864)

The three volumes of Mikrokosmus were a review of anthropology, beginning with the human frame, the soul, and their relationship in life; advancing to the human mind and the course of the world; and concluding with history, progress, and the connection among all things. It concluded with the same idea which Lotze had expressed in his earliest work, Metaphysik, presented as the culmination of the preceding chapters, and as a framework for understanding his view of the existence of man, physical and mental, as an individual and a society. In every realm of observation these three distinct regions can be found; the region of facts, the region of laws and the region of standards of value. These three regions are separate only in human thoughts, not in reality. In order to comprehend reality, one must understand that the higher standards of moral and aesthetic value are being realized, by means of laws, in the realm of facts. Such a reality can only become intelligible through the existence of a personal Deity who, in the creation and preservation of the universe, has voluntarily established certain forms and laws, through the natural operation of which His purpose is realized.

Definition of philosophy

Lotze established two points in his exposition of logic: The existence in the human mind of certain laws and forms, according to which people connect the data supplied to them by their senses; and secondly, the fact that logical thought cannot be usefully employed without the assumption of a further set of connections, not logically necessary, but assumed to exist between the data of experience and observation. These connections, of a real, not a formal character, come from the various sciences and from the usage and culture of everyday life. Language has crystallized them into certain definite notions and expressions, without which one cannot proceed a single step, but which people have accepted without knowing their exact meaning, much less their origin. Consequently, the special sciences and the wisdom of common life entangle themselves easily and frequently in contradictions. A problem of a purely formal character thus presents itself: How to bring unity and harmony into the scattered thoughts of general culture, to trace them to their primary assumptions and follow them into their ultimate consequences, to connect them all together, to remodel, curtail or amplify them, so as to remove their apparent contradictions, and to combine them in a united, harmonious view of things. More especially, how do we investigate those concepts which form the initial assumptions of the several sciences, and fix the limits of their applicability? This is the formal definition of philosophy.

Whether a harmonious conception gained in this manner will represent more than an agreement among our thoughts; whether it will represent the real connection among things and thus possess objective, and not merely subjective, value, cannot be decided at the outset. It is unwarranted to start with the expectation that everything in the world should be explained by one principle, and it is a needless restriction of the means to expect unity of method. Philosophical investigations cannot start with an inquiry into the nature of human thought and its capacity to attain objective knowledge, because in that case we would be actually using the instrument whose usefulness we were trying to determine. The objective value of any view we gain will be proved by the degree to which it succeeds in assigning to every element of culture its due position; or in which it is able to appreciate and combine different and apparently opposite tendencies and interests; or in the justice with which it weighs human manifold desires and aspirations and balances them in due proportions, refusing to sacrifice to a one-sided principle any truth or conviction which experience has proven to be useful and necessary.

Philosophical investigations will then naturally divide themselves into three parts. The first deals with the inevitable forms in which people are obliged to think about things, if they think at all (metaphysics). The second is devoted to the application of the results of metaphysics to the region of facts, especially to the regions of external and mental phenomena (cosmology and psychology). The third deals with the standards of value from which people pronounce their aesthetic or ethical approval or disapproval. In each area one must aim for views which are clear and consistent within themselves; secondly, one shall wish to form some general idea of how laws, facts, and standards of value may be combined in one comprehensive view. Considerations of this latter kind will naturally present themselves in the two great departments of cosmology and psychology, or they may be delegated to an independent research under the name of religious philosophy.

Metaphysics

Metaphysics are the underlying direction of Lotze's theoretical philosophy, and he devoted two of his major works to the subject. His desire was to reexamine the concepts inherent in the usage of language, regarding the existence of things and the connections among them, in order to make them consistent and thinkable. The further assumption, that the modified notions arrived at in this way have an objective meaning, and that they somehow correspond to the real order of the existing world which, of course, they can never actually describe, depends upon a general confidence which one must have in human reasoning powers, and in the significance of a world in which humans themselves thoughts have a due place assigned.

Lotze opposed two common philosophical tendencies as impracticable: The attempt to establish general laws or forms, which the development of things must have obeyed, or which a Creator must have followed in the creation of a world (Hegel); and the attempt to trace the genesis of human notions and decide as to their meaning and value (modern theories of knowledge). People are surrounded by a world of many things; their notions, by which they manage correctly or incorrectly to describe, are also ready made. What remains to be done is, not to explain how such a world manages to be what it is, nor how people came to form these notions, but merely this—to expel from the circle and totality of their conceptions those abstract notions which are inconsistent and jarring, or to remodel and define them so that they may constitute a consistent and harmonious view.

Lotze discarded as useless and untenable many favorite conceptions of the school, and many crude notions of everyday life. The course of things and the connections between them is only thinkable if people assume a plurality of existences, the reality of which (distinguished from knowledge of them) can be conceived only as a multitude of relations. This quality of standing in relation to other things is what gives to a thing its reality. The nature of this reality can neither be consistently represented as a fixed and hard substance nor as an unalterable something, but only as a fixed order of recurrence of continually changing events or impressions. Further, every attempt to think clearly what those relations are, and what people really mean if tjeu talk of a fixed order of events, also forces upon us the necessity of thinking that they cannot be merely externally strung together or moved about by some indefinable external power, such as fate or predestination. The things themselves which exist and their changing phases must have some internal connection to each other; they themselves must be active or passive, capable of doing or suffering. This would lead to the view of Leibnitz, that the world consists of monads, self-sufficient beings leading an inner life. But this idea involves a further conception of Leibnitz, that of a pre-established harmony, by which the Creator has taken care to arrange the life of each monad so that it agree with that of all others. That conception, according to Lotze, is neither necessary nor thoroughly intelligible. Why not interpret at once, and render intelligible, the common conception originating in natural science, of a system of laws which governs the many things? In attempting to make this conception clear and thinkable, one is forced to represent the connection of things as a universal substance, the essence of which one conceives as a system of laws which underlies everything and, in its own self, connects everything, but is imperceptible and known merely through the impressions it produces, which people call things.

A final reflection then teaches that the nature of this universal and all-pervading substance can only be imagined as something analogous to human mental life, where alone people experience the unity of a substance (which people call "self") preserved in the multitude of its (mental) states. It also becomes clear that only where such mental life really appears do people need to assign an independent existence. The purposes of everyday life, as well as those of science, are equally served if people deprive the material things outside of them of an independence, and assign to them merely a connected existence through the universal substance, by the action of which alone they can appear.

Historical position

Though Lotze disclaims being a follower of Herbart, his formal definition of philosophy and his conception of the object of metaphysics are similar to those of Herbart, who defines philosophy as an attempt to remodel the notions given by experience. He shared Herbart’s opposition to the philosophies of Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel, which aimed at objective and absolute knowledge, and also to the criticism of Kant, which aimed at determining the validity of all human knowledge. However, the ideas expressed in Lotze's writings resemble the objects and aspirations of the idealistic school more than the cold formalism of Herbart. Unlike the idealists, Lotze held that the absolute can only be inadequately defined in rigorous philosophical language; the aspirations of the human heart, the contents of our feelings and desires, the aims of art and the tenets of religious faith must be grasped in order to fill the empty idea of the absolute with meaning. These manifestations of the divine spirit again cannot be traced and understood by reducing (as Hegel did) the growth of the human mind in the individual, in society and in history to the monotonous rhythm of a predefined pattern. Reality is larger and wider than philosophy; the problem, "how the one can be many," is only solved for us in the numberless examples in life and experience which surround us, for which we must retain a lifelong interest and which constitute the true field of all useful human work.

This conviction of the emptiness of terms and abstract notions, and of the fullness of individual life, enabled Lotze to combine in his writings the two courses in which German philosophical thought had been moving since the death of Leibniz: The esoteric philosophy of the universities which tried to reduce all knowledge to an intelligible principle, and unsystematized philosophy of writers of the classical period, such as Lessing, Winckelmann, Goethe, Schiller, and Herder, all of whom expressed in some degree their indebtedness to Leibniz.

Bibliography

  • Logic, in three books: of Thought, of Investigation, and of Knowledge (1874), ed. and trans. B. Bosanquet, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1884; 2nd edition, 1887
  • Metaphysics, in three books: Ontology, Cosmology, and Psychology (1879), ed. and trans. B. Bosanquet, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1884; 2nd edition, 1887.
  • Microcosmus: An Essay Concerning Man and His Relation to the World (1856-58, 1858-64), trans. E. Hamilton and E. E. C. Jones, Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1885; 4th edition, 1899. Kessinger Publishing, 2006. ISBN 1425301207
  • Outlines of Logic and of Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. and trans. G. T. Ladd, Boston, MA: Ginn & Co., 1887.
  • Outlines of Metaphysic, ed. and trans. G. T. Ladd, Boston, MA: Ginn & Co., 1884
  • Outlines of a Philosophy of Religion, ed. F. C. Conybeare, London: Swan Sonnenschein & Co., 1892.
  • “Philosophy in the Last Forty Years. First Article.” (1880) In Kleine Schriften, v. 3, ed. D. Peipers, Leipzig: S. Hirzel, 1885-91.

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Adamson, R. The Development of Modern Philosophy. Blackwood, 1903. ISBN 1428615423
  • Cassirer, E. Substance and Function. Open Court, 1923.
  • Craig, E., ed. "Rudolf Hermann Lotze." In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol. 5. 839–842. Routledge, 1998.
  • Gabriel, G. "Frege, Lotze, and the Continental Roots of Early Analytic Philosophy." In E. Reck, ed., From Frege to Wittgenstein. Oxford University Press, 2002. ISBN 0195133269
  • Gregory, F. Scientific Materialism in Nineteenth Century Germany. Reidel, 1977. ISBN 902770760X
  • Hatfield, G. The Natural and the Normative: Theories of Spatial Perception from Kant to Helmholtz. MIT Press, 1991. ISBN 0262080869
  • Hauser, K. "Lotze and Husserl," Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 85: 152-178, 2003.
  • James, W. A Pluralistic Universe. Harvard University Press, 1977.
  • Kusch, M. Psychologism. Routledge, 1995.
  • Lenoir, T.The Strategy of Life. Reidel, 1982.
  • Morgan, M. J. Molyneaux's Question: Vision, Touch, and the Philosophy of Perception. Cambridge University Press, 1977.
  • Reardon, B., ed. Liberal Protestantism. Stanford University Press, 1968.
  • Rhees, Rush, ed. Ludwig Wittgenstein: Personal Recollections. Rowman and Littlefield, 1981.
  • Richards, R.The Romantic Conception of Life. University of Chicago Press, 2002.
  • Rollinger, R.D. "Lotze on the Sensory Representation of Space." In L. Albertazzi, ed., The Dawn of Cognitive Science: Early European Contributors. 103-122. Kluwer, 2001.
  • Rollinger, R.D. "Hermann Lotze on Abstraction and Platonic Ideas," Idealization XI: Historical Studies on Abstraction and Idealization. Edited by Francesco Coniglione, Roberto Poli, and Robin Rollinger, in Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and Humanities, Vol. 82, 147-161. Rodopi,2004
  • Santayana, George. Lotze's System of Philosophy. Edited by Paul Grimley Kuntz. Indiana University Press, 1971.
  • Schnädelbach, H. 1984. Philosophy in Germany, 1831-1933. Cambridge University Press, 1984.
  • Willard, D. Logic and the Objectivity of Knowledge. Ohio University Press, 1984.
  • Woodward, W.R. "From Association to Gestalt: The Fate of Hermann Lotze's Theory of Spatial Perception, 1846-1920." Isis 69: 572–582.
  • This article incorporates text from the Encyclopædia Britannica Eleventh Edition, a publication now in the public domain.

External links

All links retrieved December 22, 2022.

General philosophy sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.