Difference between revisions of "Anamnesis" - New World Encyclopedia

From New World Encyclopedia
({{Contracted}})
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Contracted}}----
+
{{Contracted}}
'''''Anamnesis''''' ([[Ancient Greek|Greek]]: αναμνησις = ''recollection'', ''reminiscence'') is a term used in [[medicine]], [[philosophy]], [[psychoanalysis]], and [[religion]].
+
The philosophical significance of anamnesis ([[Ancient Greek|Greek]]: αναμνησις ''recollection'', ''reminiscence'') derives from its role in [[Plato]]’s epistemology. Anamnesis, or as it is also known, the theory of recollection, is one of the best known of all Platonic themes. The theory of anamnesis says that there are certain concepts or beliefs in the mind from before birth, which explain aspects of the learning process undergone by normal human beings. So anamnesis is essentially a theory of learning, and may be summed up in a single phrase: learning (mathesis) is anamnesis (recollection).  
  
==Philosophy==
+
The theory of anamnesis is a version of theory of [[innate ideas]]. [[Rationalists]] such as [[Descartes]] and [[Leibniz]] argued that certain concepts and knowledge, which we could not have acquired from sensory experience, are innate to the human mind. Plato’s strategy is similar. The distinguishing feature of Plato’s theory from other theories of innate knowledge is his claim that we have been in possession of this knowledge before birth. Learning is understood in terms of our recollecting knowledge which was once ours before we were born.
In [[philosophy]], [[Plato]] uses the term '''''anamnesis''''' in the [[epistemology|epistemological]] theory that he develops in his [[dialogue]]s ''[[Meno (Plato)|Meno]]'' and ''[[Phaedo (Plato)|Phaedo]]''.
 
  
===''Meno''===
+
==Anamnesis in Plato's Philosophy==
In ''Meno'', Plato's character (and old teacher) [[Socrates]] is challenged by Meno with what has become known as the sophistic paradox, or the paradox of knowledge:
 
  
:Meno:  And how are you going to search for [the nature of virtue] when you don't know at all what it is, Socrates?  Which of all the things you don't know will you set up as target for your search?  And even if you actually come across it, how will you know that it ''is'' that thing which you don't know?<ref>''Meno'' 80d</ref>
+
The word anamnesis is standardly translated as ‘recollection’. Anamnesis is a noun derived from the verb anamimneskein, which means ‘to be reminded’. According to [[Plato]], what we call learning is actually recollection of facts which we possessed before incarnation into human form.
  
In other words, if you don't know what the knowledge looks like, you won't recognise it when you see it, and if you ''do'' know what it looks like, then you don't need to look for it.  Either way, then, there's no point trying to gain knowledge.
+
Plato argues for the theory of recollection in two dialogues –the Meno, and the Phaedo–and mentions it in one other—the Phaedrus. His basic strategy of argument is that human beings know certain things, or possess certain concepts, which could not have been gotten from sense experience. Plato’s explanation is that the human soul knew these things before it was born, so that learning these things is really a matter of remembering them.  
  
Socrates' response is to develop his theory of ''anamnesis''. He suggests that the [[soul]] is immortal, being repeatedly [[incarnation|incarnated]]; knowledge is actually in the soul from eternity (86b), but each time the soul is incarnated its knowledge is forgotten in the shock of birth.  What we think of as learning, then is actually the bringing back of what we'd forgotten. (Once it has been brought back it is true belief, to be turned into genuine knowledge by understanding.)  And thus Socrates (and Plato) sees himself, not as a teacher, but as a [[midwife]], aiding with the birth of knowledge that was already there in the student.
+
It is important to see that anamnesis is not meant to explain all learning. The Greek word translated ‘learning’, manthanein, (from which the English ‘mathematics’ is derived) does not pertain to information acquired through the senses, or knowledge of skills. So, for example, ananmnesis is not meant to explain the acquisition of skills such as being able to play the guitar, or with simple factual information such as the dates of the battle of Marathon. The claim that learning is anamnesis appears to be restricted to a priori knowledge, that is knowledge which does not depend on experience for its justification.
  
The theory is illustrated by Socrates asking a slave boy questions about geometry.  At first the boy gives the wrong answer; when this is pointed out to him, he is puzzled, but by asking questions Socrates is able to help him to reach the true answer.  This is intended to show that, as the boy wasn't told the answer, he could only have reached the truth by recollecting what he had already known but forgotten.
+
===Anamnesis in the Meno===
  
===''Phaedo''===
+
In the Meno, Plato introduces the claim that “seeking and learning are in fact nothing but recollection” [81e] in the context of a paradox, sometimes called the eristic paradox or the paradox of learning. The paradox of learning aims to show that learning is impossible, and inquiry futile, since a person can neither learn what he already knows, nor what he does not know. He cannot inquire about what he already knows, since he already knows it, and if he does not know what he is looking for then he surely will not find it [80e].  
In ''Phaedo'', Plato develops his theory of ''anamnesis'', in part by combining it with his theory of [[Idea#Plato|Form]]s. First, he tells us more about how ''anamnesis'' can be achieved; whereas in ''Meno'' we're given nothing but the method of questioning with which Socrates proceeds, in ''Phaedo'' Plato presents us with a way of living our lives so that we can overcome the misleading nature of the body through ''[[Catharsis|katharsis]]'' (Greek: &kappa;&alpha;&theta;&alpha;&rho;&sigma;&iota;&sigmaf;; &ldquo;cleansing&rdquo; (from guilt or defilement), &ldquo;purification&rdquo;). The body and its senses are the source of error; knowledge can only be regained through the use of our reason, contemplating things with the soul (see 66 b&ndash;d).
+
The paradox of learning poses a threat to Socrates’ philosophical investigations. Socrates’ (as he appears in Plato’s earlier dialogues) style of philosophising involves inquiring into the nature of concepts such as courage, virtue, and wisdom. He customarily interrogates or examines unsuspecting persons on their knowledge of these concepts. The structure of this Socratic interrogation (exelenchein) is roughly as follows: Firstly, Socrates requests his interlocutor to define a notion such as justice. He may ask, as he does in the Republic, What is justice? After his interlocutor has offered a definition of justice (E.g. justice is giving to others what they are owed), Socrates proceeds to show that this definition is inconsistent with other beliefs that the interlocutor holds. At this point, the interlocutor will be at a loss as to how to go on, that is, a state of perplexity (aporia). Many of Plato’s earlier dialogues end at this point, without having reached any conclusive answer as to the nature of the concept under scrutiny.
  
Secondly, he makes clear that genuine knowledge, as opposed to mere true belief, is distinguished by its content.  One can only know eternal truths, for they are the only truths that can have been in the soul from eternity.  Though it can be very useful to have a true belief about, say, the best way to get from London to Oxford, such a belief can't count as knowledge; how could our souls have known for all eternity a fact about places that have existed for less than 2,000 years?
+
The paradox of learning is a threat to Socratic investigation because Socrates seems to assume that there are determinate answers to his ‘What is F?’ questions (e.g., ‘what is justice?’), which can be discovered and known to be discovered. The theory of recollection (in the Meno) is introduced as Socrates' response to the paradox of learning. It is meant to show that Socrates’ investigations of concepts such as justice and knowledge are not futile because there is some possibility of success. The theory of recollection says that philosophical inquiry of the Socratic sort is possible because we already possess the knowledge ‘within ourselves’; and learning is simply a matter of remembering what we already know, but don’t know that we know.
  
==Modern Definition==
+
Socrates demonstrates the claim that learning is recollection by means of a very famous examination of a slave, who is asked to solve a problem in geometry.  The problem is to work out the length of the side of a square double in area to any given square. At first Socrates interrogation proceeds very much along the lines of the failed investigations in the earlier dialogues, with the slave providing wrong answers, and eventually falling into a state of despair (aporia) about how to proceed. However, in contrast with the earlier dialogues, Socrates is now able to guide the slave and help him work out the correct answer. Since Socrates does not actually tell him anything—provide him with information –- but simply helps him to reason out the matter for himself, Socrates claims that the slave has gathered true beliefs from within himself, by himself, and that this process in recollection. The crucial point is this: since the slave has not been told right answer, he must have got the right answer from within his mind. But this is possible, Socrates says, only if he previously knew the answer and is simply remembering it. In this way, anamnesis is introduced as the explanation for the success of the slave boy in acquiring the correct answer. The implication is, of course, that if the slave is able to acquire knowledge in this way, then others who inquire into the nature of concepts such as justice and knowledge may also succeed in remembering the answer. This suggests that Plato thought that philosophical knowledge (or perhaps more specifically, ethical knowledge) is a priori: it not knowledge which is obtained by information coming from the sense, including here the testimony of human authority figures.
  
In most dictionaries, "Anamnesis" is defined as a recalling to mind or reminiscence, though in older editions, it may also be mentioned as a recalling of the spirit.
+
===Anamnesis in the Phaedo===
  
''"a recalling to mind, or reminiscence. Anamnesis is often used as a narrative technique in fiction and poetry as well as in memoirs and autobiographies."''
+
The theory of recollection reappears, and is argued for, in the Phaedo, which is generally agreed to have been written after the Meno. The Phaedo is set on the day of Socrates execution by the state of Athens, and narrates Socrates last conversations with his philosophical companions. Anamnesis is introduced in the context of Socrates argument for the immortality of the soul. However, it is important to note that the argument for recollection is independent of any argument for the pre-existence of the soul. If the theory of recollection is true, then the soul existed previously, but not the converse.  
-britannia.com
 
  
''"Main Entry: an·am·ne·sis''
+
The argument for recollection in the Phaedo begins with a reference to the argument in the Meno. This summary is quite helpful in understanding the process as it occurs then. “People when questioned are able to state the truth about everything for themselves, and unless knowledge and a correct account were present within them, they would be unable to do this”. [73a7]. After this summary, Socrates goes on to provide another argument for the claim that all learning is recollection. This argument is substantially different from that in the Meno. The general strategy of argument in the Phaedo seems to be that human beings have knowledge which they could not have acquired after birth. This entails that the soul existed before birth, and since they have not always possessed this knowledge, it follows that they recover it by anamnesis. What knowledge does Plato think we possess which not have been gotten by experience, and why can’t experience generate knowledge of this sort?
  
''Pronunciation: "a-"nam-'nE-s&s''
+
The argument in the Phaedo is conducted with an example of ‘equality’ but Socrates explicitly generalizes the argument from the ‘equal’ to other concepts such as beauty and goodness. In other words, whatever applies to the ‘equal’ itself in the argument, also applies to terms such as good, beautiful etc.  These concepts are what are usually known as the Forms, ideal entities existing beyond the spatio-temporal world. Anamnesis is offered as an explanation for how we came to possess these concepts because, Socrates says, there never are any ideal instances of equality which map on to our perfect grasp of the concept. We cannot explain our grasp of the notion of ‘equality’ in terms of experience because experience never presents us with any genuine examples of ‘equality’. One apple is never, for example, really the same size as another apple.
  
''Function: noun''
+
===Anamnesis in the Phaedrus===
  
''Inflected Form(s): plural an·am·ne·ses /-"sEz/''
+
The theory of recollection reappears directly only once more in Plato’s work and this is in the Phaedrus. Its introduction here is quite different from its argumentative presentation in both the Meno and the Phaedo, occurring in the context of Plato’s myth of the charioteer, which is an allegorical description of the human soul.
  
''Etymology: New Latin, from Greek anamnEsis, from anamimnEskesthai to remember, from ana- +
+
In the Phaedrus, Plato compares the soul to a winged charioteer driving a team of winged horses. The soul follows a procession of gods headed by Zeus to the edge of heaven, and there it gains a glimpse of true reality and the Forms. All the souls share in this vision although different souls gaze upon the forms to different degrees. At this point, the souls struggle to control the horses which drive their chariots, and they fall to earth where they are incarnated as human beings in human bodies.
mimnEskesthai to remember — more at MIND''
 
  
''1 : a recalling to mind : REMINISCENCE''
+
Plato’s central concern in the Phaedrus is with the nature of love, and the myth of the charioteer is supposed to illumine that topic. Plato portrays the love as a sort of divine madness and anamnesis is introduced to explain this madness of love. Plato says that when a soul incarnated in human form beholds beauty in another he becomes inflamed with love because he comes to recollect the Form of beauty as was seen by his soul in the procession before its incarnation in human form. The Form of beauty is dimly reflected in the particular. The lover’s powerful emotional responses are due to his seeing and beginning to remember the majestic sight of the Form before his incarnation.
  
''2 : a preliminary case history of a medical or psychiatric patient"''
+
===Issues in interpretation===
-webster.com
 
  
==Religion==
+
As with almost every aspect of Plato’s thinking, philosophical discussions of anamnesis have generated a vast scholarly literature. In the present context, a few central points of disagreement will be briefly indicated.
"Anamnesis" is used in some [[church]]es in reference to the [[Eucharist]].  This has its origin in [[Jesus]]' words at the [[Last Supper]], "Do this in memory of me" ([[Greek language|Greek]] "Τουτο ποιειτε εις την εμην ''αναμνησιν''",<ref>[[Gospel of Luke|Luke]] 22:19 [http://www.hti.umich.edu/cgi/r/rsv/rsv-idx?type=citation&book=Luke&chapno=22&startverse=19&endverse=], [[1 Corinthians]] 11:24-25 [http://www.hti.umich.edu/cgi/r/rsv/rsv-idx?type=citation&book=1+Corinthians&chapno=11&startverse=24&endverse=25]</ref> and can refer either to the memorial character of the Eucharist itself<ref>[http://www.friendsofpedro.net/main/CFC/CFCGlossary.html]</ref> or to the part of the service where the [[Passion]], [[Resurrection of Jesus|Resurrection]], and [[Ascension]] of Jesus are remembered.<ref>[http://www.marthomachurch.org.uk/stjames/liturgies.htm]</ref>
 
  
For example, in the [[Divine Liturgy|Divine Liturgy of Saint John Chrysostom]], the anamnesis begins with the words:
+
One main area of disagreement as to whether anamnesis is a relatively commonplace process, in which many engage, or whether it represents a difficult and advanced state of development. Plato’s commentators divide roughly into two camps according to whether they think that recollection is meant to explain advanced philosophical learning only, or whether it is meant to explain advanced philosophical learning and mundane concept formation.
:"Remembering, therefore, this command of the Saviour [i.e., to eat and drink in remembrance of him], and all that came to pass for our sake, the cross, the tomb, the resurrection on the third day, the ascension into heaven, the enthronement at the right hand of the Father, and the second, glorious coming..." <ref>[http://www.ocf.org/OrthodoxPage/liturgy/liturgy.html]</ref>
+
 
This phrase precedes the [[epiklesis]], when the [[priest]] asks [[God]] to send the [[Holy Spirit]] to change the bread and wine into the body and blood of Christ.
+
Most interpreters agree that anamnesis in the Meno is meant to explain the possibility of achieving philosophical knowledge, or more particularly, knowledge of the answers to Socrates’ “What is X?” questions. The trouble arises because the argument for recollection in the Phaedo supports an interpretation of recollection in which it is an explanation for basic concept formation, as for example, when one has come to understand the concept of ‘equality’. A number of important commentators such as Cornford, Ackrill, and Bostock, have read from the Phaedo in this way. If this understanding of the Phaedo were correct, then it would seem that recollection is offered as an explanation for both concept formation, and also more difficult philosophical discoveries into the nature of (e.g.) justice and knowledge (i.e., as it appears in the Meno). (A quick reading of the Phaedrus would also seem to support this view, but see Scott (199x).
 +
 
 +
Not all commentators agree that the Phaedo should be read in this way. These commentators, notably Dominic Scott, think that the knowledge of ‘equality’ mentioned in the argument in the Phaedo refers to advanced philosophical knowledge of the Platonic form of equality and that recollection is offered as an explanation for the philosopher’s knowledge of the Platonic form. Basic concept formation is not, on this view, something which anamnesis is meant to explain.
  
In some [[western Christian]] traditions, on the other hand, the anamnesis comes after the consecration of the bread and the wine.<ref>[http://www.catholicgbg.org/tasteandseeweb/resources/hometab/liturgicalterms.html]</ref>
 
  
''An Episcopal Dictionary of the Church'' says of the anamnesis: "This memorial prayer of remembrance recalls for the worshiping community past events in their tradition of faith that are formative for their identity and self-understanding" and makes particular mention of its place in "the various eucharistic prayers".<ref>[http://www.er-d.org/19625_13716_ENG_HTM.htm]</ref>
 
  
 
==Notes==
 
==Notes==

Revision as of 09:29, 4 August 2006

The philosophical significance of anamnesis (Greek: αναμνησις recollection, reminiscence) derives from its role in Plato’s epistemology. Anamnesis, or as it is also known, the theory of recollection, is one of the best known of all Platonic themes. The theory of anamnesis says that there are certain concepts or beliefs in the mind from before birth, which explain aspects of the learning process undergone by normal human beings. So anamnesis is essentially a theory of learning, and may be summed up in a single phrase: learning (mathesis) is anamnesis (recollection).

The theory of anamnesis is a version of theory of innate ideas. Rationalists such as Descartes and Leibniz argued that certain concepts and knowledge, which we could not have acquired from sensory experience, are innate to the human mind. Plato’s strategy is similar. The distinguishing feature of Plato’s theory from other theories of innate knowledge is his claim that we have been in possession of this knowledge before birth. Learning is understood in terms of our recollecting knowledge which was once ours before we were born.

Anamnesis in Plato's Philosophy

The word anamnesis is standardly translated as ‘recollection’. Anamnesis is a noun derived from the verb anamimneskein, which means ‘to be reminded’. According to Plato, what we call learning is actually recollection of facts which we possessed before incarnation into human form.

Plato argues for the theory of recollection in two dialogues –the Meno, and the Phaedo–and mentions it in one other—the Phaedrus. His basic strategy of argument is that human beings know certain things, or possess certain concepts, which could not have been gotten from sense experience. Plato’s explanation is that the human soul knew these things before it was born, so that learning these things is really a matter of remembering them.

It is important to see that anamnesis is not meant to explain all learning. The Greek word translated ‘learning’, manthanein, (from which the English ‘mathematics’ is derived) does not pertain to information acquired through the senses, or knowledge of skills. So, for example, ananmnesis is not meant to explain the acquisition of skills such as being able to play the guitar, or with simple factual information such as the dates of the battle of Marathon. The claim that learning is anamnesis appears to be restricted to a priori knowledge, that is knowledge which does not depend on experience for its justification.

Anamnesis in the Meno

In the Meno, Plato introduces the claim that “seeking and learning are in fact nothing but recollection” [81e] in the context of a paradox, sometimes called the eristic paradox or the paradox of learning. The paradox of learning aims to show that learning is impossible, and inquiry futile, since a person can neither learn what he already knows, nor what he does not know. He cannot inquire about what he already knows, since he already knows it, and if he does not know what he is looking for then he surely will not find it [80e]. The paradox of learning poses a threat to Socrates’ philosophical investigations. Socrates’ (as he appears in Plato’s earlier dialogues) style of philosophising involves inquiring into the nature of concepts such as courage, virtue, and wisdom. He customarily interrogates or examines unsuspecting persons on their knowledge of these concepts. The structure of this Socratic interrogation (exelenchein) is roughly as follows: Firstly, Socrates requests his interlocutor to define a notion such as justice. He may ask, as he does in the Republic, What is justice? After his interlocutor has offered a definition of justice (E.g. justice is giving to others what they are owed), Socrates proceeds to show that this definition is inconsistent with other beliefs that the interlocutor holds. At this point, the interlocutor will be at a loss as to how to go on, that is, a state of perplexity (aporia). Many of Plato’s earlier dialogues end at this point, without having reached any conclusive answer as to the nature of the concept under scrutiny.

The paradox of learning is a threat to Socratic investigation because Socrates seems to assume that there are determinate answers to his ‘What is F?’ questions (e.g., ‘what is justice?’), which can be discovered and known to be discovered. The theory of recollection (in the Meno) is introduced as Socrates' response to the paradox of learning. It is meant to show that Socrates’ investigations of concepts such as justice and knowledge are not futile because there is some possibility of success. The theory of recollection says that philosophical inquiry of the Socratic sort is possible because we already possess the knowledge ‘within ourselves’; and learning is simply a matter of remembering what we already know, but don’t know that we know.

Socrates demonstrates the claim that learning is recollection by means of a very famous examination of a slave, who is asked to solve a problem in geometry. The problem is to work out the length of the side of a square double in area to any given square. At first Socrates interrogation proceeds very much along the lines of the failed investigations in the earlier dialogues, with the slave providing wrong answers, and eventually falling into a state of despair (aporia) about how to proceed. However, in contrast with the earlier dialogues, Socrates is now able to guide the slave and help him work out the correct answer. Since Socrates does not actually tell him anything—provide him with information –- but simply helps him to reason out the matter for himself, Socrates claims that the slave has gathered true beliefs from within himself, by himself, and that this process in recollection. The crucial point is this: since the slave has not been told right answer, he must have got the right answer from within his mind. But this is possible, Socrates says, only if he previously knew the answer and is simply remembering it. In this way, anamnesis is introduced as the explanation for the success of the slave boy in acquiring the correct answer. The implication is, of course, that if the slave is able to acquire knowledge in this way, then others who inquire into the nature of concepts such as justice and knowledge may also succeed in remembering the answer. This suggests that Plato thought that philosophical knowledge (or perhaps more specifically, ethical knowledge) is a priori: it not knowledge which is obtained by information coming from the sense, including here the testimony of human authority figures.

Anamnesis in the Phaedo

The theory of recollection reappears, and is argued for, in the Phaedo, which is generally agreed to have been written after the Meno. The Phaedo is set on the day of Socrates execution by the state of Athens, and narrates Socrates last conversations with his philosophical companions. Anamnesis is introduced in the context of Socrates argument for the immortality of the soul. However, it is important to note that the argument for recollection is independent of any argument for the pre-existence of the soul. If the theory of recollection is true, then the soul existed previously, but not the converse.

The argument for recollection in the Phaedo begins with a reference to the argument in the Meno. This summary is quite helpful in understanding the process as it occurs then. “People when questioned are able to state the truth about everything for themselves, and unless knowledge and a correct account were present within them, they would be unable to do this”. [73a7]. After this summary, Socrates goes on to provide another argument for the claim that all learning is recollection. This argument is substantially different from that in the Meno. The general strategy of argument in the Phaedo seems to be that human beings have knowledge which they could not have acquired after birth. This entails that the soul existed before birth, and since they have not always possessed this knowledge, it follows that they recover it by anamnesis. What knowledge does Plato think we possess which not have been gotten by experience, and why can’t experience generate knowledge of this sort?

The argument in the Phaedo is conducted with an example of ‘equality’ but Socrates explicitly generalizes the argument from the ‘equal’ to other concepts such as beauty and goodness. In other words, whatever applies to the ‘equal’ itself in the argument, also applies to terms such as good, beautiful etc. These concepts are what are usually known as the Forms, ideal entities existing beyond the spatio-temporal world. Anamnesis is offered as an explanation for how we came to possess these concepts because, Socrates says, there never are any ideal instances of equality which map on to our perfect grasp of the concept. We cannot explain our grasp of the notion of ‘equality’ in terms of experience because experience never presents us with any genuine examples of ‘equality’. One apple is never, for example, really the same size as another apple.

Anamnesis in the Phaedrus

The theory of recollection reappears directly only once more in Plato’s work and this is in the Phaedrus. Its introduction here is quite different from its argumentative presentation in both the Meno and the Phaedo, occurring in the context of Plato’s myth of the charioteer, which is an allegorical description of the human soul.

In the Phaedrus, Plato compares the soul to a winged charioteer driving a team of winged horses. The soul follows a procession of gods headed by Zeus to the edge of heaven, and there it gains a glimpse of true reality and the Forms. All the souls share in this vision although different souls gaze upon the forms to different degrees. At this point, the souls struggle to control the horses which drive their chariots, and they fall to earth where they are incarnated as human beings in human bodies.

Plato’s central concern in the Phaedrus is with the nature of love, and the myth of the charioteer is supposed to illumine that topic. Plato portrays the love as a sort of divine madness and anamnesis is introduced to explain this madness of love. Plato says that when a soul incarnated in human form beholds beauty in another he becomes inflamed with love because he comes to recollect the Form of beauty as was seen by his soul in the procession before its incarnation in human form. The Form of beauty is dimly reflected in the particular. The lover’s powerful emotional responses are due to his seeing and beginning to remember the majestic sight of the Form before his incarnation.

Issues in interpretation

As with almost every aspect of Plato’s thinking, philosophical discussions of anamnesis have generated a vast scholarly literature. In the present context, a few central points of disagreement will be briefly indicated.

One main area of disagreement as to whether anamnesis is a relatively commonplace process, in which many engage, or whether it represents a difficult and advanced state of development. Plato’s commentators divide roughly into two camps according to whether they think that recollection is meant to explain advanced philosophical learning only, or whether it is meant to explain advanced philosophical learning and mundane concept formation.

Most interpreters agree that anamnesis in the Meno is meant to explain the possibility of achieving philosophical knowledge, or more particularly, knowledge of the answers to Socrates’ “What is X?” questions. The trouble arises because the argument for recollection in the Phaedo supports an interpretation of recollection in which it is an explanation for basic concept formation, as for example, when one has come to understand the concept of ‘equality’. A number of important commentators such as Cornford, Ackrill, and Bostock, have read from the Phaedo in this way. If this understanding of the Phaedo were correct, then it would seem that recollection is offered as an explanation for both concept formation, and also more difficult philosophical discoveries into the nature of (e.g.) justice and knowledge (i.e., as it appears in the Meno). (A quick reading of the Phaedrus would also seem to support this view, but see Scott (199x).

Not all commentators agree that the Phaedo should be read in this way. These commentators, notably Dominic Scott, think that the knowledge of ‘equality’ mentioned in the argument in the Phaedo refers to advanced philosophical knowledge of the Platonic form of equality and that recollection is offered as an explanation for the philosopher’s knowledge of the Platonic form. Basic concept formation is not, on this view, something which anamnesis is meant to explain.


Notes


References
ISBN links support NWE through referral fees

  • Plato Phaedo, 1911: edited with introduction and notes by Hohn Burnet (Oxford: Clarendon Press)
  • Jane M. Day 1994 Plato's Meno in Focus (London: Routledge) — contains an introduction and full translation by Day, together with papers on Meno by various philosophers
  • Don S. Armentrout and Robert Boak Slocum [edd], An Episcopal Dictionary of the Church, A User Friendly Reference for Episcopalians (New York, Church Publishing Incorporated)
  • britannica.com
  • webster.com


Credits

New World Encyclopedia writers and editors rewrote and completed the Wikipedia article in accordance with New World Encyclopedia standards. This article abides by terms of the Creative Commons CC-by-sa 3.0 License (CC-by-sa), which may be used and disseminated with proper attribution. Credit is due under the terms of this license that can reference both the New World Encyclopedia contributors and the selfless volunteer contributors of the Wikimedia Foundation. To cite this article click here for a list of acceptable citing formats.The history of earlier contributions by wikipedians is accessible to researchers here:

The history of this article since it was imported to New World Encyclopedia:

Note: Some restrictions may apply to use of individual images which are separately licensed.