Difference between revisions of "Naturalistic fallacy" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
m ({{Contracted}})
Line 1: Line 1:
 
{{Contracted}}
 
{{Contracted}}
[[Image:GEMoore.jpg|thumb|right|200px|George Edward Moore]]
 
  
The [[naturalistic fallacy]] is an alleged [[logical fallacy]], delineated by [[Britain|British]] [[Philosophy|philosopher]] [[George Edward Moore|G. E. Moore]] in his seminal '''''Principia Ethica''''' (1903). Moore stated that a naturalistic fallacy was committed whenever a philosopher attempts to prove a claim about ethics by appealing to a ''definition'' of the term "good" in terms of one or more ''natural'' properties (such as "pleasant", "more evolved", "desired", etc.).
+
The <b>naturalistic fallacy</b> is an alleged [[fallacy]] of [[Ethics|moral]] reasoning.  The British philosopher George Edward Moore [1873-1958] introduces the naturalistic fallacy in his seminal work [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/ Principia Ethica (1903)]. Although the naturalistic fallacy began with Moore, it has been revised over the years in a sub-field of [[ethics]] known as “metaethics”, which is the study of the language, [[metaphysics]], and [[epistemology]] of [[ethics]].
  
The naturalistic fallacy is related to, and often confused with, the [[is-ought problem]] (as formulated by, for example, [[David Hume]]). As a result, the term is sometimes used loosely to describe arguments that claim to draw ethical conclusions from natural facts.
+
==Moore’s Naturalistic Fallacy==
  
Alternately, the phrase "naturalistic fallacy" is used to refer to the claim that what is natural is inherently good or right, and that what is unnatural is bad or wrong (see "[[Appeal to nature]]").
+
The naturalistic fallacy is the [[fallacy]] of attempting to define evaluative concepts with descriptive concepts (Pence 2000, 37).  The naturalistic fallacy is related to but is not identical with the “is-ought fallacy”, which is the fallacy of drawing evaluative conclusions from descriptive premises ([[David Hume|Hume [1739] 1969]]).
  
== Moore's discussion ==
+
===Hume’s Is-Ought Fallacy===
  
Moore's argument in ''Principia Ethica'' is (among other things) a defence of [[ethical non-naturalism]]; he argues that the term "good" (in the sense of [[intrinsic value]]) is ''indefinable'', because it names a simple, non-natural property. It is, rather, "one of those innumerable objects of thought which are themselves incapable of definition, because they are the ultimate terms by reference to which whatever ''is'' capable of definition must be defined" ([http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.10#s10p1 ''Principia Ethica'' § 10 ¶ 1]). By contrast, many ethical philosophers have tried to prove some of their claims about ethics by appealing to an [[analysis (philosophy)|analysis]] of the ''meaning'' of the term "good"; they held, that is, that "good" can be defined in terms of one or more ''natural'' properties which we already understand (such as "pleasure", in the case of [[hedonism|hedonists]], or "survival", in the case of [[evolutionary ethics]]).  
+
The Scottish philosopher [[David Hume|David Hume [1711-1776]]] discovered the is-ought fallacy and reported it in the volume labeled ‘Of Morals’ in his classic text <I>A Treatise of Hume Nature</I> in 1739. An example of the is-ought fallacy is concluding that gay marriage <I>ought</I> to be illegal in [[United States|America]] because there <I>is</I> a consensus among the [[United States|American]] people that gay marriage ought to be illegal. The fallacy here should be obvious since an analogous argument could show that interracial marriage should have been illegal in Alabama in 1999 before Alabama voters repealed [http://archives.cnn.com/2000/ALLPOLITICS/stories/11/07/alabama.interracial/ the Alabama gay marriage ban]in 2000.
Moore coined the term "naturalistic fallacy" to describe arguments of this form; he explains (in [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.12 § 12]) that the fallacy involved is an instance of a more general type of fallacy, which he leaves unnamed, but which we might call the "definitional fallacy". The fallacy is committed whenever a statement to the effect that some object has a simple indefinable property is misunderstood as a definition that gives the meaning of the simple indefinable property:
 
  
{{quotation|That "pleased" does not mean "having the sensation of red", or anything else whatever, does not prevent us from understanding what it does mean. It is enough for us to know that "pleased" does mean "having the sensation of pleasure", and though pleasure is absolutely indefinable, though pleasure is pleasure and nothing else whatever, yet we feel no difficulty in saying that we are pleased. The reason is, of course, that when I say "I am pleased", I do not mean that "I" am the same thing as "having pleasure". And similarly no difficulty need be found in my saying that "pleasure is good" and yet not meaning that "pleasure" is the same thing as "good", that pleasure ''means'' good, and that good ''means'' pleasure. If I were to imagine that when I said "I am pleased", I meant that I was exactly the same thing as "pleased", I should not indeed call that a naturalistic fallacy, although it would be the same fallacy as I have called naturalistic with reference to Ethics.|G. E. Moore|[http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.12 PE § 12]}}
+
The is-ought fallacy, as [[David Hume|Hume]] would put it, lies in the [[Logic|logical]] gap between ought-statements and is-statements.  Is-statements (also known as “descriptions”) are claims about what there is (e.g. sometimes people lie). Ought-statements (also known as “prescriptions” or “evaluations”) are claims about what should be (e.g. people should always tell the truth). Is-statements are exemplified in the sciences, whereas ought-statements are exemplified in ethics and aesthetics.
  
The point here is connected with Moore's understanding of properties and the terms that stand for them. Moore holds ([http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.7 §7]) that properties are either complexes of simple properties, or else irreducibly simple. The meaning of terms that stand for complex properties can be given by using terms for their constituent properties in a ''definition''; simple properties cannot be defined, because they are made up only of themselves and there are no simpler constituents to refer to. Besides "good" and "pleasure", Moore also offers colour terms as an example of indefinable terms; thus if one wants to understand the meaning of "yellow", one has to be ''shown'' examples of it; it will do no good to read the dictionary and learn that "yellow" names the colour of egg yolks and ripe lemons, or that "yellow" names the primary colour between green and orange on the spectrum, or that the perception of yellow is stimulated by electromagnetic radiation with a wavelength of between 570 and 590 nanometers. It is true that yellow is all these things, that "egg yolks are yellow" and "the colour perceived when the retina is stimulated by electromagnetic radiation with a wavelength of between 570 and 590 nanometers is yellow" are true statements. But the statements do not give the meaning of the term "yellow", and (Moore argues) to confuse them with a definition of "yellow" would be to commit the same fallacy that is committed when "Pleasure is good" is confused with a definition of "good".
+
At any rate, Hume claims that inferring ought-statements from is-statements is [[Deduction|deductively]] invalid. Thus no amount of descriptive facts force evaluative claims onto us. This means that we can always have evaluative reasons for interpreting descriptive facts in one way versus another. For example, the fact that most Americans disapprove of gay marriage could indicate that most Americans cannot separate their religious beliefs from their political stance.  But then the fact that most Americans disapprove of gay marriage does not support a law against gay marriage due to the [http://www.archives.gov/national-archives-experience/charters/bill_of_rights_transcript.html/ First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution], which states that among other things, “Congress shall make no law respecting the establishment of religion”.
  
Moore goes on to explain that he pays special attention to the fallacy as it occurs in ethics, and identifies that specific form of the fallacy as ‘naturalistic’, because (1) it is so commonly committed in ethics, and (2) because committing the fallacy in ethics involves confusing a ''natural'' object (such as survival or pleasure) with ''goodness'', something that is (he argues) ''not'' a natural object. However, it's important to note that in spite of his rhetorical focus on the ‘naturalistic’ nature of the fallacy, Moore was not any more satisfied with theories that attempted to define ''goodness'' in terms of ''non-natural'' properties than he was with naturalistic theories; indeed, the basis of his criticism of “Metaphysical Ethics” in [http://fair-use.org/principia-ethica/chapter-iv Chapter IV of ''Principia Ethica''] is that theories which define 'good' in terms of [[supernatural]] or [[metaphysics|metaphysical]] properties rest on the ''very same fallacy'' as naturalistic theories ([http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.69 §69]). The target of Moore's discussion of the "naturalistic fallacy" is ''reductionism'' at least as much as it is ''naturalism'' specifically, and the important lesson, for Moore, is that the meaning of the term "good" and the nature of the property ''goodness'' are irreducibly ''[[sui generis]]''.
+
===The Connection Between the Is-Ought Fallacy and the Naturalistic Fallacy===
  
=== The Open Question Argument ===
+
In order to get around Hume’s is-ought fallacy, some eighteenth and nineteenth century moral philosophers simply <b>defined</b> goodness in terms of natural properties, much like scientists define natural things in terms of natural properties (e.g. electricity is moving charge).  The [[Utilitarianism|utilitarians]] [[Jeremy Bentham|Jeremy Bentham [1748-1832]]] and [[John Stuart Mill|John Stuart Mill [1806-1873]]] are prime examples of such “naturalistic” philosophers.  Actually, in metaethics, a philosopher who believes that moral concepts can be defined with natural concepts is called a "moral naturalist" and a supporter of "moral naturalism". 
  
Moore's argument for the indefinability of “good” (and thus for the fallaciousness of the “naturalistic fallacy”) is often called the Open Question Argument; it is presented in [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.13 §13 of ''Principia Ethica'']. The argument hinges on the nature of statements such as "Anything that is pleasant is also good" and the possibility of asking questions such as "Is it ''good'' that x is pleasant?" According to Moore, these questions are ''open'' and these statements are ''significant''; and they will remain so no matter what is substituted for "pleasure". Moore concludes from this that any analysis of value is bound to fail. In other words, if value could be analyzed, then such questions and statements would be trivial and obvious. Since they are anything but trivial and obvious, value must be indefinable. Critics of Moore's arguments sometimes claim that he is appealing to general puzzles concerning analysis (cf. [[the paradox of analysis]]), rather than revealing anything special about value. Other responses appeal to the [[Frege|Fregean]] distinction between [[sense and reference]], allowing that value concepts are special and ''sui generis'', but insisting that value properties are nothing but natural properties (this strategy is similar to that taken by [[physicalism|non-reductive materialists]] in [[philosophy of mind]]).
+
At any rate, these early [[Utilitarianism|utilitarians]] believed that the moral term ‘good’ can be defined entirely by the phrase ‘whatever produces the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of sentient beings’, although Bentham ([1823] 1907) and Mill ([1861] 2001) disagreed about what sort of pleasure should be emphasized.  Problem solved right?  Not quite.
  
An important response to the open question argument by contemporary ethical naturalists (e.g., Peter Railton) is to understand a claim like "The Good is pleasure" as an a posteriori identity claim on a par with "Water is H2O". The question "This is H2O but is it water?" is intelligible and so, in that limited sense, whether or not water is H2O is an open question. But that does not lead us to conclude that water is not H2O. "Water is H2O" is an identity claim that is known to be true a posteriori (i.e., it was discovered via empirical investigation). The fact that this truth is not known merely by conceptually analyzing the term "water" (and the corresponding fact that the aforementioned open question is at least intelligible) does not falsify the identity claim. Similarly, an ethical naturalist might argue that, say, "The Good is pleasure" is an a posteriori identity claim whose truth is discovered empirically. That we can intelligibly ask "I see that this is pleasant, but is it good?" simply means that we cannot conceptually analyze "good" in terms of "pleasure". It does not mean that goodness is not the same thing as pleasure. "Good" and "pleasant" might pick out (refer to) the same thing. Whether or not this is the case is a matter of empirical investigation, and not conceptual analysis, according to this kind of ethical naturalist.
+
G.E. Moore claimed that the mere act of defining moral concepts with natural concepts was a [[fallacy]], the naturalistic fallacy.  Moore used the phenomenal quality (sometimes called ‘qualia’) Yellow to make his point; and thus implicitly claimed that moral qualities were analogous to or were a sort of qualia.  Moore argued that scientists can attempt to define yellow with a naturalistic description—such as ‘light with approximately 600 nm wavelength’ (McMurry and Fay 1995, 147)—but any such definition would not capture <I>what</I> yellow is. In other words, no definition using natural concepts could capture the essential properties of yellowness.  In Moore’s words…
 +
<blockquote>
 +
Consider yellow, for example. We may try to define it, by describing its physical equivalent; we may state what kind of light-vibrations must stimulate the normal eye, in order that we may perceive it. But a moment’s reflection is sufficient to shew that those light-vibrations are not themselves what we mean by yellow. <I>They</I> are not what we perceive. Indeed, we should never have been able to discover their existence, unless we had first been struck by the patent difference of quality between the different colours. The most we can be entitled to say of those vibrations is that they are what corresponds in space to the yellow which we actually perceive ([http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.10#s10p2 ''Principia Ethica'' § 10  2]).
 +
</blockquote>
 +
The same goes for moral concepts according to Moore.  Defining <i>the good</i> as what is produces the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of sentient beings in fact fails to capture what is good although it might track it.  In Moore’s words…
 +
<blockquote>
 +
Yet a mistake of this simple kind has commonly been made about good. It may be true that all things which are good are <I>also</I> something else, just as it is true that all things which are yellow produce a certain kind of vibration in the light. And it is a fact, that Ethics aims at discovering what are those other properties belonging to all things which are good. But far too many philosophers have thought that when they named those other properties they were actually defining good; that these properties, in fact, were simply not other, but absolutely and entirely the same with goodness. This view I propose to call the naturalistic fallacy and of it I shall now endeavour to dispose. ([http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.10#s10p3 ''Principia Ethica'' § 10  3]).
 +
</blockquote>
 +
Thus Hume’s is-ought fallacy was reborn with Moore’s introduction of the naturalistic fallacy. But how exactly did Moore prove that the naturalistic fallacy was a fallacy?
  
== Other uses ==
+
===The Open-Question Argument===
=== Appeal to nature ===
 
Some people use the phrase "naturalistic fallacy" or "[[Appeal to nature]]" to characterise inferences of the form "This behaviour is natural; therefore, this behaviour is morally acceptable" or "This behaviour is unnatural; therefore, this behaviour is morally unacceptable". Such inferences are common in discussions of [[homosexuality]] and [[cloning]], to take two examples. While such inferences may indeed be fallacious, it is important to realise that Moore is not concerned with them. He is instead concerned with the [[semantic]] and metaphysical underpinnings of ethics.
 
  
=== The is-ought problem ===
+
Moore convinced his contemporaries that the naturalistic fallacy was a fallacy by an argument called ‘The Open-Question Argument’ and is presented in [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/s.13 §13 of ''Principia Ethica''].  According to Moore, a term is defined just in case we provide necessary and sufficient conditions for using the term.  Moore’s was the traditional view of definition; it was developed by [[Aristotle|Aristotle [384-322 B.C.E.]]] as a way to describe the natural essences that things had.  As it happens, terms that are defined in this traditional way form closed questions with their definitions. 
The term "naturalistic fallacy" is also sometimes used to describe the deduction of an "ought" from an "is" (the [[Is-ought problem]]), and has inspired the use of mutually reinforcing terminology which describes the converse (deducing an "is" from an "ought") either as the "reverse naturalistic fallacy" or the "moralistic fallacy". An example of a naturalistic fallacy in this sense would be to conclude [[Social Darwinism]] from the theory of [[evolution]] by [[natural selection]], and of the reverse naturalistic fallacy to argue that the immorality of [[survival of the fittest]] implies the theory of evolution is false.
+
 
 +
For example, since ‘bachelor’ is defined as ‘unmarried man’ the following is a closed and thus nonsensical question: I know he is a bachelor but is he unmarried and a man?  Moore’s insight was seeing that terms which were not defined by a certain phrase formed <I>open</I> questions, and naturalistic definitions of moral concepts fell within this category. 
 +
 
 +
For example, Moore saw it to be a completely open question to ask: I know she is doing what produces the greatest pleasure for the greatest number of sentient beings, but is she doing something good?  Particularly, endorsing [[Slavery|American slavery]] in the eighteenth century would have produced the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of American people (since American whites outnumbered American blacks in the eighteenth century), however it seems far from obvious that endorsing any sort of [[slavery]] could ever be good.
 +
 
 +
For this reason Moore rejected moral naturalism and proposed "moral intuitionism" in its place.  This philosophical doctrine claims that moral terms are indefinable and rather we understand moral concepts through moral intuition.
 +
 
 +
==Is the Naturalistic Fallacy Really a Fallacy?==
 +
 
 +
Despite its intuitive appeal, several philosophers have directly or indirectly attacked the naturalistic fallacy.  To be sure, the naturalistic fallacy rests on two major and controversial assumptions.  First, it assumes that moral concepts must be sharply defined with necessary and sufficient conditions.  Second, it assumes that a concept’s meaning lies in its description instead of its reference.  However, philosophers have questioned both of these assumptions in the philosophy of language over the course of the twentieth century.
 +
 
 +
===Must Definitions Be Sharp?===
 +
Richard Boyd (1988) questions whether moral terms must have sharp definitions in order to be defined.  In the end he discovers that moral terms can have what he calls “homeostatic cluster definitions”, which are vaguely defined terms using criteria that are neither necessary or sufficient.  In fact, Boyd (1988) argues that cluster definitions are commonplace in human languages.  He uses biological [[species]] terms (e.g. ‘Homo sapiens’) as an example
 +
 
 +
Thus the fact that a moral term and its naturalistic definition do not form a closed question does not imply that defining moral concepts with natural concepts is a fallacy, since moral concepts could be vaguely and imprecisely defined homeostatic cluster concepts.  In Boyd’s words:
 +
<blockquote>
 +
Similarly, consider the objection that a moral realist must hold that goodness is a natural property, and thus commit the “naturalistic fallacy” of maintaining that moral terms possess analytic definitions in, say, physical terms.  The moral realist may choose to agree that goodness is probably a physical property but deny that it has any analytic definition whatsoever (Boyd 1988, 199).
 +
</blockquote>
 +
The first philosopher to question whether definitions needed to be sharp was [[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Ludwig Wittgenstein [1889-1951]]] who in 1951 proposed family resemblance concepts as a vague alternative to sharply-defined concepts in his classic text <I>Philosophical Investigations</I>.  Although [[Ludwig Wittgenstein|Wittgenstein ([1951] 2001)]] suggested that moral concepts were family resemblance concepts, he did not develop a detailed philosophical theory on the issue like Boyd.
 +
 
 +
===Must Definitions Be Descriptions?===
 +
 
 +
Even more important in twentieth-century philosophy of language was the proposal of an alternative theory on the meaning of meaning (or the definition of definition).  Since [[Aristotle]], philosophers have thought that the meaning of a word lies in a description of it using other words.  For example, a bachelor is an unmarried man.  However, Saul Kripke (1972) and Hilary Putnam (1973) offered a different view on the meaning of meaning.  They claimed that the meaning of a term (e.g. a name) could be its referent instead of its description.  The favorite example for philosophers in this camp is [[water]] is H<sub>2</sub>O.
 +
 
 +
We need not delve into the reasons for why some philosophers believe in the referential theory of meaning in order to present it as an alternative way to understand meaning.  Thus naturalistic philosophers can challenge the naturalistic fallacy in a second way; they can reject the naturalistic fallacy on the grounds that moral terms can be defined referentially instead of descriptively (Boyd 1988).
 +
 
 +
===Hope for the Naturalistic Fallacy===
 +
 
 +
Despite these sophisticated challenges for the naturalistic fallacy achieving the status of a legitimate fallacy in moral reasoning, we can still point out how it highlights fallacious reasoning in some form. 
 +
 
 +
First, someone who believes in the descriptivist theory of meaning and that moral concepts have sharp definitions certainly commits the naturalistic fallacy if she commits the is-ought fallacy.  Thus the naturalistic fallacy appears to be a legitimate fallacy for ordinary people who engage in certain ordinary moral reasoning.
 +
 
 +
The big question is whether experts in moral philosophy (e.g. meta-ethicists) are able to commit the naturalistic fallacy if their theories on language are sophisticated enough.  However, the answer to this question is uncertain and is an active area of research in contemporary metaethics.
 +
 
 +
==See also==
 +
 
 +
*[[Fallacy]]
  
 
==References==
 
==References==
Moore, George Edward, [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica ''Principia Ethica''] (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903).
 
  
==See also==
+
*Bentham, Jeremy. [http://www.la.utexas.edu/labyrinth/ipml/index.html <i>Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation</i>] (Oxford: Oxford University Press, [1823] 1907).
*[[Appeal to tradition]]
+
*Boyd, Richard. (1988). “How to Be a Moral Realist,” in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (ed.), <I>Essays on Moral Realism</I>. (pp. 181-228). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
*[[Appeal to novelty]]
+
*Hume, David. ([1739] 1969). <I>A Treatise of Human Nature,</I> ed. Ernest C. Mossner. Middlesex: Penguin.
*[[Definist fallacy]]
+
*Kripke, Saul A. (1972). <i>Naming and Necessity</i>. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
*[[Fact-value distinction]]
+
*McMurray, John, and Fay, Robert C. (1995). <I>Chemistry</I>. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
*[[Meta-ethics]]
+
*Mill, John Stuart. ([1861] 2001). <I>Utilitarianism</I> (George Sher, ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.
*[[Naturalism (philosophy)|Philosophical naturalism]]
+
*Moore, George Edward, [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica ''Principia Ethica''] (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903).
*[[Value theory]]
+
*Pence, Gregory. (2000). <I>A Dictionary of Common Philosophical Terms</I>. New York: McGraw-Hill.
*[[Norm (philosophy)]]
+
*Putnam, Hilary. (1973). Meaning and Reference. <i>Journal of Philosophy</i> 70(19): 699-711.
*[[Appeal to nature]]
+
*Wittgenstein, Ludwig. ([1951] 2001). <I>Philosophical Investigations</I> (G.E.M. Anscombe, ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.
  
 
==External links==
 
==External links==
  
 +
*[http://www.la.utexas.edu/labyrinth/ipml/index.html Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation]
 
* [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/ Principia Ethica]
 
* [http://fair-use.org/g-e-moore/principia-ethica/ Principia Ethica]
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-non-naturalism/ Moral Non-Naturalism] (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
+
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-non-naturalism/ Moral Non-Naturalism entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore/ G.E. Moore] (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
+
* [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore/ G.E. Moore entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
 
 +
==General Philosophy Sources==
 +
 
 +
*[http://plato.stanford.edu/ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.iep.utm.edu/ The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]
 +
*[http://www.epistemelinks.com/  Philosophy Sources on Internet EpistemeLinks]
 +
*[http://www.earlham.edu/~peters/gpi/index.htm Guide to Philosophy on the Internet]
 +
*[http://www.bu.edu/wcp/PaidArch.html Paideia Project Online]
 +
*[http://www.gutenberg.org/ Project Gutenberg]
  
[[Category:Ethics]]
+
[[Category:Philosophy and religion]]
[[Category:Philosophical arguments]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy and religon]]
 
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
 
[[Category:Philosophy]]
  
 
{{Credit|66887702}}
 
{{Credit|66887702}}

Revision as of 22:46, 15 September 2006


The naturalistic fallacy is an alleged fallacy of moral reasoning. The British philosopher George Edward Moore [1873-1958] introduces the naturalistic fallacy in his seminal work Principia Ethica (1903). Although the naturalistic fallacy began with Moore, it has been revised over the years in a sub-field of ethics known as “metaethics”, which is the study of the language, metaphysics, and epistemology of ethics.

Moore’s Naturalistic Fallacy

The naturalistic fallacy is the fallacy of attempting to define evaluative concepts with descriptive concepts (Pence 2000, 37). The naturalistic fallacy is related to but is not identical with the “is-ought fallacy”, which is the fallacy of drawing evaluative conclusions from descriptive premises (Hume [1739] 1969).

Hume’s Is-Ought Fallacy

The Scottish philosopher David Hume [1711-1776] discovered the is-ought fallacy and reported it in the volume labeled ‘Of Morals’ in his classic text A Treatise of Hume Nature in 1739. An example of the is-ought fallacy is concluding that gay marriage ought to be illegal in America because there is a consensus among the American people that gay marriage ought to be illegal. The fallacy here should be obvious since an analogous argument could show that interracial marriage should have been illegal in Alabama in 1999 before Alabama voters repealed the Alabama gay marriage banin 2000.

The is-ought fallacy, as Hume would put it, lies in the logical gap between ought-statements and is-statements. Is-statements (also known as “descriptions”) are claims about what there is (e.g. sometimes people lie). Ought-statements (also known as “prescriptions” or “evaluations”) are claims about what should be (e.g. people should always tell the truth). Is-statements are exemplified in the sciences, whereas ought-statements are exemplified in ethics and aesthetics.

At any rate, Hume claims that inferring ought-statements from is-statements is deductively invalid. Thus no amount of descriptive facts force evaluative claims onto us. This means that we can always have evaluative reasons for interpreting descriptive facts in one way versus another. For example, the fact that most Americans disapprove of gay marriage could indicate that most Americans cannot separate their religious beliefs from their political stance. But then the fact that most Americans disapprove of gay marriage does not support a law against gay marriage due to the First Amendment of the U.S. Constitution, which states that among other things, “Congress shall make no law respecting the establishment of religion”.

The Connection Between the Is-Ought Fallacy and the Naturalistic Fallacy

In order to get around Hume’s is-ought fallacy, some eighteenth and nineteenth century moral philosophers simply defined goodness in terms of natural properties, much like scientists define natural things in terms of natural properties (e.g. electricity is moving charge). The utilitarians Jeremy Bentham [1748-1832] and John Stuart Mill [1806-1873] are prime examples of such “naturalistic” philosophers. Actually, in metaethics, a philosopher who believes that moral concepts can be defined with natural concepts is called a "moral naturalist" and a supporter of "moral naturalism".

At any rate, these early utilitarians believed that the moral term ‘good’ can be defined entirely by the phrase ‘whatever produces the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of sentient beings’, although Bentham ([1823] 1907) and Mill ([1861] 2001) disagreed about what sort of pleasure should be emphasized. Problem solved right? Not quite.

G.E. Moore claimed that the mere act of defining moral concepts with natural concepts was a fallacy, the naturalistic fallacy. Moore used the phenomenal quality (sometimes called ‘qualia’) Yellow to make his point; and thus implicitly claimed that moral qualities were analogous to or were a sort of qualia. Moore argued that scientists can attempt to define yellow with a naturalistic description—such as ‘light with approximately 600 nm wavelength’ (McMurry and Fay 1995, 147)—but any such definition would not capture what yellow is. In other words, no definition using natural concepts could capture the essential properties of yellowness. In Moore’s words…

Consider yellow, for example. We may try to define it, by describing its physical equivalent; we may state what kind of light-vibrations must stimulate the normal eye, in order that we may perceive it. But a moment’s reflection is sufficient to shew that those light-vibrations are not themselves what we mean by yellow. They are not what we perceive. Indeed, we should never have been able to discover their existence, unless we had first been struck by the patent difference of quality between the different colours. The most we can be entitled to say of those vibrations is that they are what corresponds in space to the yellow which we actually perceive (Principia Ethica § 10 2).

The same goes for moral concepts according to Moore. Defining the good as what is produces the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of sentient beings in fact fails to capture what is good although it might track it. In Moore’s words…

Yet a mistake of this simple kind has commonly been made about good. It may be true that all things which are good are also something else, just as it is true that all things which are yellow produce a certain kind of vibration in the light. And it is a fact, that Ethics aims at discovering what are those other properties belonging to all things which are good. But far too many philosophers have thought that when they named those other properties they were actually defining good; that these properties, in fact, were simply not other, but absolutely and entirely the same with goodness. This view I propose to call the naturalistic fallacy and of it I shall now endeavour to dispose. (Principia Ethica § 10 3).

Thus Hume’s is-ought fallacy was reborn with Moore’s introduction of the naturalistic fallacy. But how exactly did Moore prove that the naturalistic fallacy was a fallacy?

The Open-Question Argument

Moore convinced his contemporaries that the naturalistic fallacy was a fallacy by an argument called ‘The Open-Question Argument’ and is presented in §13 of Principia Ethica. According to Moore, a term is defined just in case we provide necessary and sufficient conditions for using the term. Moore’s was the traditional view of definition; it was developed by Aristotle [384-322 B.C.E.] as a way to describe the natural essences that things had. As it happens, terms that are defined in this traditional way form closed questions with their definitions.

For example, since ‘bachelor’ is defined as ‘unmarried man’ the following is a closed and thus nonsensical question: I know he is a bachelor but is he unmarried and a man? Moore’s insight was seeing that terms which were not defined by a certain phrase formed open questions, and naturalistic definitions of moral concepts fell within this category.

For example, Moore saw it to be a completely open question to ask: I know she is doing what produces the greatest pleasure for the greatest number of sentient beings, but is she doing something good? Particularly, endorsing American slavery in the eighteenth century would have produced the greatest amount of pleasure for the greatest number of American people (since American whites outnumbered American blacks in the eighteenth century), however it seems far from obvious that endorsing any sort of slavery could ever be good.

For this reason Moore rejected moral naturalism and proposed "moral intuitionism" in its place. This philosophical doctrine claims that moral terms are indefinable and rather we understand moral concepts through moral intuition.

Is the Naturalistic Fallacy Really a Fallacy?

Despite its intuitive appeal, several philosophers have directly or indirectly attacked the naturalistic fallacy. To be sure, the naturalistic fallacy rests on two major and controversial assumptions. First, it assumes that moral concepts must be sharply defined with necessary and sufficient conditions. Second, it assumes that a concept’s meaning lies in its description instead of its reference. However, philosophers have questioned both of these assumptions in the philosophy of language over the course of the twentieth century.

Must Definitions Be Sharp?

Richard Boyd (1988) questions whether moral terms must have sharp definitions in order to be defined. In the end he discovers that moral terms can have what he calls “homeostatic cluster definitions”, which are vaguely defined terms using criteria that are neither necessary or sufficient. In fact, Boyd (1988) argues that cluster definitions are commonplace in human languages. He uses biological species terms (e.g. ‘Homo sapiens’) as an example.

Thus the fact that a moral term and its naturalistic definition do not form a closed question does not imply that defining moral concepts with natural concepts is a fallacy, since moral concepts could be vaguely and imprecisely defined homeostatic cluster concepts. In Boyd’s words:

Similarly, consider the objection that a moral realist must hold that goodness is a natural property, and thus commit the “naturalistic fallacy” of maintaining that moral terms possess analytic definitions in, say, physical terms. The moral realist may choose to agree that goodness is probably a physical property but deny that it has any analytic definition whatsoever (Boyd 1988, 199).

The first philosopher to question whether definitions needed to be sharp was Ludwig Wittgenstein [1889-1951] who in 1951 proposed family resemblance concepts as a vague alternative to sharply-defined concepts in his classic text Philosophical Investigations. Although Wittgenstein ([1951] 2001) suggested that moral concepts were family resemblance concepts, he did not develop a detailed philosophical theory on the issue like Boyd.

Must Definitions Be Descriptions?

Even more important in twentieth-century philosophy of language was the proposal of an alternative theory on the meaning of meaning (or the definition of definition). Since Aristotle, philosophers have thought that the meaning of a word lies in a description of it using other words. For example, a bachelor is an unmarried man. However, Saul Kripke (1972) and Hilary Putnam (1973) offered a different view on the meaning of meaning. They claimed that the meaning of a term (e.g. a name) could be its referent instead of its description. The favorite example for philosophers in this camp is water is H2O.

We need not delve into the reasons for why some philosophers believe in the referential theory of meaning in order to present it as an alternative way to understand meaning. Thus naturalistic philosophers can challenge the naturalistic fallacy in a second way; they can reject the naturalistic fallacy on the grounds that moral terms can be defined referentially instead of descriptively (Boyd 1988).

Hope for the Naturalistic Fallacy

Despite these sophisticated challenges for the naturalistic fallacy achieving the status of a legitimate fallacy in moral reasoning, we can still point out how it highlights fallacious reasoning in some form.

First, someone who believes in the descriptivist theory of meaning and that moral concepts have sharp definitions certainly commits the naturalistic fallacy if she commits the is-ought fallacy. Thus the naturalistic fallacy appears to be a legitimate fallacy for ordinary people who engage in certain ordinary moral reasoning.

The big question is whether experts in moral philosophy (e.g. meta-ethicists) are able to commit the naturalistic fallacy if their theories on language are sophisticated enough. However, the answer to this question is uncertain and is an active area of research in contemporary metaethics.

See also

References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Bentham, Jeremy. Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, [1823] 1907).
  • Boyd, Richard. (1988). “How to Be a Moral Realist,” in Geoffrey Sayre-McCord (ed.), Essays on Moral Realism. (pp. 181-228). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
  • Hume, David. ([1739] 1969). A Treatise of Human Nature, ed. Ernest C. Mossner. Middlesex: Penguin.
  • Kripke, Saul A. (1972). Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
  • McMurray, John, and Fay, Robert C. (1995). Chemistry. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.
  • Mill, John Stuart. ([1861] 2001). Utilitarianism (George Sher, ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett.
  • Moore, George Edward, Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1903).
  • Pence, Gregory. (2000). A Dictionary of Common Philosophical Terms. New York: McGraw-Hill.
  • Putnam, Hilary. (1973). Meaning and Reference. Journal of Philosophy 70(19): 699-711.
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. ([1951] 2001). Philosophical Investigations (G.E.M. Anscombe, ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

External links

General Philosophy Sources

Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.