Difference between revisions of "Aristotelianism" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
Line 2: Line 2:
 
{{main|Aristotle}}
 
{{main|Aristotle}}
 
[[Image:Francesco Hayez 001.jpg|thumb|right|Aristotle, by Francesco Hayez]]
 
[[Image:Francesco Hayez 001.jpg|thumb|right|Aristotle, by Francesco Hayez]]
'''Aristotelianism''' is a [[Tradition#Philosophical tradition|tradition]] of [[philosophy]] that takes its defining inspiration from the work of [[Aristotle]]. Sometimes contrasted by critics with the [[rationalism]] and [[Platonic idealism|idealism]] of [[Plato]], Aristotelianism is understood by its proponents as critically developing Plato’s theories.<ref>For contrasting examples of this, see Hans-Georg Gadamer, ''The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy'' (trans. P. Christopher Smith), Yale University Press, 1986, and Lloyd P. Gerson, ''Aristotle and Other Platonists'', Cornell University Press, 2005.</ref> Most particularly, Aristotelianism brings Plato’s ideals down to Earth as [[Objective (goal)|goals]] and [[goods]] internal to natural species that are realized in activity. This is the characteristically Aristotelian idea of [[teleology]].
+
'''Aristotelianism''' is a philosophical tradition that takes its defining inspiration from the work of [[Aristotle]]. Since Aristotle's death in 322 B.C.E. there has been an unbroken continuation of schools and individual philosophers who have cultivated the study of his works and adopted and expanded on his doctrines and methods. During the ninth, tenth and eleventh centuries, an Arabic tradition of Aristotelianism was developed by Syrians, Persians, Turks, Jews, and Arabs who wrote and taught in their own countries as well as in Africa and Spain. During the twelfth century, new Latin translations from Greek and from Arabic commentaries introduced Aristotle to the medieval Christian scholastics, and initiated an intellectual revival in Europe. Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas developed a synthesis of Aristotelian ideas with Christian doctrines which became essential to Roman Catholic theology. During the seventeenth century, modern philosophy began to develop largely as a reaction to, or in response to, traditional Aristotelian teachings. Contemporary philosophers, thought they generally reject Aristotelian metaphysics, incorporate Aristotelian concepts in their theories of ethics and politics.
  
Elaborated by ancient commentators upon Aristotle’s work, Aristotelianism began its modern history with its reception by Islamic, Jewish and Christian scholars. The most famous of these scholars are [[Averroes]] and St. [[Thomas Aquinas]]. Aquinas argued that the truth in Aristotle’s philosophy is complemented and completed by the truth revealed in the Christian tradition. The [[Roman Catholic Church]] has reasserted a Thomistic Aristotelianism since the 1870s.
 
  
After retreating under criticism from modern natural philosophers, the idea of teleology was transmitted through [[Christian Wolff (philosopher)|Wolff]] and [[Kant]] to [[Hegel]], who applied it to history as a totality. Although this project was criticized by [[Trendelenburg]] and [[Brentano]] as un-Aristotelian, Hegel’s influence is now often said to be responsible for an important Aristotelian influence upon [[Marx]].<ref>For example, George E. McCarthy (ed.), ''Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth-Century German Social Theory and Classical Antiquity'', Rowman & Littlefield, 1992.</ref> Postmodernists, in contrast, reject Aristotelianism’s claim to reveal important theoretical truths.<ref>For example, Ted Sadler, ''Heidegger and Aristotle: The Question of Being'', Athlone, 1996.</ref> In this, they follow [[Heidegger]]’s critique of Aristotle as the greatest source of the entire tradition of Western philosophy. Recent Aristotelian ethical and ‘practical’ philosophy, such as that of [[Hans-Georg Gadamer|Gadamer]], is often premised upon a rejection of Aristotelianism’s traditional metaphysical or theoretical philosophy. From this viewpoint, the early modern tradition of political [[republicanism]], which views the public sphere or State as constituted by its citizens’ virtuous activity, can appear thoroughly Aristotelian.
+
== Characteristics of Aristotelianism ==
 +
Aristotelianism has made an indelible contribution to the language used to articulate philosophical concepts, experiences and problems.  Some words are still in their original Greek forms, others are derived from Latin equivalents of Aristotle’s words. The use of the terms “subject” and “predicate” in grammar and logic; “form” (information, transform) and “matter” to express the correlative aspects of essential nature and physical being;  “energy” as the active power inherent in a thing; “potential” for latent possibility; “substance” and “essence,” “quantity” and “quality,” “accidental,” “relation,” “cause” (and the many meanings of “because”), “genus” and “species” (general, special), “individual,” and “indivisible” (atomic) are only some of the words which have become established in common use.
 +
Philosophical features of Aristotelianism include a methodology which takes a critical approach to existing or hypothetical doctrines, an emphasis on knowledge that can be acquired by natural means through the senses and the exercise of reason. Aristotelian metaphysics places the individual at the center of the realm of existence.     
 +
In the philosophy of nature, Aristotelianism portrays a perfect and economic organization of the natural world, in which heavenly, geocentric spheres driven by intelligent movers carry the stars, the Sun, the planets, and the Moon, in circular movements, and influence the “sublunary” world. From its beginnings, Aristoteliansm incorporated the concept of gravity, in which light bodies rise away from the center of the earth and  heavy bodies move naturally toward it with a speed related to their weight.
 +
Aristotelian aesthetics hold that poetry and literature are an imitation of what is possible in real life; and that tragedy in drama and literature can achieve purification (katharsis) through artificially constructing a situation which evokes fear and pity. Aristotelian ethics emphasize intellectual activity as the primary path to happiness, followed by the practice of virtue. Virtue is characterized as moderation and conscious self-control. Aristotelian political theory considers the state as a self-sufficient society, necessary to provide the social structure and order in which men can achieve happiness.  
  
The most famous contemporary Aristotelian philosopher is [[Alasdair MacIntyre]]. Especially famous for helping to revive [[virtue ethics]] in his book ''[[After Virtue]]'', MacIntyre revises Aristotelianism with the argument that the highest temporal goods, which are internal to human beings, are actualized through participation in social practices. He opposes Aristotelianism to the managerial institutions of capitalism and its state, and to rival traditions—including the philosophies of [[Hume]] and [[Nietzsche]]—that reject its idea of essentially human goods and virtues and instead legitimate capitalism. Therefore, on MacIntyre’s account, Aristotelianism is not identical with Western philosophy as a whole; rather, it is "the best theory so far."
+
Aristotelian teleology incoporates Plato’s ideals as goals and “goods” internal to natural species, that are realized in activity. Sometimes contrasted by critics with the [[rationalism]] and [[idealism]] of [[Plato]], Aristotelianism is understood by its proponents as a critical development of  Plato’s theories.<ref>For contrasting examples of this, see Hans-Georg Gadamer, ''The Idea of the Good in Platonic-Aristotelian Philosophy'' (trans. P. Christopher Smith), Yale University Press, 1986, and Lloyd P. Gerson, ''Aristotle and Other Platonists'', Cornell University Press, 2005.</ref>
  
==References==
+
== History of Aristotelianism ==
 +
===Influence of the Aristotelian Tradition ===
 +
Since Aristotle's death in 322 B.C.E. there has been an unbroken continuation of schools and individual philosophers who have cultivated the study of his works and adopted and expanded on his doctrines and methods. Aristotle’s ideas, originally developed in Greek,  were taken up by Latin authors, then by Syriac, Arabic, and Hebrew authors, and beginning in the middle Ages, by Italian, French, English, and German writers.
 +
The Greek Aristotelian tradition continued for two thousand years along the eastern Mediterranean Sea, diverging at various times between the fourth and fifth centuries to give rise to or reinforce ther traditions. Latin Aristotelianism originated in Rome in the fourth century, and acquired new life from Greece early in the sixth century.  It was revived in the ninth century and again in the twelfth. In the twelfth century, a new tradition of Aristotelianism emerged from Constantinople, and a third tradition from Arab translators and commentators in Spain. Both of these new traditions dispersed, through the schools of the Roman Catholic Church, to Italy, France, and the British Isles. In the fifteenth century, the Greek tradition once more came to Italy from Constantinople and influenced the Italian Renaissance.
 +
=== Aristotelianism in Islamic Philosophy ===
 +
 
 +
In Arabic philosophical circles, Aristotle was called Aristalus, Aristu, First Teacher, and by sobriquets such as “the wise man.” Hellenistic texts were first introduced into Islamic thoughts during the time of Al-Kindi (c. 801-873 C.E.), who commissioned Arabic translations of the works of the Greek philosophers.  In the tenth century, Al-Farabi discovered a more accurate translation, and incorporated Aristotle’s thought so thoroughly into his own philosophy that he was called the “Second Teacher.”  Ibn Bajjah (Avempace, c. 1095 - 1138/39) introduced the Islamic Aristotelian tradition into Spain, where it was further developed by his disciple, Ibn Tufail (c.1105-1185).  His protégé, Averroes (1126 – 1198) wrote extensive commentaries on Aristotle which had a profound impact on medieval scholasticism in Europe. 
 +
 
 +
The Persian philosopher Avicenna (980 -1032 C.E.) synthesized the theories of Aristotle with the monotheistic tradition of Islam.  His work, ’al Shifa (The Cure) was translated into Latin in twelfth-century Spain, and his metaphysics considerably influenced Albertus Magnus and Thomas Aquinas. 
 +
 
 +
The primary characteristics of Islamic Aristotelianism were an emphasis on the superiority of philosophy, and knowledge gained through reason, over knowledge gained though faith; and the theory of a single, universal Active Intellect, an emanation of God, with which the human soul came into contact at its highest stage of development.  Just as Aristotelianism later encouraged the advancement of scientific investigation in Europe, in the Islamic world it inspired the development of logic and of a system for classifying the natural sciences
 +
 
 +
=== Medieval Aristotelianism ===
 +
From the fall of Rome until 1450, Aristotle’s works, originally written in Greek, were unavailable to most educated Europeans.  Boethius (480 – 525) produced some early translations into Latin but these were largely ignored, and only his translations of the “Categories”and “De interpretatione” were widely studied before the twelfth century.
 +
During the ninth and tenth centuries, an Arabic tradition of Aristotelianism was developed by Syrians, Persians, Turks, Jews, and Arabs who wrote and taught in their own countries as well as in Africa and Spain until the twelfth century. Much of the Arabic and Hebrew works passed into the Latin tradition between 1130 and 1550. During the twelfth century, new Latin translations from Greek and from the Arabic commentaries of Avicenna and Averroes, and the Hebrew works of Maimonides (1125 – 1204), introduced Aristotle to the medieval Christian scholastics, and initiated an intellectual revival.  During the thirteenth century, the Roman Catholic Church began to react to the challenges posed by new developments in philosophy. The teaching of Aristotelian books was condemned at Paris in 1210, 1215 and 1231; and lists of propositions inspired by certain interpretations of Aristotle were condemned at Paris and Oxford in 1270 and 1277.
 +
 
 +
Some Christian theologians attempted to appropriate the teachings of Aristotle and interpret them in a way that was compatible with Christian doctrines. Albertus Magnus paraphrased the entire works of Aristotle, and Thomas Aquinas produced a synthesis of Aristotelianism and Christian doctrines that became essential to Roman Catholic theology. Since the 1870s, the [[Roman Catholic Church]] has reasserted a Thomistic Aristotelianism.
 +
During the fourteenth century, John Duns Scotus and William of Ockham responded by elaborating philosophical and theological teachings which were radically opposed to Aristotelianism.
 +
Soon after the beginning of Latin Aristotelianism in Europe during the twelfth century, Aristotelian teachings were introduced into the Greek schools of Athens and Alexandria by certain Armenians and Syrians. The Armenian tradition was still alive in the nineteenth century in such places as Madras and Venice; and the Syrian tradition, which never completely disappeared, was still active in the fourteenth century. 
 +
=== Aristotelianism and the Renaissance ===
 +
During the Renaissance (ca. 1348 - ca. 1648), more Aristotelian commentaries were produced than at any other time in history. Many of the Renaissance universities used Aristotelian texts in the training of  philosophers, and the corpus aristotelicum was used as a framework for textbooks and encyclopedias, and as a point of departure for many philosophical treatises. The growing number of universities increased the numbers of teachers expounding the works of Aristotle and the students learning from them. The advent of printing heightened the impact of Aristotelianism by making Aristotelian works, and commentaries on them, much more widely available. A change in the role of philosophy in university education, and new advances in scholarship, created a need for new commentaries. Exposure to newly-discovered classical texts from outside the Aristotelian tradition provoked philosophical re-examination and criticism. 
 +
Aristotle’s emphasis on naturally acquired knowledge and on the use of reason to examine and explain phenomena contributed to the growth of the natural sciences. His own observations of the natural world and his classification of beings into categories influenced scientific study. The primacy of the individual in Aristotelian thought contributed to a new appreciation of the value of the individual and of the natural beauty of human beings. The Aristotelian view of a logical and beautifully organized world governed by higher intelligences according to inherent logical principles  had a transforming effect on the Christian worldview.
 +
 
 +
=== Aristotelianism During the Seventeenth Century ===
 +
During the seventeenth century, Aristotelian philosophy took on a new role as the background against which new ideas and systems were developed. Aristotelianism  as taught by the scholastics was considered to be outmoded and conservative, and most of the works written were traditional textbooks. Philosophers such as Descartes and Galileo developed their views in reaction to Aristotelianism as it had been taught for the previous four centuries.  However, many seventeenth century Aristotelian philosophers incorporated contemporary scientific developments in their thought, and the views of commentators such as  Eustachios a Sancto Paulo, Franciscus Toletus, Charles d’Abra de Raconis, Scipion Dupleis and the scholars of the Portuguese Comibra school formed a background for the development of modern philosophy.
 +
 
 +
==Aristotelianism and Modern Philosophy==
 +
 
 +
After retreating under criticism from modern natural philosophers, the idea of teleology was transmitted through [[Christian Wolff]] and [[Kant]] to [[Hegel]], who applied it to history as a totality. Although this project was criticized by Trendelenburg and [[Brentano]] as un-Aristotelian, Hegel is now often said to be responsible for an important Aristotelian influence upon [[Marx]].<ref>For example, George E. McCarthy (ed.), ''Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth-Century German Social Theory and Classical Antiquity'', Rowman & Littlefield, 1992.</ref> Postmodernists, in search of new ways of perceiving truth and understanding reality,  reject the claim that  Aristotelianism reveals important theoretical truths.<ref>For example, Ted Sadler, ''Heidegger and Aristotle: The Question of Being'', Athlone, 1996.</ref> They follow [[Heidegger]]’s critique of Aristotle as the greatest source of the entire tradition of Western philosophy. Recent Aristotelian ethical and ‘practical’ philosophy, such as that of Hans-Georg Gadamer, is often premised upon a rejection of Aristotelianism’s traditional metaphysical or theoretical philosophy, while accepting its theory in other areas. The early modern tradition of political [[republicanism]], which views the public sphere or State as constituted by its citizens’ virtuous activity, appears to be thoroughly Aristotelian.
 +
 
 +
The most famous contemporary Aristotelian philosopher is [[Alasdair MacIntyre]]. Especially famous for helping to revive [[virtue ethics]] in his book ''After Virtue'', MacIntyre revises Aristotelianism with the argument that the highest temporal goods, which are internal to human beings, are actualized through participation in social practices. He places Aristotelian concept of essentially human goods and virtues in opposition to the managerial institutions of capitalism and its state, and to rival traditions, including the philosophies of [[Hume]] and [[Nietzsche]], that legitimate capitalism. MacIntyre claims that Aristotelianism is not identical with Western philosophy as a whole; rather, it is "the best theory so far."
 +
 
 +
==Notes==
  
 
<references/>
 
<references/>
  
==Further reading==
+
==References==
  
*Chappell, Timothy (ed.), ''Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics'', Oxford University Press, 2006.
+
*Chappell, Timothy (ed.), ''Values and Virtues: Aristotelianism in Contemporary Ethics'', Oxford University Press, 2006. ISBN: 0199291454 9780199291458 9780199291458 0199291454
*Ferrarin, Alfredo, ''Hegel and Aristotle'', Cambridge University Press, 2001.
+
*Ferrarin, Alfredo, ''Hegel and Aristotle'', Cambridge University Press, 2001. ISBN: 0511018118 9780511018114 9780511018114 0511018118 0521783143
*[[Anthony Kenny|Kenny, Anthony]], ''Essays on the Aristotelian Tradition'', Oxford University Press, 2001.
+
* Kenny, Anthony, ''Essays on the Aristotelian Tradition'', Oxford University Press, 2001. ISBN: 0198250681 9780198250685 9780198250685 0198250681
*Knight, Kelvin, ''Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre'', Polity Press, 2007.
+
*Knight, Kelvin, ''Aristotelian Philosophy: Ethics and Politics from Aristotle to MacIntyre'', Polity Press, 2007. ISBN: 0745619762 9780745619767 9780745619767 0745619762 0745619770 9780745619774 9780745619774 0745619770
*Lobkowicz, Nicholas, ''Theory and Practice: History of a Concept from Aristotle to Marx'', University of Notre Dame Press, 1967.
+
*Lobkowicz, Nicholas, ''Theory and Practice: History of a Concept from Aristotle to Marx'', University of Notre Dame Press, 1967. ISBN: 0819133353  9780819133359
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory'', University of Notre Dame Press, 1984 / Duckworth, 1985 (2nd edn.).  
+
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory'', University of Notre Dame Press, 1984 / Duckworth, 1985 (2nd edn.). ISBN: 2130478964 9782130478966 *MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''Whose Justice? Which Rationality?'', University of Notre Dame Press / Duckworth, 1988.  
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''Whose Justice? Which Rationality?'', University of Notre Dame Press / Duckworth, 1988.  
+
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition'', University of Notre Dame Press / Duckworth, 1990. ISBN: 0268018715 : 9780268018719
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry: Encyclopaedia, Genealogy, and Tradition'', University of Notre Dame Press / Duckworth, 1990.
 
 
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘The Theses on Feuerbach: A Road Not Taken’, in Kelvin Knight (ed.), ''The MacIntyre Reader'', University of Notre Dame Press / Polity Press, 1998.
 
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘The Theses on Feuerbach: A Road Not Taken’, in Kelvin Knight (ed.), ''The MacIntyre Reader'', University of Notre Dame Press / Polity Press, 1998.
 
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues'', Open Court / Duckworth, 1999.
 
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ''Dependent Rational Animals: Why Human Beings Need the Virtues'', Open Court / Duckworth, 1999.
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘Natural Law as Subversive: The Case of Aquinas’ and ‘Rival Aristotles: 1. Aristotle Against Some Renaissance Aristotelians; 2. Aristotle Against Some Modern Aristotelians’, in MacIntyre, ''Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays'' volume 2, Cambridge University Press, 2006.  
+
*MacIntyre, Alasdair, ‘Natural Law as Subversive: The Case of Aquinas’ and ‘Rival Aristotles: 1. Aristotle Against Some Renaissance Aristotelians; 2. Aristotle Against Some Modern Aristotelians’, in MacIntyre, ''Ethics and Politics: Selected Essays'' volume 2, Cambridge University Press, 2006. ISBN: 0521670624 9780521670623 9780521670623 0521670624 0521854385 9780521854382 9780521854382 0521854385
*Riedel, Manfred (ed.), ''Rehabilitierung der praktischen Philosophie'', Rombach, volume 1, 1972; volume 2, 1974.
+
 
*Ritter, Joachim, ''Metaphysik und Politik: Studien zu Aristoteles und Hegel'', Suhrkamp, 1977.
+
*Riedel, Manfred (ed.), ''Rehabilitierung der praktischen Philosophie'', Rombach, volume 1, 1972; volume 2, 1974. OCLC: 785799   
*Schrenk, Lawrence P. (ed.), ''Aristotle in Late Antiquity'', Catholic University of America Press, 1994.
+
 
*Sharples, R. W. (ed.), ''Whose Aristotle? Whose Aristotelianism?'', Ashgate, 2001.
+
*Ritter, Joachim, ''Metaphysik und Politik: Studien zu Aristoteles und Hegel'', Suhrkamp, 1977. OCLC: 1634915   
*Shute, Richard, ''On the History of the Process by Which the Aristotelian Writings Arrived at Their Present Form'', Arno Press, 1976 (originally 1888).
+
 
*Sorabji, Richard (ed.), ''Aristotle Transformed: The Ancient Commentators and Their Influence'', Duckworth, 1990.
+
*Schrenk, Lawrence P. (ed.), ''Aristotle in Late Antiquity'', Catholic University of America Press, 1994. ISBN: 0813207819 9780813207810 9780813207810 0813207819
*Stocks, John Leofric, ''Aristotelianism'', Harrap, 1925.
+
 
*[[Henry B. Veatch|Veatch, Henry B.]], ''Rational Man: A Modern Interpretation of Aristotelian Ethics'', Indiana University Press, 1962.
+
*Sharples, R. W. (ed.), ''Whose Aristotle? Whose Aristotelianism?'', Ashgate, 2001. ISBN: 0754613623 9780754613626
 +
 
 +
*Shute, Richard, ''On the History of the Process by Which the Aristotelian Writings Arrived at Their Present Form'', Arno Press, 1976 (originally 1888). ISBN: 0405073380 9780405073380
 +
*Sorabji, Richard (ed.), ''Aristotle Transformed: The Ancient Commentators and Their Influence'', Duckworth, 1990. ISBN: 0801424321 9780801424328 OCLC: 20092056   
 +
 
 +
*Stocks, John Leofric, ''Aristotelianism'', Harrap, 1925. OCLC: 173467   
 +
 
 +
*Veatch, Henry B., ''Rational Man: A Modern Interpretation of Aristotelian Ethics'', Indiana University Press, 1962.
 +
 
 +
{{Philosophy navigation}}
  
 
{{Philosophy navigation}}
 
{{Philosophy navigation}}

Revision as of 00:58, 13 March 2007